Imagination in history.
Sacks, David Harris
Practicing New Historicism By Catherine Gallagher and Stephen
Greenblatt Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press, 2000
Hamlet in Purgatory By Stephen Greenblatt Princeton and Oxford:
Princeton University Press, 2001
"History," the word, is Greek in origin; it derives from
historia, a term whose primary meaning is "inquiry." At its
root, it names an intellectual process, not its subject matter or its
final result. But it can also mean the knowledge obtained through
investigation or study, an account of one's inquiries, or a
narrative of events, past or present. Arguably the title of
Herodotus's famous book, The Histories, conveys all these meanings.
In Latin, historia refers more narrowly to narratives of events or to
fictional tales and stories; the same goes for histoiro in medieval
French, In modern English, however, the word "history" names
two related but distinct concepts: it can be a narrative or study of the
past, or it can be the past that is narrated or studied. We "do
history" when we research and write about previous times and
places; we "make history" when we cause events or participate
in process which later may become a subject of historical investigation
or story telling.
Nevertheless in the history of the English language,
"history" understood as a written narrative represents the
earlier usage. In a manner of speaking, therefore, history as written
precedes history as lived. Whether the same holds in logical,
ontological, or causal terms--i.e., whether a priori models of time and
of human interactions within it define, construct, direct, or shape our
experience or knowledge of historical events and processes--has been one
of the central issues among humanists and historians for the last two
decades. Perhaps no group of scholars has done more than the
practitioners of New Historicism to make apparent the important role
played by literary and institutional convention and by intellectual and
ideological presupposition in conditioning our understandings of the
past, our reactions to the present, and our aspirations for the future.
New Historicism came into prominence as an interdisciplinary
movement in literary studies, history, and related subjects around the
year 1980. The term itself was first introduced in 1982 to distinguish
its form of text-based historicism not only from traditional literary
history, but also from American New Criticism.(1) Assuredly it has
already proven itself as a movement, not just in offering insights into
a host of specific topics from the self-fashioning of artists and
courtiers to the making of the modern body, (2) but also in conveying
the utility of construing "cultures as texts" and of thinking
of literature and the other creative arts as a "key to particular
historically embedded social and psychological formations"
(Gallagher and Greenblatt, 7, 9). There is also no doubt that the
diverse ways of working of the founding generation of New Historicists
have been widely emulated or adapted by colleagues and students in a
variety of different fields and disciplines. Almost from the outset,
there have been numerous attempts to summarize its accomplishment and
criticize its methods; I won't endeavor to cite the huge corpus of
commentaries and critiques that have appeared, let alone list all the
works of scholars who identify themselves in one way or another as New
Historicists. (3) I propose instead to look closely at the two books
before us to see where the movement now stands.
I
Practice
According to Catherine Gallagher and Stephen Greenblatt, two of New
Historicism's earliest and most important proponents, their
movement is not a theory or even a school, but an evolving set of
practices applied to particular problems and performed by a loose and
changing coalition of practitioners with different purposes and
projects. Practicing New Historicism is their attempt to explain the
character of this interdisciplinary movement, to offer an account of its
intellectual affiliations and major concerns, and to reveal by their
practical example some of its paradigmatic methods and moves.
What then is a "practice"? It does not seem to be the
sort of activity contemplated in the old joke: A stranger to New York
City stops a man on the street who is carrying a violin case and asks
"How do I get to Carnegie Hall?" Fritz Kreisler answers:
"Practice! Practice!" For Kreisler--for the exemplar of violin
virtuosity that he represents--it is possible not just to repeat the
same sequence of actions over and over but in doing so to get closer and
closer to perfection. There is an external standard of excellence,
applicable by neutral observers, and practice makes perfect! New
Historicism, as explained by Gallagher and Greenblatt, eschews any such
idea. One can do it well or badly, but not asymptotically approach the
thing in itself. Nor is New Historicism's notion of a practice the
precise equivalent of what Aristotle meant by praxis. For Aristotelians
there is an external standard toward which action is directed--namely
eudaimonia, human flourishing. Accordingly, praxis involves the exercise
of practical wisdom, or phronesis, by an individual who, guided by the
moral disposition to act rightly, applies theory to circumstances. Karl
Marx, perhaps the greatest of modern Aristotelians, also had a
teleological conception of praxis. In his case, it entails the
translation of theory into revolutionary action aimed to overthrow
bourgeois capitalism and establish communism.
While New Historicism's idea of a practice borrows heavily
from this Marxist philosophical tradition of critical-practical
activity--nowhere more so than in seeking to undermine established
structures of thought and power--New Historicists in general, and
Gallagher and Greenblatt in particular, lack the confidence of
traditional Marxists that they know the driving force of history or its
final end. They are not engaged in actions intended to promote a
specific social movement or political cause. In this they would perhaps
agree with Marc Bloch: "No one today," he ventured,
"would dare to say, with the orthodox positivists, that the value
of a line of research is to be measured by its ability to promote
action." But like Bloch, they no doubt would also allow that
"mere amusement ... is no longer permitted us in our day, even ...
when it is the amusement of the intelligence." Writing in 1941,
after the fall of France, Bloch said, that
in this poor world of ours which ... has created so little happiness
for itself, the tedious minutiae of historical erudition, easily
capable of consuming a whole lifetime, would deserve condemnation
as an absurd waste of energy, bordering on the criminal, were they
to end merely by coating one of our diversions with a thin veneer
of truth. Either all minds capable of better employment must be
disuaded from the practice of history, or must prove its legitimacy
as a form of knowledge. (4)
For Bloch what the study of history offers is understanding and
explanation of historical events and developments, not merely the
enumeration of factual knowledge. Nevertheless, living in Vichy France and under the menace of Nazism, he concluded that "[a] science will
always seem to us somehow incomplete if it cannot, sooner or later, in
one way or another, aid us to live better." (5)
The New Historicist program conforms in large measure to this
paradigm, as Gallagher and Greenblatt implicitly acknowledge. To use
Bloch's formulation, they aim to escape "from mere
narrative," to reject the "modern poisons of routine learning
and empiricism parading as common sense," and "to penetrate
beneath the mere surface of actions." (6) However, in thus seeking
"understanding," New Historicists have been more concerned
than Bloch and others in the founding generation of the Annales school,
to reveal, and sometimes to unmask, the structures of power they see
being served by the particular narratives and ideological constructions
they examine. They use their work to challenge the master narratives in
whose thrall we sometimes have been and can still remain entrapped. In
this respect, their writing has a distinct ethical dimension even more
explicit than the one Bloch discussed. Nevertheless, they are too aware
of the role of accident in human history, too knowledgeable of ways in
which cultural forms and habits resist reduction to any one formula, and
too devoted to the unpredictable play of the imagination in human
activity to be able to offer their own grand narrative to replace those
that have fallen under the weight of critique.
