Intellectual property and the property rights movement: should intellectual property be accorded the same protections as tangible forms of property?
Menell, Peter S.
The property rights movement (PRM) has taken active interest in
several Supreme Court cases over the past few years. It was hardly
surprising to see PRM activists mobilize in support of Susette Kelo,
whose home was condemned by the city of New London. She argued that
condemning her property to convey it to a private developer did not
constitute "public use" and hence violated her constitutional
rights. Ms. Kelo's plight fell squarely within PRM's core
agenda of safeguarding the liberty interests of property owners against
governmental interference. Nor was it surprising to see PRM
organizations mobilize in Rapanos v. United States, involving the scope
of federal authority to regulate wetlands; San Remo Hotel v. City &
County of San Francisco, challenging the constitutionality of a hotel
conversion ordinance under the Takings Clause; Lingle v. Chevron U.S.A.,
seeking to overturn a state statute limiting the rent that oil companies
could charge dealers leasing company-owned service stations; or
Tahoe-Sierra Preservation Council, Inc. v. Tahoe Regional Planning
Agency, asserting that a temporary moratorium on development effected an
unconstitutional taking of private property.
By contrast, eBay v. MercExchange did not seem to fit the PRM mold.
The "property" at issue--a patent on a method of selling goods
through an "electronic network of consignment stores"--could
hardly have been more different in character and economic underpinning
than Susette Kelo's home. MercExchange had prevailed in a patent
infringement action and sought to enjoin eBay, the popular online
auctioneer, from further use of the patented method in the hope of
forcing a favorable licensing deal. The patentability of such methods
was itself quite controversial because of the abstract nature of
business method claims. Furthermore, the governmental
"interference" with the patent owner's property was
limited. The district court denied MercExchange's request for a
permanent injunction based on the patent owner's willingness to
license to other parties, the adequacy of monetary damages, the fact
that the patentee did not itself practice the invention, and
"growing concern" over the effects of business method patents
on competition and innovation. The U.S. Court of Appeals overturned the
denial of the permanent injunction, holding that, as a "general
rule," injunctions must follow all patent infringement findings
absent "exceptional circumstances" such as a grave risk to
public health. As a result, eBay appealed to the Supreme Court, which
granted certiorari in late 2005.
In an amicus brief filed in the Supreme Court on behalf of
"various law and economics scholars," Prof. Richard Epstein,
one of the PRM's leading theorists, contended that the
Merc-Exchange patent deserved much the same protection as real estate.
By analogizing patent infringement to trespass, the brief argued that
injunctive relief should be presumed in cases of patent infringement. It
pushed the boundaries of patent law advocacy by citing land encroachment
precedent.
The property rights rhetoric in the eBay case marked an important
new front in the campaign to establish a strict and broad interpretation
of property rights and their enforcement. Professor Epstein's
expansion of his property rights advocacy into the intellectual property
domain over the past several years coincides with the growing importance
of intangible assets in the modern economy. The digital revolution has
displaced General Motors and other manufacturing enterprises from the
top of the economic food chain. Knowledge-based companies such as
Google, Microsoft, and Apple reflect the new economic order.
[ILLUSTRATION OMITTED]
Other property rights advocates have joined the effort to
"port" the absolutist libertarian vision to the realm of
intellectual property. In a May 21, 2007 op-ed page advertisement in the
New York Times, the Washington Legal Foundation led:
Stolen Property, Stolen Future
What if strangers showed up in your backyard and held a block
party? America's fiercely defended tradition of private property
rights wouldn't tolerate this. But that is in essence what's
happening to the intellectual property ... of American businesses
overseas.
Should "intellectual property" be so blithely equated
with tangible forms of "property"? While there are certainly
historical connections and functional parallels between
"intellectual property" and "property,"
philosophical, legal, economic, and political bases for protecting
intellectual property and tangible property differ in significant ways.
Those underpinnings suggest that the effort to bring intellectual
property into the "property" tent may well backfire.
SEMANTICS AND SUBSTANCE
Private property in land and other tangible resources is perhaps
the oldest human institution and has long occupied a prominent position
in law and philosophy. But to what extent does intellectual
property--rights in intangible resources--fall within the relatively
uniform right structure applied to land and other tangible resources?
The law has long treated land and intellectual property within the
general rubric of "property." The first use of the term
"intellectual property" in a reported legal decision can be
traced to an 1845 patent case in which the court observed that "a
liberal construction ... given to a patent" will encourage
"ingenuity and perseverance" and "only in this way can we
protect intellectual property, the labors of the mind, productions and
interests as much a man's own, and as much the fruit of his honest
industry, as the wheat he cultivates, or the flocks he rears."
