The Emergence of a Scientific Culture: Science and the Shaping of Modernity, 1210-1685.
Shank, Michael H.
Stephen Gaukroger. The Emergence of a Scientific Culture: Science
and the Shaping of Modernity, 1210-1685.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006. x + 564 pp. index. illus.
tbls. bibl. [pounds sterling]5. ISBN: 978-0-19-929644-6.
This impressive and wide-ranging book is the first of a quintet
devoted to the question: how in the (Western) world did all cognitive
values come to be associated with scientific ones? In the seventeenth
and eighteenth centuries, les belles lettres were fading as the keys to
ethics and learning, worrying Casaubon and Gibbon; increasingly,
religion, morality, and philosophy were judged by scientific criteria, a
transformation that Gaukroger deems a fait accompli by the late
nineteenth century.
This first volume sets up the problem, emphasizing the period from
the 1210 condemnation of Aristotle at Paris to the eve of Newton's
Principia. The breadth of Gaukroger's vision and his scholarship
give the book a historical credibility that few recent accounts can
match. He understands that Aristotelian natural philosophy became an
important cultural force in Europe from the thirteenth century onward,
but argues that it followed the "boom-bust" pattern of
incipient revolutions in other civilizations. Like the latter, medieval
Europe failed to "consolidate" its scientific culture.
Gaukroger believes that Western science is unique in having broken the
boom-bust pattern. (Caution: exceptionalism is a common pre-bust
belief.) In the seventeenth century, revelation and the new natural
philosophy reinforced one another; the natural philosopher was
transformed into the legitimate arbiter of standards for most forms of
inquiry. This short review allows only glimpses of the book's rich
and complex arguments, which are difficult to summarize adequately, let
alone to critique in a few words.
Gaukroger begins by clearing the decks for his own account,
undermining explanations of the early modern "consolidation of
scientific culture" that rely on the autonomy, neutrality, and
method of science. In his historical reconstruction, thirteenth-century
culture witnessed the large-scale introduction of Aristotelian natural
philosophy alongside revelation. To bridge these forms of knowledge,
Aquinas proposed metaphysics, but this uneasy answer ultimately proved
unsatisfactory--witness the Pomponazzi Affair on the immortality of the
soul. After Aristotelianism exhausted itself and faced competition from
other philosophies in the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries, however, a
curious thing happened. In the seventeenth century, revelation became
allied with various forms of the new natural philosophy, which thus
acquired a new cultural role and a new legitimacy. Gaukroger sees this
superimposition of "the 'two books' [of nature and
revelation] ... into a single volume" (507) as an unprecedented
development in the history of world culture. Since the unity of
knowledge it presupposed was peculiarly the forte of the new (largely
British) natural philosopher, his "persona" as an honest man
capable of inquiring into all disciplines became the locus for the
cultural authority of science in areas far beyond its original scope. In
seeing early modern natural philosophy as systematically more consonant with revelation than its medieval counterpart, Gaukroger stands the old
secularization narrative on its head, with distant echoes of the Merton
thesis.
An argument of this scope relies necessarily on the synthesis of a
vast, sometimes flawed, literature, and also demands the exclusion of
many relevant sources. By way of critique, I point to several early
choices that leave a deep imprint on his account. The privileged
position of thirteenth-century Paris in Gaukroger's opening story
gives his narrative an unduly Aquinocentric, theological, and Gilsonian
cast (the Oxford story is very different). At the same time, his
argument overrates the idiosyncratic Parisian condemnations of Aristotle
and others, especially those of 1277, which allegedly "shaped the
intellectual landscape for the next 350 years" (48). In the end,
for Gaukroger, it is fundamentally a Thomistic framework that the
Scientific Revolution will set aside.
Perhaps for this reason, Gaukroger passes very lightly over the
non-Thomistic fourteenth-century transformations of natural philosophy
into a high-powered logical and measurement-oriented enterprise that
diffused into theology (a point relevant to Gaukroger's grand
thesis). Also, given the importance of mathematization in the rise of
the new natural philosophy, it is curious that he pays so little
attention to either the mathematical sciences themselves (optics,
astronomy) or the mathematizing trends in late medieval natural
philosophy, which contemporaries rightly saw as going beyond Aristotle.
(Problematic for similar reasons is his out-of-date account of
Copernicus, whose predecessors did try to keep the mathematical and the
physical aspects of astronomy together.)
Gaukroger's grand beginning of an even grander five-volume
narrative is an exceptional book. Its structure of scientific authority,
as it were, is certain to stimulate long and lively discussions among
academics of every stripe, from medievalists through historical
sociologists to historians of science, religion, and the world's
civilizations.
MICHAEL H. SHANK
University of Wisconsin-Madison