So, despite New Historicism's well-known resistance to
disciplinary canons and its aspiration to bring about cultural reform,
the movement's conception of itself seems to share most with the
definition of a "practice" as the exercise of a profession. On
the whole, its members see themselves as participating in discussions
and debates about the past, the present, and the future that engage the
wider world of culture and politics. But their base is in university
departments and scholarly journals, most notably Representations, and
their influence, while very broad for an academic movement, has largely
been confined within the world of professional scholarship. While there
is no fixed theory to which everyone adheres or a body of
incontrovertible findings that all accept, the practitioners of New
Historicism share a language, as it were, as well as assumptions and
questions that condition their discourse and relations with others.
One feature of New Historicist practice has been reliance on
anecdotes, and two chapters of Practicing New Historicism are devoted to
describing, explaining, and defending this preoccupation. The first
explores the movement's debts to Clifford Geertz's method of
"thick description" and to Eric Auerbach's form of
literary historicism, especially his attention to "mimesis."
Gallagher and Greenblatt argue that New Historicism built a bridge
between these two seemingly disparate approaches. Geertz's style of
interpretation sought to recover the imaginative world of social
groupings or communities in which individual acts could be understood as
signs in a common code, while Auerbach's historicism, in effect,
conjured out of a particular moment in a literary work "a complex,
dynamic, historically specific spirit of interpretation"
characteristic of a particular time and place (Gallagher and Greenblatt
37). In the hands of the New Historicists, the result of this union is a
disposition to treat cultures themselves as texts and texts as
embodiments of whole culture. While Gallagher and Greenblatt seem right
in suggesting that this treatment of cultures and texts is traceable
ultimately to Herder and German romanticism, whether Auerbach's
historicism and Geertz's cultural anthropology belong on the same
branch of this evolutionary tree is more open to doubt. But my focus
here is on what lessons New Historicists learned from Geertz and
Auerbach, not on whether the apparent affinities they discovered can
survive close historical or critical scrutiny, and on the former
Gallagher and Greenblatt are our native informants, as it were.
The use of the anecdote focuses on the way short, self-contained
narratives drawn most often from outside the realm of imaginative
literature or from small fragments of larger literary works can be used
to "put literature and literary criticism in touch with ... the
lived life" outside of literary texts. Anecdotes, Gallagher and
Greenblatt suggest, "select or ... fashion, out of the confused
continuum of social existence, units of social action small enough to
hold within the fairly narrow boundaries of full analytical
attention." They convey a "touch of the real," but they
also participate in and draw upon the imaginary. Whether anecdotes refer
to actual events no matter how carefully recorded, they are "alike
fictions in the root sense of things made, composed, fashioned."
Just like literary works, therefore, they "are shaped by the
imagination and by the available resources of narration and
description" in their context (Gallagher and Greenblatt 26, 28,
31). Those facts make it possible to read anecdotes as texts, and to see
in them, as Auerbach did so brilliantly in the opening chapters of his
Mimesis, the complex, multi-layered, life-world that produced them in
the first instance. As is revealed by the four chapters on art,
literature, and history with which this volume concludes, the debt to
Auerbach's historicism is large.
"The anecdote," Gallagher and Greenblatt say,
"satisfied the desire for something outside the literary, something
indeed that would challenge the boundaries of the literary. It offered
access to the everyday, the place where things actually are done, the
sphere of practice that even in its most awkward and inept articulations
makes a claim on the truth that is denied to the most eloquent of
literary texts." But it also did something more, they argue. By
introducing a "touch of the real," it provided a way to
"interrupt" what they call "the Big Stories," i.e.,
the master historical narratives treating the growth of capitalism, the
course of modernization, or the triumph of communism as not only the
main subject matter of historical study but the inevitable end product
of a unitary history process. Anecdotes, then, became the basis for
formulating what they call "counterhistories," which could be
"counterpoised against more ambitiously comprehensive historical
narratives" (Gallagher and Greenblatt, 31, 49, 51, 52, 54).
Here Gallagher and Greenblatt associate New Historicism not only
with the interest in anecdotes evinced by "humanist or
'culturalist' British left-wing" historians, such as E.
P. Thompson and Raymond Williams, but also with Michel Foucault's
use of "the anecdotal rupture" in his grand counterhistorical
project (Gallagher and Greenblatt 67). Again perhaps it matters little
whether Thompson and Williams would have felt comfortable in
Foucault's intellectual company, or he in theirs. For the purposes
of Practicing New Historicism, it arguably is enough to know that New
Historicists derived one of their most characteristic ways of working by
yoking together the divergent aims and approaches that they had learned
from these figures. The result is less a method, or even a set of
skills, than a disposition to treat the world as composed of a
kaleidoscope of fragments, something remote from the historical
intuitions of Thompson and Williams, if not always of Foucault.
"Counterhistory," Gallagher and Greenblatt say,
"opposes itself not only to dominant narrative, but also to
prevailing modes of historical thought and methods of research"
(Gallagher and Greenblatt, 52). Seen in this light, the concept of
"counterhistory" shares something with Karl Popper's
principle of "falsifiability" in scientific inquiry. According
to Popper's formulation, all scientifically meaningful propositions
must be open to disproof by contrary cases. In consequence, the truth of
positive claims to knowledge is only provisional and in any given
instance the demonstration of a contrary case results in the
"falsification," i.e. the rejection, of the claim.