Prof. Justin Hughes, in a recent Southern California Law Review article,
notes that "the courts and legislatures had regularly discussed
copyrighted works as 'property' throughout the seventeenth,
eighteenth, and early nineteenth centuries, with the adjectival concepts
of 'artistic,' 'literary,' and
'intellectual' orbiting around the property notion."
There can be little question today that intellectual property
assets are forms of "property." The Patent Act expressly
declares that "patents shall have the attributes of personal
property" and the Supreme Court acknowledges them as such. The
Copyright Act states that "ownership of a copyright may be
transferred in whole or in part by any means of conveyance or by
operation of law, and may be bequeathed by will or pass as personal
property by the applicable laws of intestate succession."
But the classification of patents, copyrights, trademarks, and
trade secrets as forms of "property" does not resolve the
contours of those assets and the rights and protections that their
owners enjoy. Property is not a monolithic concept and its treatment
varies significantly across classes of resources. The critical question
is not whether the rubric "property" applies to intellectual
property, but whether the traditional rights associated with real and
other tangible forms of property apply to intellectual property.
Professor Epstein and some other PRM advocates assert that the
rules associated with real property (such as a strict right to exclude
and restrictions on governmental interference) should govern
intellectual property. Those scholars would shoehorn intellectual
property into an idealized Blackstonian conception of property rights as
exclusive and inviolate. Yet such a classification is more semantic than
actual. The two fields derive from different philosophical foundations,
embody different rules and institutions, and reflect different political
constituencies.
PHILOSOPHICAL DIFFERENCES
John Locke believed that every man has an inherent property
interest in his own person and, by extension, in the labor of his body,
subject to there being "enough, and as good left in common for
others." Upon this foundation, Locke asserted "life, liberty,
and property" to be inalienable rights of a just society.
Drawing upon Locke's natural rights conception of property,
the Property Rights Movement advocates an absolutist approach to the
protection of property rights and strict limitations on government
interference with private property. Notwithstanding the Founders'
varied views of private property --such as Benjamin Franklin's view
that "Private Property ... is a Creature of Society, and is subject
to the Calls of that Society, whenever its Necessities shall require it,
even to its last Farthing"--the property rights movement sees in
the Constitution's Takings Clause uncompromising protection of
property, founded in liberty.
By contrast, patents and copyrights emerged largely through
legislative enactments pursuant to a specific utilitarian constitutional
directive: "to promote the Progress in Science and the useful
Arts." Although the documentary history relating to this clause is
sparse, there can be little question that the Founders saw the
Intellectual Property Clause functioning quite differently than the
Takings Clause. In an address to Congress on January 8, 1790, President
George Washington noted:
[T]here is nothing which can better deserve your patronage than the
promotion of science and literature. Knowledge is, in every
country, the surest basis of public happiness. In one in which the
measures of government receive their impression so immediately from
the sense of the community as in ours, it is proportionably
essential.
In response, the newly formed House of Representatives resolved:
"We concur with you in the sentiment that ... the promotion of
science and literature will contribute to the security of a free
Government; in the progress of our deliberations we shall not lose sight
of objects so worthy of our regard." In the spring of that year,
Congress passed the first federal patent and copyright laws.
UTILITARIAN APPROACH
Rather than emulate real property rules and institutions,
intellectual property can best be understood as a malleable bundle of
rights to be molded to promote the progress of science and the arts.
Indeed, the various modes of intellectual property protection diverge
significantly from Blackstone's model of absolute
rights--perpetual, exclusive, and inviolate. Two of the most prominent
forms of intellectual property patents and copyrights--protect works for
limited durations (although in the case of copyrights, the term is quite
long). Furthermore, exclusivity in the field of "intellectual
property" is far less inviolate than it is in the traditional
property domains. Intellectual property law comprises a system of policy
levers that legislatures tailor and courts interpret in order to promote
innovation and protect the integrity of markets in light of the
ever-changing state of technology as well as social institutions.
Patent law's experimental use defense and various exceptions
(e.g., severe restrictions on enforcement of medical procedure patents,
prior user rights for business methods) limit the exclusivity of patent
rights. Copyright law's fair use doctrine, numerous compulsory
licenses, and various exemptions significantly qualify the exclusivity
of copyright interests. Trademark law's distinctiveness doctrine,
infringement standard, and nominative use defense significantly
constrain the exclusivity of trademark rights. Trade secret law's
independent discovery defense similarly qualifies the exclusivity of
such rights. Upon even casual inspection, the "property" label
serves primarily to signify that intellectual property rights are
ownable and transferable.
Nonetheless, classification of intellectual property as
"property" has substantive effect in some contexts. The Fifth
Amendment limitations on takings of private property turn on that
classification. But as reflected in the eBay case, the
"property" label is not determinative of the standard for
injunctive relief.
