Cognitive ecology as a framework for Shakespearean studies.
Tribble, Evelyn ; Sutton, John
"COGNITIVE ECOLOGY" is a fruitful model for Shakespearean
studies, early modern literary and cultural history, and theatrical
history more widely. Cognitive ecologies are the multidimensional
contexts in which we remember, feel, think, sense, communicate, imagine,
and act, often collaboratively, on the fly, and in rich ongoing
interaction with our environments. Along with the anthropologist Edwin
Hutchins, (1) we use the term "cognitive ecology" to integrate
a number of recent approaches to cultural cognition: we believe these
approaches offer productive lines of engagement with early modern
literary and historical studies. (2)
The framework arises out of our work in extended mind and
distributed cognition. (3) The extended mind hypothesis arose from a
post-connectionist philosophy of cognitive science. This approach was
articulated in Andy Clark's Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and
World Together Again, and further developed by Susan Hurley and Mark
Rowlands, among others. (4) The distributed cognition approach arose
independently, from work in cognitive anthropology, HCI (Human-Computer
Interaction), the sociology of education and work, and science studies.
The principles of distributed cognition were articulated in
Hutchins's ethnography of navigation, Cognition in the Wild, (5)
and developed by theorists such as David Kirsh and Lucy Suchman. (6)
These models share an anti-individualist approach to cognition. In
all these views, mental activities spread or smear across the boundaries
of skull and skin to include parts of the social and material world. In
remembering, decision making, and acting, whether individually or in
small groups, our complex and structured activities involve many
distinctive dimensions: neural, affective, kinesthetic, sensory,
interpersonal, historical, political, cultural, technological; indeed,
each dimension in this necessarily partial list is itself wildly
heterogeneous. Many cognitive states and processes are hybrids, unevenly
distributed across the physical, social, and cultural environments as
well as bodies and brains, hooking up in both temporary and more
enduring ways with other people and with certain things--artifacts,
media, technologies, or institutions--each with its own history and
tendencies. In other words, this is a system-level mode of analysis.
System here is not to be seen at the relatively abstract level of Michel
Foucault's opisteme or even Pierre Bourdieu's habitus, but
instead as dynamic, material, and non-localizable. In this view system
"cannot be understood in its development or function as strictly
localized within one level of analysis." (7) In a dynamic model of
system, no one element can be identified as the unit of analysis.
Rather, thought is distributed across insides (internal mechanisms
constraining attention, perception, and memory); objects (artifacts and
environments); and people (social systems). Because our practices of
remembering or decision-making in cultural settings always involve the
coordination of many disparate resources at once, we cannot assign any
general analytic priority to one of these dimensions. (8) The
integrative label "cognitive ecology" particularly highlights
the point that disparate but tightly interconnected elements within any
such culturally specific setting operate in a complementary balance that
shifts over time.
Although firmly grounded in contemporary sciences of mind,
cognitive ecology thus has little in common with the rigid rationalist
logicism of classical forms of cognitivism. Thinking is not the product
of stable and determinate internal structures. Communication and action
are not the mere expressions of the real cognitive processes in the
head, but are thinking or remembering in action. A raft of loosely
allied movements in the situated, embodied, and distributed cognitive
sciences reject the individualist "classical sandwich," by
which "mind" stolidly mediates between input and output,
perception and action, instead studying more-or-less intelligent
practices in their cultural-historical settings. (9) As Hutchins
describes it, the rule-governed top-down models of classical Artificial
Intelligence have given way to increasing recognition of the
inseparability of mind, body, and culture: rather than a brainbound
model of cognition that reduces thought to "internal symbolic
events," the proper unit of analysis is the
"cultural/cognitive ecosystem" ("Cognitive Ecology,"
707, 712).
For many philosophers of mind and cognitive scientists, the
troubling claim in this integrative vision is that the boundaries of
skull and skin do not encompass the mind. Although this is a materialist
theory, mind is not identical to brain, for the naked brain alone-the
naked human brain in particular--is not the sole basis of our
psychological capacities. Human brains are adapted to latch on to,
create, manipulate, incorporate, and assimilate external
resources--tools, languages and notations, notebooks and neighbors--that
have themselves become apt for incorporation. The individual is
essentially incomplete, in being deeply sculpted and continually
transformed by plugging in to wider socio-technical networks. (10) The
idea is not that the isolated, unsullied individual first provides us
with the gold standard for a cognitive agent, and that mind is then
projected outward into the ecological system: but that from the start
(historically and developmentally) remembering, attending, intending,
and acting are distributed, co-constructed, system-level activities.