Counterhistory understood in this manner also draws on the idea of
"counterfactual analysis," which represents a standard way of
isolating and testing causal explanations. While most historians would
resist the implication of Popper's analysis that their only
incontrovertibly true empirical statements are in the negative, much of
modern historical scholarship proceeds by the invocation of
counterfactuals in the course of making counterhistorical arguments.
Historians often criticize causal arguments in the form "if X was
present, Y follows" by falsifying the counterfactual into which it
can readily be translated: "if X is absent, Y does not
follow."
But a grand narrative, no matter the end point it identifies as its
own, commonly offers no unitary causal explanation for what happened.
Instead, it weaves a continuous storyline out of a series of little
stories--of anecdotes, if you will--that are seen to build on one
another cumulatively to produce the final result. Grand narratives do
not offer their explanations in a form testable by counterfactuals, and
so cannot be undermined by a single contrary case, no matter how richly
resonant that case might be. The best the latter can do is challenge the
larger structure and make it problematical. A counterhistory, in the
terms offered by Amos Funkenstein, from whom the concept is borrowed, is
something else again. (7) It not only seeks to destabilize the larger
narrative framework it challenges, but to displace it. Nevertheless, it
too offers its explanations in forms not readily amenable to
counterfactual refutation. Grand narratives and counterhistories, then,
are best understood not as a means for presenting proofs, but as devices
for organizing our historical imaginations and understandings. As such
they often coexist for long periods in dialogue or conflict before a new
paradigm comes along to shift the debate from settled ground.
Despite this limitation, Gallagher and Greenblatt want something
more from counterhistory--more perhaps than the latter can provide.
"Counterhistories," they say, "have tried to revive"
what they call the "alterity within" systems of thought.
"The force field of the anecdote," they argue, "pulled
even the most canonical works off the border of history and into the
company of nearly forgotten and unfamiliar existences. There
literature's own dormant counterhistorical life might be
reanimated: possibilities cut short, imaginings left unrealized,
projects half formulated, might be detected there," and stirred
back to life "at 'the touch of the real,'" as they
hoped (Gallagher and Greenblatt, 74). The remaining four chapters of the
book explore the porous boundaries between the "real" and the
"imaginary," alternating in pairs between early modern and
modern subjects.
Two chapters focus on the Real Presence in the Catholic Eucharist.
Chapter 3 considers belief in the presence of Christ's body and
blood in the bread and wine of Holy Communion as a paradigmatic example
of representation and its conundrums. Through a thoroughly engaging
comparison of Joos van Gent's late fifteenth-century Urbino
altarpiece Communion of the Apostles with its predella entitled
Profanation of the Host by Paolo Uccello, the chapter explores the
relations and tensions between faith and doubt, between Christians and
Jews, between membership in a community and exclusion, and finally
"between beliefs and representations" (Gallagher and
Greenblatt, 107). Chapter 5 returns to the same territory to examine
some of the controversies generated in the Reformation era by the
doctrine of the Real Presence and to show how Shakespeare's Hamlet
can be understood to have been "written in the shadow of these
controversies" (Gallagher and Greenblatt, 151). Although few
Reformation historians will find anything new here, and some might want
a more thoroughgoing familiarity with recent revisionist and
post-revisionist scholarship in Reformation studies, the play's
links to Reformation themes revealed in this chapter illuminate a number
of its dark corners. These two chapters resonate deeply with the renewed
interest in the place of religion in shaping modernity that is apparent
among scholars of early modern history and culture regardless of
discipline.
Two further chapters take us into the world of Victorian England.
Chapter 4, devoted to an exploration of "body history" and
what Gallagher and Greenblatt call "the materialist
imagination" (110), offers commentary on early nineteenth-century
debates among political economists and social reformers about the value
of the potato in the emerging industrial economy of the age and in the
diet of the poor in England and Ireland. The object is to contrast the
representational reality of Christ's presence discussed in the
previous chapter with the apparent materiality of the potato and the
human body and its appetites in order to show that they are themselves
products of imaginative representation and provide no stable history or
culture-free ground for explanation. For some commentators at the time,
the potato seemed capable of breaking the cycle of famine and distress
and to be the salvation of the poor, since it grew plentifully,
seemingly without exceptional efforts at cultivation, and unlike grain,
required no long series of productive processes to transform it into
something edible. For others, however, it seemed to be the food of
impoverishment, since it appeared to require no skill to grow; it turned
peasants, as it were, into beings born directly from the soil, the human
equivalent of the potato itself. And for many of the era's
political economists, devotees of Ricardo's "iron law of
wages," the fact that potatoes could be readily raised on small
plots by those who ate them meant that their use would keep wages low,
partly by promoting the growth of population beyond the capacity of the
economy to support them.
E. P. Thompson makes another appearance in this chapter, this time
in a somewhat puzzling discussion of his well-known essay "The
Moral Economy and the English Crowd in the Eighteenth Century,"
which Gallagher and Greenblatt honor but fail fully to grasp. (8)
Thompson's powerful focus on the interrelationship among political
rights, social justice, and the formation of class identity manifested
in the activities of English food rioters gives a rather different
weight to the concept of "moral economy" than does the
culturalist reading provided here. It is true, as Gallagher and
Greenblatt say, that Thompson does not mention the place of the potato
in the eighteenth- and nineteenth-century economy and in economic
thought. He concentrates instead on grain and bread, since these not
only were the subjects of the traditional regime of market regulation,
but also were the targets of the collective violence of the food
rioters. For him, the rioters step in to enforce the ethical and legal
principles that underpinned the old system of market control when the
officials responsible for assuring fair prices for grain and bread
failed in their duties. The rioters focused on rights to bread, not on
bread itself; and it was hunger for justice, more than for food that
prompted their collective action. There is good reason, therefore, for
Thompson's neglect of the potato and of the debates it engendered;
and while we have learned much from the history of the body to which
Gallagher and Greenblatt refer, it is doubtful that Thompson himself, or
we as his readers, would have found consideration of its finding a means
to "strengthen the 'culturalism' of his account"
(Gallagher and Greenblatt, 126). Thompson's interest was in the
mutually constitutive relations between the cultural and the social, not
in cultural analysis of symbolic systems undertaken on its own. There is
something still to be said for this focus on human sociability and on
the ways which peoples make and remake their collective lives in their
social interactions, although not always according to their own
choosing. (9)
The sixth and final chapter is the longest and also the most
loosely jointed. It takes up the novel in relation to modern skepticism.