But for literary theorists and cultural historians, we suspect that
the awkward terms are "mind" and "cognition," both
so historically labile and genealogically suspect, both so often
redolent of reifying assumptions. (11) Many see "cognition" as
excluding affect, and as wrapped up in managerial dreams and rationalist
follies. (12) So we could just talk about remembering, feeling,
reasoning, perceiving, dreaming, hearing, planning, walking, singing,
communicating, and so on, given that one key departure here from
universalizing individualism is that we reject the ideal of abstracting
away to some single feature common to all these disparate activities.
But we join Hutchins and Clark in polemically reclaiming the term.
"Cognition" need not have the rationalist and individualist
connotations: it does not exclude emotion, or even focus on
"thinking" alone. Rather, "the idea is that high-level
cognition is produced by the culturally-orchestrated application of
low-level cognitive processes to cultural materials." (13) We
retain the language of remembering, thinking, and decision-making
because social and cultural histories need to acknowledge the
extraordinary complexity of the collaborative intelligent agency and
expertise of their actors. "Mind" is skilful activity rather
than a stock of knowledge: the analysis of mind must therefore be
fundamentally historical in character, because changing cultural
artifacts, norms, and institutions are not external but partly
constitute it. (14)
There are many potential examples of the relevance of cognitive
ecological models to early modern literary and cultural history. In this
brief overview, we develop two: early modern theatrical history and
recent historical interest in "things." Cognitive ecology
facilitates a system-level analysis of theater: this model of cognitive
ecology would posit that a complex human activity such as theater must
be understood across the entire system, which includes such elements as
neural and psychological mechanisms underpinning the task dynamics; the
bodily and gestural norms and capacities of the trained actors; the
physical environment(s), including the relationships between playing and
audience space; cognitive artifacts such as parts, plots, and playbooks;
technologies such as sound or lighting; the social systems underpinning
the company, including the mechanisms for "enskillment"; the
economic models by which the company runs; the wider social and
political contexts, including censorship, patronage, and commercial
considerations; and the relative emphasis placed upon various elements
of the enterprise, including writerly or directorial control, clowning,
visuality, and improvisation. No one of these elements is primary, but
instead each affects and modulates the others. (15)
For an example of how such a model might work, we can consider the
cognitive ecology of attention in the theater. Any performance has
designs on mechanisms of attention and perception, but these are not
simply biological phenomena, but are fundamentally also properties of
social and material systems. Vision is a skilled practice; as Christina
Grasseni suggests in her work on the development of "skilled
vision" for identifying good breeding stock among Tuscan cattle:
"Vision, like the other senses, needs educating and training in a
relationship of apprenticeship and within an ecology of practice."
(16) While attention and perception are cognitive mechanisms, they are
also fundamentally cultural in nature, shaped by rich social knowledge
of particular cultural fields. Early modern audiences possessed a rich
intuitive understanding of social conventions and hierarchy that would
have been integrated into the economy of attention on the early modern
stage. Yet attention is also technologically mediated.
Shakespeare's players had the resources of sound, including voice,
sound effects, and music. These were used extensively in commanding
attention; offstage sounds such as flourishes, alarums, and knocks
directed audience and actors' attention, and high intensity sounds
often began the plays. (17) The vocal and gestural expertise of the
players was essential in manipulating and managing attention and
perception. In "The Character of an Excellent Actor," possibly
written by John Webster, the actor is described as engaging the audience
through his physical and kinetic prowess: "by a full and
significant action of body, he charmes our attention." (18)
In contrast, contemporary theaters rely heavily upon the technology
of lighting to literally throw focus on particular stage areas and to
attract the audience's eyes. In this environment, the work of
attention is given over almost entirely to the lighting technician. This
change in the cognitive ecology of the theater has a far-reaching
effect. Lighting is a powerful technology for managing attention and
manipulating mood and affect. Yet it is also a demanding taskmaster and
profoundly alters relationships among actors, audience, and
behind-the-scenes theatrical workers. Lighting requires that blocking be
planned in advance; the on-the-fly conventions of movement across the
stage that governed Shakespeare's actors cannot be employed once
movement must be coordinated with lighting technology. The use of
lighting requires technical rehearsal and centralized planning of the
sort associated with concept-oriented directing. The coordination of the
actors with this particular technological system becomes of overriding
importance.
This is only one of many examples of interplay of internal
cognitive mechanisms and social and material environment. Cognitive
ecologies are always dynamic--as one element changes, others may take up
the slack, so to speak. A model of cognitive ecology would predict that
some systems will place more or less weight on internal mechanisms, on
central control, or on particular forms of cognitive artifacts and
social systems; as one element changes, the others shift as well. For
this reason, a model of cognitive ecology can help to shape and theorize
much recent innovative work in theatrical history. An ecological model
is highly compatible with the emphasis on company-centered and
repertory-based theatrical histories such as The Children of the
Queen's Revels and The Queen's Men and their Plays. (19) As
Sally-Beth McLean and Scott McMillin argue, the Queen's Men relied
upon an improvisational, open style that invited clowning and audience
participation, to some extent at the expense of writerly control. In
contrast, the children's companies prior to 1600, with their
limited repertory and relatively long rehearsal times (in contrast to
the adult male companies), used a schooling model in which explicit
direct instruction was apparently common.
Moreover, the recent work on the apprenticeship system in the adult
companies by David Kathman could be shaped through an ecological model
focused on the "enskillment" processes used to train the boy
actors. (20) Other contemporary anthropological research on the
induction of novice practitioners into a skilled workplace setting has
confirmed the importance of the social and environmental surround.
Grasseni argues that perception is not an inert mechanism, but instead
must be trained through a process of "education of attention"
(43). In such a system "specific sensibilities and capacities ...
are engendered through the active socialisation of apprentices into
structured and shared contexts of practice" (46-47). This framework
demands that we examine the "process of enskillment in a
culturally, socially, and materially structured environment" (43).
Kirsh's argument that distributed cognition is the study of the
"variety and subtlety of coordination" has profound
implications for the way we understand skill--as Downey writes,
"learning a skill is the development within the novice of an
ability to coordinate the body with the environment." (21) Skill is
profoundly social. Even when practiced in isolation, skill is
undergirded by a myriad of social practices, technologies, and tools and
emerges within rich social, material, and somatic environments.
Similarly, objects and artifacts must be seen as integral to a
model of cognitive ecology. Bodies, spaces, artifacts, and environments
are all coordinated in a cognitive ecological model, and agents both
shape and are in turned shaped by their manipulation of objects. As
Grasseni writes, "any mental process is artefact-mediated, and any
thought is cultural. Cognitive artefacts are then the key vehicles
through which culture becomes part of the environmental system"
(47). Here the work of Tiffany Stern, Simon Palfrey, and Paul Menzer on
the importance of the cognitive artifact of the cue-script is also
amenable to analysis through an ecological framework. (22) Palfrey and
Stern argue for the profound shaping of early modern theatrical practice
by the actors' parts. Parceled out to individual players, these
parts formed the basis of the private study that was the primary mode of
preparation for performance. Since these parts contained only the
player's own lines and his cues, they afforded careful attention to
the changing passions of the role. "Affordance" is a term
coined by J. J. Gibson. An "affordance" is that feature of an
object or an environment that invites a certain mode of use and
discourages others, as a chair "affords" sitting. While a
chair can be used to stand upon, using it in this way goes against the
grain of the design; one can sit on a ladder, but not very comfortably.
(23) The affordance of the cue-script is access to the unfolding sense
of the "passions" of each character--information that is
actually quite difficult to glean amid the myriad of other distractions
in a playbook. In contrast, a playbook obscures the salient material for
an actor--his own lines--with the result that most contemporary actors
use the technology of highlighting to draw attention to them. As
important as the cue-script is, however, it is only one element in the
wider ecology and should not be seen as the master locus of control.
While the cue-script affords some activities and constrains others,
these actions must be seen within the wider context of human skill and
activity in which they are situated. Players aimed at "artful
accomplishment" of the smoothest possible performance. (24) This
model implies coordination, planning, and error correction, through an
ongoing mutual modulation of the unfolding time-pressured event. Such
modulation could be achieved even in performance through gestures
(subtly or otherwise signaling the interlocutor to await the full cue,
for example). Despite the individual study of the part, and despite the
dispersal of the play into these atomistic units, theater is a group
exercise and involved group expertise. (25) The social dynamic of
rehearsal and performance would include attention to mistakes and
self-correction, of the sort no doubt facilitated by the use of the
repeated cue, through the entire array of embedded experience and tacit
knowledge that underpins successful group coordination. (26)
This example confirms the particular ways in which embodied
individuals, skilful groups, and parts of the physical and technological
environment are interanimated in distinctive historical settings.