But unlike Odysseus's scar and the world in Pantagruel's
mouth, which Auerbach had used to lay bare the essential features of
Homer's epic narrative and Montaigne's Pyrrhonistic doubt,
neither the novel as a genre nor skepticism as a philosophical
disposition can be treated as representing any one system of signs or as
being uniquely expressive of the characteristics of a particular time
and place. The novel chosen for close examination is Charles
Dickens's Great Expectations and the discussion ranges over a
complex array of subjects: relations between modern skeptical doubt and
the modern novel; relations between the living and the dead in the
creation of ideology; and relations between fathers and sons, or the
lack of them, in the shaping of imagination, the formation of personal
identity, and development of a concept of society. The moves made are
connected by association more than inner logic or a tight sequence of
causes and effects, and in consequence the form of the chapter itself
replicates several of the features of the modern skeptical outlook
discussed within it.
The chapter ends by reminding readers of the place that
Shakespeare's Hamlet has in Dickens's novel and of the
cultural, intellectual, and literary "distance" between the
two (Gallagher and Greenblatt, 204). But apart from invoking the role of
modern skepticism in undermining structures of belief in the era of
Enlightenment and beyond, no historical explanation is offered to
account for the differences. The rise of the modern novel and the
development of modern skepticism undoubtedly are implicated in each
other's histories, but the novel and skepticism are too varied in
their forms and instantiations to lend explanation of their separate and
collective histories very well to historicism, old or new.
Practicing New Historicism is a subtly rich and rewarding book. It
gives readers a good sense of New Historicism's intellectual and
methodological debts as well as of its aims and the approaches that it
uses. The discussions of individual works, whether visual or literary,
always provide insights, some quite profound, even if at several points
their larger arguments may seem a bit muddled or fail fully to persuade.
It also gives a very fine sense of New Historicism's contributions
to literary criticism. But it is not intended to be a contribution to
historical study and is somewhat limited in the sense of historical
process it conveys. In keeping with the modes of thought presented in
this volume, there is no overarching conclusion. Its final chapter
completes the cycle of argument by predicting, and simultaneously
demonstrating and lamenting, the continued survival of
"disbelief" free "from all ontologies, including
materialism" as a mode of addressing the world (Gallagher and
Greenblatt, 210).
II
Imagination
I turn now to Greenblatt's Hamlet in Purgatory, a work
preoccupied with things imagined and with poetic and historical
imagination. (10) History as written is inescapably the work of the
imagination--it requires bringing into presence events or developments
that are necessarily absent and communicating their presence vividly, or
at least intelligibly, to readers who have neither experienced them at
firsthand nor examined their traces in the surviving historical record.
In some ways, therefore, doing history and reading history share
something with the encounters with ghosts with which Greenblatt is
engaged in his impressive, insightful, and very substantial discussion
of the history of spirit and ghost lore and of the so-called "third
place" of Purgatory in Hamlet in Purgatory. We depend for many of
our present-day assumptions and presuppositions on conventions, ideas,
and images drawn from the past. Sometimes they haunt us, and we must
exorcise them from our souls and move on. Sometimes, however, they enter
into the very core of our beings and shape or motivate our actions, as
did the ghost of Hamlet's father whose presence in Hamlet provides
the focus for Greenblatt's subtle and well-crafted reconstruction
of the history of purgatorial conceptions before, during, and after the
Reformation era.
But as Thomas Babington Macaulay noted long ago, history is also
inescapably in the realm of our reasoning powers--i.e., of our skills in
discovering and assessing historical records and documents, our
abilities in transforming our discoveries into findings, and our
capacities in organizing our findings into logical, coherent arguments.
"History," Macaulay says, "at least in its state of ideal
perfection, is a compound of poetry and philosophy. It impresses general
truths on the mind by a vivid representation of particular characters
and incidents." (11) "A perfect historian," he argues
elsewhere, "must possess an imagination sufficiently powerful to
make his narrative affecting and picturesque. Yet he must content
himself with the materials he finds, and to refrain from supplying
deficiencies by additions of his own. He must be a profound and
ingenious reasoner. Yet he must possess sufficient self-command to
abstain from casting his facts in the mould of his hypothesis."
(12)
Macaulay professed himself to be acquainted with no work of history
that was equally obedient to "its two rulers, the Reason and the
Imagination," none which "approach[ed] what a history ought to
be ... no history which [did] not widely depart, either on the right
hand or the left, from the exact line." Given the "insuperable
difficulties" in producing such a perfectly balanced history, no
one would "think it strange," he said, "that every writer
should have failed, either in the narrative or in the speculative
department of history." These are somewhat harsh words, but even
now it is hard to argue against the conclusion that only the rare
historical writer has been able to walk along "the exact line"
Macaulay envisioned.
Where does Greenblatt's Hamlet in Purgatory fit on
Macaulay's sliding scale? In certain ways, it is much more a
history, in the sense that Macaulay meant the word, than
Greenblatt's other works, including Practicing New Historicism. In
asking us to remember the age in which Hamlet was written, it leans more
to the side of the imagination, not just in its subject matter but also
in the vividness of its interpretations. But in building up a picture of
that distant world from the evidence of the texts studied, it also
participates in an act of historical recovery that would have been
familiar in its basic elements to Macaulay himself. With the possible
exception of Greenblatt's study of the career of Sir Walter Ralegh,
(13) none of his books offers so sustained an examination of a single,
if complex, historical problem, or tells a single story in so focused a
fashion. It is not the perfect history of Macaulay's aspiration,
but it lies more toward the middle of the spectrum than what we might
call the "pole of imagination" tout court.