Cognitive ecology can thus also enrich recent work on things and in
historical phenomenology. For Jonathan Gil Harris, for example, both
objects and sensations are time travellers, saturated with the imprints
of many other times. (27) So matter is untimely, out of time with
itself, in that the sedimented past resists absorption and will not be
superseded. It's not that the past haunts the present in some
spectral way, but that it actively works in and through present objects.
Anachronism is thus a feature of things, not of certain theories,
because multiple traces--many apparently obsolete--are always
pluralizing and problematizing settled chronologies. With objects
riddled by traces, coordinating or competing, polytemporality may be
intrinsic to matter: but this does not dictate any particular
temporality as inherent in a thing. Its temporality is rather generated
by what happens, by what we do with it and how it responds, by reworking
and reading and reactivating. Harris reads "the sulphurous odor of
Macbeth's fireworks," for example, as generating
"polychronic experiences" of "a compression of different
times," conjuring in deadly conjunction both "the spectre of
the Gunpowder Plot" and the older olfactory coordinates of Catholic
ritual (119, 139). Matter is always in process, implying and inviting
the dynamic formation of new hybrid assemblages in which bodies and
objects distribute agency across a "symbiotic system comprising
supposedly disparate elements that act in concert" (144).
To the views in poststructuralism and science studies with which
Harris aligns this account, we can now add the integrative framework
offered by cognitive ecology. As we have sketched it, the distributed
elements in any richly interconnected cognitive assemblage are all
changing at different rates as they interact in changing assemblages.
The traces and potentialities left by these interactions are not erased
as the system moves into new states, or as some of its elements migrate.
This cognitive ecological approach thus stands to enrich a range of
questions currently engaging early modern studies, including theatrical
history, historical phenomenology, object studies, and body studies.
Moreover, such an approach helps to build theoretically and historically
informed accounts of skill, within a genuinely embodied and extended
model of cognition.
Notes
(1.) Edwin Hutchins, "Cognitive Ecology," Topics in
Cognitive Science 2 (2010): 705-15.
(2.) The term cognitive ecology itself was borrowed by the
biological sciences from cognitive science as a means of integrating
behavioral ecology "with an understanding of the underlying
psychological and neural mechanisms," Sue Healy and Victoria
Braithwaite, "Cognitive Ecology: a field of substance?" Trends
in Ecology and Evolution 15 (2000): 22-26, esp. 22; see also Reuven
Dukas and John M. Ratcliffe, eds., Cognitive EcologylI (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 2009) and Janet Dixon Keller, "Human
Cognitive Ecology: an Instructive Framework for Comparative
Primatology," American Journal of Primatology 62 (2003): 229-41.
(3.) See Evelyn Tribble, Cognition in the Globe: Attention and
Memory in Shakespeare's Theatre (New York: Palgrave MacMillan,
2011); John Sutton, "Exograms and Interdisciplinarity: History, the
Extended Mind, and the Civilizing Process," in R. Menary, ed., The
Extended Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2010), 189-225.
(4.) See Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and World Together Again
(Cam bridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997); Susan Hurley, Consciousness in Action
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998); Mark Rowlands, The
Bodyin Mind: Understanding Cognitive Processes (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1999), and The New Science of the Mind: From Extended
Mind to Embodied Phenomenology (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2010).
(5.) Edwin Hutchins, Cognition in the Wild (Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press, 1995); see also Bruno Latour, "Cogito ergo sumus! Or,
psychology swept inside out by the fresh air of the upper deck: review
of Hutchins 1995," Mind, Culture, and Activity 3 (1996): 54-63.
(6.) David Kirsh, "The Intelligent Use of Space,"
Artificial Intelligence 72.1-2 (1995): 31-68; David Kirsh, "Problem
solving and situated cognition," The Cambridge Handbook of Situated
Cognition, ed. P. Robbins et al. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2009), 264-306; Lucy Suchman, Human-machine Reconfigurations: Plans and
Situated Actions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007).
(7.) William Clancey, "Scientific Antecedents of Situated
Cognition," Cambridge Handbook of Situated Cognition, 11-34, esp.
17.
(8.) David Kirsh, "Distributed Cognition: A Methodological
Note," Pragmatics and Cognition 14 (2006): 249-62. See also Steven
D. Brown, "The Quotation Marks have a Certain Importance: Prospects
for a 'Memory Studies,' " Memory Studies 1.3 (2008):
261-71.