Taken as a work of historical analysis, which it is only in part of
course, the book presents a remarkably imaginative structure. "I
believe that nothing comes of nothing," Greenblatt says, "even
in Shakespeare. I wanted to know where he got the matter he was working
with and what he did with that matter" (Greenblatt, 4). The first
chapter begins with Simon Fish's A Supplication of the Beggars of
1529, reviews the place in English religious life of some of the
institutions associated with Purgatory at the time, and examines the
extensive early reformation critique of the place as a poet's
fiction. The latter claim condemns Purgatory as a fraud, damning it to
Hell as it were; but in the second chapter Greenblatt undertakes to
evaluate in a religiously neutral way what it means to treat Purgatory
as "a vast piece of poetry," i.e., as an imagined reality
(Greenblatt, 47). This chapter ranges broadly over medieval literature and art and considers in depth several literary representations of Saint
Patrick's Purgatory, a treatise originally dating from the late
twelfth century. But Greenblatt applies this broader approach only to
his treatment of medieval materials, not to the Renaissance or early
modern ones taken up elsewhere in the book, and one may wonder whether a
similarly broad, comparative perspective would have further illuminated
issues arising later in the book.
The following chapter, the third, takes up the purgatorial claims
of the dead to prayer and remembrance and closely examines the medieval
narrative known in its fourteenth-century Middle English version as The
Gast of Gy. Greenblatt treats these claims as "rights of
memory," to quote the chapter's title. The chapter then ends
with a detailed reading of Thomas More's A Supplication of Souls,
first published in 1529. In The Supplication, More, lord chancellor at
the time, mounted his vigorous defense of the intercessory institutions
of the Church against Fish and other critics. It is only in the fourth
chapter that ghosts finally appear in full Renaissance theatrical garb.
Ghosts "do not altogether vanish in the later sixteenth
century," Greenblatt argues, although they are "labeled"
by Protestants "as fictions of the mind.... Instead they turn up
onstage" (Greenblatt, 151). In this fourth chapter we find a
wide-ranging overview of the representation of ghosts and spirits in
English Renaissance drama, including the corpus of Shakespeare's
plays. This discussion then leads in the fifth and final substantive
chapter to a brilliant exploration of the way Hamlet draws on and builds
upon the materials that Greenblatt has so effectively interpreted in the
previous chapters.
As the above account might suggest, Greenblatt's treatment in
the early chapters necessarily gives greater weight to the views of
those who believed in Purgatory and conformed to the institutions and
practices associated with it than to those who opposed the intercessory
regime with which it was intimately connected. Scant attention is given
to the arguments of John Wycliffe, who believed in Purgatory but not in
the worldly institutions of intercession to which it gave rise, and
equally little is said about the views and activities of the Lollards.
Although Fish and other Protestants who attacked Purgatory, such as
William Tyndale and John Foxe, receive very thorough treatments, they
appear effectively as outsiders bringing in new ideas with which to
overturn the old. It is assumed, correctly of course, that the
Protestantism of these figures accounts for their rejection of the
purgatorial regime, but whether they received their Protestantism
exclusively as an import or derived it in part from native roots does
not engage Greenblatt's discussion. Nor does any attempt to account
historically for the great paradigm shift demonstrated by the book. In
consequence, the Reformation is treated as a given historical fact and
only the responses to it are examined as parts of an ongoing historical
development. A more satisfactory approach might have been to treat the
Reformation itself as a process in which religious identities were
formed, and sometimes performed, in and by the clash of rival positions.
Viewed in this manner, the debate about Purgatory would be seen as
constitutive of the Reformation's history.
The presence of the Ghost in Shakespeare's Hamlet--the
presence, that is, of that spectral figure putatively of the prince of
Denmark's father, who appears on stage near the beginning of the
play asking his son to "Remember me"--gives this probing and
stimulating book its intellectual and critical impetus. As Greenblatt
convincingly demonstrates, the Ghost's call upon Hamlet to remember
repeats language traditionally associated with the regime of
intercessory prayer in Catholic practice. How, then, should we
understand this and other echoes of Purgatory in Shakespeare's play
and, more generally, in the beliefs of his contemporaries? The story
Greenblatt tells is meant to answer this deep, if simple-sounding
question. Its nexus is located in the early moments of the English
Reformation, when Fish's attack on the power and greed of the
clergy in A Supplication of the Beggars was answered by More's own
defense of traditional intercessory institutions and practices in A
Supplication of Souls. Fish's Supplication was written in the
voices of the wandering poor, the very same downtrodden beggars and
vagabonds to whose plight Thomas More had drawn attention in Utopia.
More, in response, presented his Supplication in the voices of dead
souls pleading for prayers from kin and neighbors. For Greenblatt, the
text of Hamlet, with its pervasive skepticism about things seen and
unseen, its probing of the boundary between the imagined and the real,
and its frequent references to memory and remembrance, contains within
it something of the same contested territory marked out by this
important early Reformation debate.
Much of what Shakespeare says in the play reveals his thoroughgoing
familiarity with the forms and attractions of the Old Religion. This
knowledge is not surprising, perhaps, given that the playwright came
from a recusant family and early in his career may well have had
personal links with Lancashire Catholics. Greenblatt, however, sensibly
does not attempt to settle whether "Shakespeare himself was a
secret Catholic sympathizer." Although he explores some important
religious issues in considerable depth, his goal is "not to
understand the theology behind the ghost, still less to determine
whether it was 'Catholic' or 'Protestant'"
(Greenblatt, 4, 254). Nor does he enter into current debates among
English historians about the pace of the Reformation or the relative
strength of Catholicism and Protestantism in the early modern era. He
cites some of so-called "revisionists," such as Eamon Duffy,
Christopher Haigh, and J. J. Scarisbrick, but does not offer a close
treatment of their works or discuss Reformation historians who disagree
with them.
Greenblatt finds no systematic defense of Catholicism in
Shakespeare's play. Nor does he find in it a defense of
Protestantism, although elements of a Protestant sensibility and of
Protestant usage also abound in the play. Too much in its language and
plot, most notably the Ghost's bloody demand for revenge, speaks
against the play advancing any established religious movement or
advocating a single religious stance. Instead, Greenblatt says, it mixes
elements derived from the medieval literature of "wonder" and
tales of miracles, in which spirits regularly manifest their presence,
with those of Senecan revenge tragedy, where we also find ghosts as
standard fixtures of the genre. Purgatory, which provides the foundation
for the medieval forms, focuses on the cure of souls in the other world
of the dead, where the justice of God is tempered with His mercy. It
draws attention to what the living might do for the well being of those
who have passed from this world, not to how they might avenge in this
world wrongs experienced by the departed while still alive. In revenge
tragedy, souls cry out for bloody retribution not spiritual redemption.
"[W]hile compatible with a Christian (and, specifically, a
Catholic) call for remembrance," Greenblatt argues, Purgatory
"is utterly incompatible with a Senecan call for vengeance."
Nevertheless in Shakespeare's hands, the tension--the seeming
contradiction--between remembrance and revenge, which might otherwise
have led "to derision," works, Greenblatt suggests, to
"intensify the play's uncanny power." It achieves this
effect, "by participating in a violent ideological
struggle"--not between confessions, but between
sensibilities--"that turned negotiations with the dead from an
institutional process governed by the church to a poetic process
governed by guilt, projection, and imagination" (Greenblatt,
237,252).
Although Greenblatt does not emphasize the fact, 1529, the year
that Fish and More published their rival Supplications, represents a
critical moment in England's political and religious history--the
point where, as it were, the needs of the state and the requirements of
the conscience converged. By then Henry VIII was firmly committed to
ending his marriage with Catherine of Aragon, but had not yet decided on
the break from Rome. As More clearly recognized, the future course of
events lay in the balance, and the power of words to persuade and
condemn was concomitantly great. It was a time when the existence of
Purgatory was not only of importance to the soul's welfare, but
also to the church's and the state's; it was worth a fight.
Whatever else Purgatory did, its putative existence emphasized the
central (although, as Greenblatt correctly reminds us, not the
exclusive) place of the church as an institution in interceding with God
through the saints on behalf of sinful individuals living and dead. If
the place was a sham--"a poet's fable" as Tyndale put it,
or an idle fantasy just like Utopia, as Foxe would later insist--many
other claims made by the church and its priests to the possession of
spiritual power and to a share of the worldly wealth of its communicants
were as well. The highly contested character of this moment therefore
comes as no surprise.
The picture was rather different at the time of the first
performance of Hamlet in 1601. By then not only had the official
doctrine and liturgy of the Church of England erased the name of
Purgatory, but the traditional institutions of intercession--the
saints' cults, monasteries and chantries, and anniversary
masses--also had been dismantled. While some Catholics continued to
conspire against Protestant rule in England, and representatives of the
rival confessions contested for converts and persisted in their
vituperative debates, Greenblatt eschews any treatment of these matters.
His interest is in the text, and in what Shakespeare, the author, did to
make it what it was. Hamlet, in Greenblatt's view, took no sides in
the great religious quarrels of the era, but instead incorporated
elements from competing outlooks and used them for its literary
purposes, inviting the members of its audience to confront if not
resolve the deepest contradictions residing within the conventional
concepts and practices by which they lived. Many no doubt took the play
in this way, but one may well wonder whether a number might have seen
more immediate religious conflicts or controversies at stake with some
Protestants perhaps hoping that James VI in Scotland (Elizabeth's
likely successor), would follow a more aggressive anti-Catholic stance
once installed in England, and some Catholics possibly hoping he would
be more tolerant toward them.
Although it is possible to differ over the interpretation of
Shakespeare's aims in Hamlet--the play is far too rich to reduce to
any single view--Greenblatt surely is correct in concluding that the
playwright was not himself seeking to intervene directly in the great
confessional disputes of his day. But to a surprising degree in so
carefully a contextualized study, little is said about the play's
first audiences or early readers and what they might have brought with
them to their interpretations. The assumption seems to be that they
built their views out of the same materials as Shakespeare. It is
perhaps worth keeping in mind, however, that for many of them religious
controversy remained fully alive at the time the play was first
performed, although in retrospect we might agree, as Greenblatt
seemingly does, that the institutional and cultural changes wrought by
the Reformation had by then given Protestantism a nearly insurmountable
dominion over the scene. Even if most contemporaries had faith in the
probable victory of Protestantism, it remained uncertain what sort of
Protestantism it would be. Moreover, for English men and women living
ca. 1601, whether Protestant or Catholic or those yet to be firmly
converted to either camp, the course of Providential history still held
out the prospect of a last great battle between the forces of light and
of darkness. In 1601, England was still at war with Spain; it had been
threatened with the possible return of the Armada as recently as 1599.
Whether England or Spain would triumph in the end was not yet certain.
No matter how deep one's faith, treating historical events as
reflecting the will of God meant weighing their providential
significance case by case and acting according to what one judged God
demanded. The evidence was never anything but ambiguous. Was victory a
sign of one's rectitude or a temptation to pride? Was defeat a test
of one's faith or a warning of one's error? In consequence,
among seriously committed Protestants and Catholics there was the belief
that the religious convictions of the English remained in play. Indeed,
as Peter Lake and Michael Questier recently have been arguing, many
philosophically deep and politically important issues had been
revivified in the 1590s in the course of clashes between the so-called
Puritans and the Church of England's hierarchy and their conformist supporters in which the importance of ceremonies and the doctrine of
predestination were once again in hotly contested debate. In these
circumstances, room was opened anew for Catholic apologists to intervene
on behalf of their own views. Protestants feared Catholic resurgence and
felt the need to battle against anything that smacked of popery, while
Catholics, or some of them, remained ever hopeful of winning back the
faithful. (14) Hence, some in Hamlet's first audience might well
have seen the play engaged with these living political and
ecclesiological issues of the day and not only with the spiritual and
psychological ones to which Greenblatt so effectively draws our
attention.
Although nothing that Greenblatt says contradicts the above
account, it is not his purpose to explore this kind of historical
territory. His interests reside elsewhere, namely "in the
tragedy's magical intensity" (Greenblatt, 4), i.e., its
imaginative capacity to call the spirits of its characters vividly into
presence. For him, the text in effect engages in an internal dialogue
about the boundary between the living and the dead. Is the apparition that Hamlet saw, or thought he saw, truly the living spirit of his dead
father or actually the work of the devil tempting the prince of Denmark
to sin? Is the boundary between this life and the next open or closed?