(9.) The term "classical sandwich" originates with Susan
Hurley, Consciousness in Action (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, 1998). See also John Haugeland, "Mind Embodied and
Embedded," in Having Thought: Essays in the Metaphysics of Mind,
ed. John Haugeland (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998),
207-37; Margaret Boden, Mind as Machine: A History of Cognitive Science,
2 vols. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006); Andy Clark, Supersizing
the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2008).
(10.) See Clark, Supersizing the Mind; Sutton, "Exograms and
Interdisciplinarity."
(11.) See Anna Wierzbicka, Semantics, Culture, and Cognition:
Universal Human Concepts in Culture-Specific Configurations (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1992); Paul S. MacDonald, History of the
Concept of Mind: Speculations about Soul, Mind and Spirit from Homer to
Hume (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2003).
(12.) For a discussion of "cognitivism" as roughly
equating "managerialism," see Slavoj Zizek, "Cultural
Studies versus the 'Third Culture,'" The South Atlantic
Quarterly 101.1 (2002): 19-32.
(13.) Edwin Hutchins, "Enaction, Imagination, and
Insight," Enaction: Towards a New Paradigm in Cognitive Science,
ed. J. Stewart, O. Gappene, and E. di Paolo (Cambridge MA: MIT Press,
2011), forthcoming,
(14.) John Sutton, "Spongy Brains and Material Memories,"
in Environment and Embodiment in Early Modern England, ed. Mary
Floyd-Wilson and Garrett Sullivan (Basingstoke: Palgrave, 2007), 14-34.
(15.) For a fuller account of distributed cognition and theatrical
history, see Evelyn Tribble, Cognition in the Globe: Attention and
Memory in Shakespeare's Theatre (New York: Palgrave, 2011).
(16.) Christina Grasseni, "Skilled Vision: An Apprenticeship
in Breeding Aesthetics," Social Anthropology 12 (2004): 41-55, esp.
41.
(17.) Bruce Smith, The Acoustic World of Early Modern England:
Attending to the O-Factor (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1999).
(18.) [John Webster?], "The Character of An Excellent
Actor," in Actors on Acting, ed. E. T. Cole and H. K. Chinoy (New
York: Crown, 1949), 89.
(19.) Lucy Munro, Children of the Queen's Revels: A Jacobean
Theatre Repertory, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005); Scott
McMillin and Sally-Beth MacLean, The Queen's Men and their Plays
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998); see also Roslyn L.
Knutson, Playing Companies and Commerce in Shakespeare's Time
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001).
(20.) David Kathman's recent work on apprenticeship includes
"Players, Livery Companies, and Apprentices," in Oxford
Handbook on Theatre History, ed. Richard Dutton (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2009), 413-28; "How Old Were Shakespeare's
Boy Actors?," Shakespeare Survey 58 (2005): 220-46; "Grocers,
Goldsmiths, and Drapers: Freemen and Apprentices in the Elizabethan
Theater," Shakespeare Quarterly 55.1 (2004): 1-49.
(21.) G. Downey, "Scaffolding Imitation in Capoeira: Physical
Education and Enculturation in an Afro-Brazilian Art," American
Anthropologist 110 (2008): 204-13, esp. 211.
(22.) Tiffany Stern, Rehearsal from Shakespeare to Sheridan
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000); Simon Palfrey and Tiffany
Stern, Shakespeare in Parts (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000);
Paul Menzer, The Hamlets: Cues, Qs, and Remembered Texts (Newark:
University of Delaware Press, 2008).
(23.) J. J. Gibson, The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception
(Boston, Houghton Mifflin, 1979), 127-36; Bruce McConachie discusses the
usefulness of Gibson's term in relationship to spectatorship and
attention in Engaging Audiences: A Cognitive Approach to Spectating in
the Theatre (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2008), 74.
(24.) Lucy Suchman, "Centers of Coordination: A Case and Some
Themes," Discourse, Tools, and Reasoning: Essays on Situated
Cognition, ed. L. B. Resnick (Berlin: Springer, 1997): 41-62, esp. 50.
(25.) See R. Keith Sawyer, "Improvisational Cultures:
Collaborative Emergence and Creativity in Improvisation" Mind,
Culture and Activity. 7. 3 (2000): 180-85.
(26.) Menzer, Cues, Qs, discusses error correction and social
coordination in his discussion of the cue-scripts for Hamlet.
(27.) Jonathan Gil Harris, Untimely Matter in the Time of
Shakespeare (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2009).