How can one decide? In Greenblatt's treatment, these questions also
concern the boundary between material and imagined reality, and
therefore between experience and art or culture. Is the boundary
impervious or porous? Should it be one or the other? These deep
questions, which connect to but transcend the great debates of the
Reformation, were not yet settled, and it is one of the many successes
of this important book that it treats them as living problems for the
English as they confronted and accommodated to the reverberating
consequences of the religious revolution through which their kingdom was
passing.
For Greenblatt "Purgatory exists in the imaginary universe of
Hamlet only as what the suffering prince, in a different context, calls
'a dream of passion.'" It gave "its viewers,"
he says, "many of the deep imaginative experiences, the tangled
longing, guilt, pity, and rage evoked by More." But did this
"unforgettably vivid dream," also participate "in a
secularization process ... in which the theater offers a disenchanted
version of what the cult of Purgatory once offered?" Without
rejecting the possibility outright, Greenblatt concludes that "the
palpable effect is something like the reverse: Hamlet immeasurably
intensifies a sense of the weirdness of the theater, its proximity to
certain experiences that had been organized and exploited by religious
institutions and rituals" (Greenblatt, 252,253). A similar point is
made in the book's short but apt "Epilogue," which takes
us to Shakespeare's The Tempest. There the playwright famously
probed the relationship between dreams and reality, spirits and actors,
prayers and applause, the theater and "the great globe
itself." Shakespeare seems to be more than playful when he has
Prospero say: "As you from crimes would pardoned be, / Let your
indulgence set me free." In the face of the desacralization of
religious institutions that accompanied the Reformation, Greenblatt
seems to be suggesting a migration of the holy to other sites, temporal
in character with the theater high among them.
Hamlet in Purgatory addresses the history it considers primarily
through the close examination of texts, each seen in relation to a
fabric of other texts with which it shares subject matter, concepts, and
rhetoric, if not genre or form. The readings offered are as illuminating
as they are subtle, and it is one of the great pleasures of the book to
follow along as its author makes the connections among seemingly diverse
literary motifs and images and draws out their implications. The book
asks hard questions, and it presses to answer them. It is also a deeply
humane book. In asking us to consider "the afterlife of Purgatory,
the echoes of its dead name" (3), it is calling upon us to weigh
our own encounters with the spirits of the dead in the traditions or
conventions that shape our self-understanding and our actions.
III
History
Although many of the methods employed by historians in the present
day might be unrecognizable to the founders of the discipline, history
still retains its ancient, Herodotean roots, as a form of inquiry. As
with Herodotus and Thucydides, however, the results of historical
research most commonly are presented as stories, small, medium, and
large. And, as in Macaulay's conception, its ideal form arguably is
still a vividly told narrative, or series of interconnected narratives,
grounded in the careful discovery, evaluation, and presentation of
evidence. Stories, as distinct from descriptions, normally involve
change of some kind.
However, in much of the work of New Historicists, such as
Greenblatt's Renaissance Self-Fashioning or his often reprinted
essay "Invisible Bullets," emphasis was given to the
persistent power of political and cultural institutions or structures to
contain the forces of change. (15) Change, when it was discussed at all,
was understood to proceed by abrupt breaks or ruptures from settled
frameworks of practice and power. Between these breaks, the movement of
events disappeared entirely or became compressed and flattened. In
Shakespearean Negotiations Greenblatt modified this position somewhat.
There the emphasis was on the "circulation" of vivid
representations in a reciprocal dialogue, rather than on their
containment. Nevertheless, little attention was paid to the processes by
which cultural forms or ideological structures changed over time. (16) A
similar idea is to be found in his Marvelous Possessions, a book
especially focused on what Greenblatt calls "the assimilation of
the other." There, explicitly adapting Marx, he speaks of "the
reproduction and circulation of mimetic capital," a formulation
that stresses the accumulation of a stockpile of vivid images that have
recognized value under existing "social relations of
production" and that can be mixed and matched to make further
representations. (17) In many ways the models of historical development
embedded in Practicing New Historicism replicate these understandings.
Hamlet in Purgatory, in contrast, is simultaneously an analysis and
an account of a long-term, interlocking process of change in some of
England's main cultural institutions. On the one hand, it examines
the development of Purgatory as an imagined place and its continued
presence in Renaissance literature and culture. Although Greenblatt says
that his book is about the post-Reformation life of Purgatory, there is
at least as much about its long history during the middle ages as about
what happened to it during and after the Reformation. On the other hand,
the book seeks to explore the emergence of the theater as a major
cultural institution in Renaissance England.
In making his case, Greenblatt sees the medieval and Reformation
materials from which Shakespeare constructed the Ghost in Hamlet as the
same materials from which the theater as a social form established its
niche in modern culture and from which the drama and its performances
derive their ideological or cultural power. The process is one in which
elements from the past, often wrenched from the frameworks in which they
were first established, persistently enter into the present, even though
typically in different, sometimes quite new, surroundings. Although
something of the idea of circulation still remains, conventions and
practices from within Western Christendom's own past are
transformed by the fires of the Reformation, and not simply transmitted,
circulated, and reassimilated.
Viewed in its broadest terms, therefore, Hamlet in Purgatory is a
book about how past history lives on in memory and inherited practices
and continues to shape present culture. While the book does not
represent the rejection of its author's previous views or
abandonment of his past positions, it offers--to this reader at least--a
significant move away from some of their most problematic features.
While the concept of "containment" might help to explain the
absence of significant historical change over long periods, it makes its
occurrence something of a mystery. Similarly, while the idea of
"negotiation" can go some way to account for the circulation
of social energies within and between texts, it does so by downplaying
the potential for change in social and cultural life. What is
transmitted is the characteristic force of the person or thing within
the circulating medium, not the transformative effects they might have.
In Hamlet in Purgatory, the focus is on how individuals and
communities come to live with, participate in, and accommodate the fact
of historical change. We do so, Greenblatt now seems to be saying, by
adaptation and reinterpretation, rather than by destruction or
replacement. In effect, the ghost of Hamlet's father becomes a
figure for the continuing hold the spirit of the past has on the
present. Just as for Shakespeare, so for us, "nothing comes from
nothing" (Greenblatt, 4). While many historians would not endorse
this view in its entirety, there is no doubt that it captures a large
measure of the truth about historical processes.
Notes
(1.) Stephen Greenblatt, "Introduction," in Genre Special
Topic 7: The Power of Forms in the English Renaissance, ed. Stephen
Greenblatt, Genre 15, nos. 1-2 (Spring-Summer 1982), 5. This volume was
reprinted as The Power of Forms in the English Renaissance, ed. Stephen
Greenblatt (Norman, OK: Pilgrim Books, 1982). The term "new
historicism" was not an entirely new coinage in 1982; see Wesley
Morris, Toward a New Historicism (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1972).
(2.) Stephen Greenblatt, Renaissance Self-Fashioning: From More to
Shakespeare (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980); The Making of
the Modern Body: Sexuality and Society in the Nineteenth Century, ed,
Catherine Gallagher and Thomas Laqueur (Berkeley and Los Angeles:
University of California Press, 1987).
(3.) I associate myself with both sides. I made my first attempts
to comment critically on certain features of this movement in two review
articles published in the later 1980s: "History in Literature: The
Renaissance," Journal of British Studies 26, no. 1 (January 1987):
107-23; "Searching for 'Culture' in the English
Renaissance," Shakespeare Quarterly 39, no. 4 (Winter 1988):
465-88. My book The Widening Gate: Bristol and the Atlantic Economy,
1450-1700 (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press,
1991) is number 15 in the University of California Press's New
Historicism series, edited by Stephen Greenblatt.
(4.) Marc Bloch, The Historian's Craft, intro. Joseph R.
Strayer, trans. Peter Putnam (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, Inc., 1953), 9.
(5.) Ibid., 10.
(6.) Ibid., 13. For Gallagher and Greenblatt's comments on New
Historicism's associations with aspects of the Annales
school's program, see Practicing New Historicism, 53, 59. It is
worth noting as well that New Historicism at its founding was especially
concerned to reject what it saw as the moral obtuseness of "the
mainstream literary history practiced in the first half" of the
twentieth century. See Greenblatt's early comments on "The
Political Background of Shakespeare's Richard II and Henry
IV," delivered in 1939 by Dover Wilson before the German
Shakespeare Society at Weimar; Greenblatt, "Introduction,"
Power of Forms, 5-6.
(7.) See Amos Funkenstein, "History, Counterhistory, and
Narrative," in Probing the Limits of Representation: Nazism and the
"Final Solution," ed. Saul Friedlander (Cambridge: Harvard
University Press, 1992), 66-81; Amos Funkenstein, Theology and the
Scientific Imagination from the Middle Ages to the Seventeenth Century
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1986), 202-89, esp. 273-89.
Gallagher and Greenblatt discuss Funkenstein's idea on p. 52.
(8.) Gallagher and Greenblatt cite this 1971 Past and Present
article from E. P. Thompson, Customs in Common: Studies in Traditional
and Popular Culture (New York: New Press, 1991), 185-258.
(9.) For a recent critique of cultural analysis as practiced by
anthropologists such as Geertz, see Adam Kuper, Culture: The
Anthropologists' Account (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
1999). For a somewhat similar critique from the perspective of literary
study, see Terry Eagleton's "Blackwell Manifesto": The
Idea of Culture (Oxford: Blackwell, 2000).
(10.) I have also discussed Greenblatt's Hamlet in Purgatory
in similar terms in "Exercising the Imagination," an H-ALBION
review on H-NET, which also comments on Carlo Ginzburg, No Island Is an
Island: Four Glances at English Literature in a World Perspective (New
York: Columbia University Press, 2000); Davis Harris Sacks,
"Exercising the Imagination," H-Album Review, for H-NET,
August 2002, http://www.h-net.msu.edu/reviews/showrev.cgi?path =
204381032241906.
(11.) Thomas Babington Macaulay, "Hallam," in The Works
of Lord Macaulay Complete, ed. Hannah More Macaulay, Lady Trevelyan, 8
vols. (London: Long-roans, Green and Co., 1873), 5: 162; a review of
Henry Hallam, The Constitutional History of England, from the Accession
of Henry VII. to the death of George II, 2 vols. (1827), first published
in the Edinburgh Review in September 1828.
(12.) Macaulay, "History," in Works, 5: 122-23; a review
of Henry Neele, The Romance of History. England (London, 1828), first
published in the Edinburgh Review in May 1828.
(13.) Stephen Greenblatt, Sir Walter Ralegh: The Renaissance Man
and His Roles (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1973).
(14.) See Peter Lake and Michael Questier, The Antichrist's
Lewd Hat: Protestants, Papists, and Players in Post-Reformation England
(New Haven: Yale University Press, 2002).
(15.) Greenblatt, Renaissance Self-Fashioning. For the earliest
version of "Invisible Bullets," see Stephen Greenblatt,
"Invisible Bullets: Renaissance Authority and Its Subversion,"
in Glyph: Textual Studies #8, ed. Waiter Benn Michaels (1981) 40-61.
(16.) Stephen Greenblatt, Shakespearean Negotiations: The
Circulation of Social Energy in Renaissance England (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1988).
(17.) Stephen Greenblatt, Marvelous Possessions: The Wonder of the
New World (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1991), 3, 6.
DAVID HARRIS SACKS is Professor of History and Humanities at Reed
College. Among his works on the history and culture of early modern
Britain and the Atlantic world, The Historical Imagination in Early
Modern Britain: History, Rhetoric, and Fiction, 1500-1800 (1997), a
collection of essays coedited with Donald R. Kelley, appeared in
paperback in fall 2002. He is presently at work on two books: The Sweet
Name of Liberty: The Culture of Freedom in Early Modern England, and
Restoring the Distracted Globe: Richard Hakluyt and His World.