Unlike Locke's liberty conception of real property, the
principal economic justification for intellectual property derives from
a broader economic problem: the inability of a competitive market to
support an efficient level of innovation in some areas of technological
innovation and creative expression--particularly those in which research
and development (R&D) is Costly, innovation is easily perceived, and
imitation is relatively inexpensive and can occur rapidly. A competitive
economy will drive profits to zero, not accounting for sunk costs such
as R&D. Although imitation keeps prices low for consumers and avoids
deadweight loss of monopolistic exploitation, it produces a suboptimal level of investment in R&D. Most firms would not invest in
developing new technologies and creative works if rivals could enter the
market and dissipate the profit before R&D costs adjusted for
attendant risks could be recovered.
Unlike tangible goods, knowledge and creative works are public
goods in the sense that their use is nonrivalrous. One agent's use
does not limit another agent's use. Indeed, in its natural state,
knowledge is also "nonexcludable." That is, even if someone
claims to own the knowledge, it is difficult to exclude others from
using it. Intellectual property law is an attempt to solve that problem
by legal means; it grants qualified exclusive use of the protected
knowledge or creative work to the creator.
Such control, however, reduces social welfare in several ways.
First, monopoly exploitation results in deadweight loss to consumers.
Second, exclusive control may inhibit the use of scientific or
technological knowledge for further research. Third, from an ex ante
point of view, there is no guarantee that the research effort will be
delegated to the most efficient firms, or even to the right number of
firms.
Patent protection, for example, seeks to balance those competing
effects by affording protection only to substantial (nonobvious)
inventions, limiting the term of protection, and requiring that the
inventor fully disclose the invention. In the most basic model of patent
protection--where inventions do not serve as building blocks for later
inventions and the only control variable is the duration of
protection--the optimal duration of patent protection balances the
incentives for innovation against the deadweight loss of monopoly
exploitation.
Cumulative innovation--where first-generation inventions become
inputs for second-generation innovators--substantially complicates the
design of patent protection. In order to reward first-generation
innovators sufficiently for inventions that may produce positive
spillovers by enabling second-generation inventions (improvements, new
applications, and accessories), first-generation innovators should be
able to appropriate the value of second-generation innovations. On the
other hand, providing even a share of the second-generation
innovators' returns to the first generation innovator reduces the
incentive for second-generation innovators to pursue their research.
This tension is abated to the extent that first-generation innovators
are best positioned to pursue second-generation innovation or where
collaboration (e.g., joint ventures) brings first- and second-generation
innovation within the same profit center.
The cumulative nature of innovation unquestionably strengthens the
case for allowing joint ventures, especially with respect to
complementary products. In practice, however, one entity rarely is best
positioned to pursue all second-generation projects. Furthermore,
second-generation innovators are not known (and cannot be knowable)
before the making of first-generation research investments. Yet, once
first-generation research investments are made, they are sunk costs that
become irrelevant for bargaining over the division of profits from
multi-generation innovation. This problem can be addressed by expanding
the duration and scope of first-generation patents or by denying patent
protection altogether to second-generation innovation. The results,
however, depend critically upon strong assumptions relating to licensing
of innovation and the knowledge and rationality of innovators. In
practice, there are many strategic impediments to licensing. In
addition, innovators rarely possess good information for assessing the
best diffusion path for their technologies and licensing can be costly.
The utilitarian linkage between property and intellectual property
theory hinges upon low transaction costs. Institutional economists see
vibrant competition as a more positive force in spurring invention,
innovation, and diffusion of technology than coordinated development by
a single prospector. For this reason, narrower and weaker rights
structures may be more efficacious in promoting innovation in particular
fields. Even Prof. William Landes and Judge Richard Posner recognize
that "'depropertizing' intellectual property may
sometimes be the soundest policy economically." Professors James
Bessen and Michael Meurer find, for example, that the costs of business
method and software patents (attributable to the inherent ambiguity of
rights boundaries) generally outweigh the relatively modest benefits of
such patents.
STRUCTURAL UNITY OR UTILITARIAN DESIGN
When Professor Epstein looks at intellectual property, he is struck
by the "structural unity" with real property. He sees
exclusivity and the right to transfer as the foundations under-girding
both systems, while discounting the problems of fragmentation and
concentration in both domains. His limited perspective exaggerates the
"unity" of real and intellectual property with regard to
exclusivity and freedom to transfer while overlooking the many
structural differences that distinguish real and intellectual property.
There is little doubt that intellectual property rights can be
exclusive. But they need not be and often are not, at least not to the
extent associated with real property. Exclusivity in the realm of real
property addresses the "tragedy of the commons." Providing
exclusive rights to land and other tangible resources limits the overuse of inherently depletable resources. By contrast, intellectual resources
(knowledge) are not depletable and hence are not subject to overuse
externalities. Treating them as real property can lead to
underutilization. We can all enjoy a Mozart opera without diminishing
the enjoyment of others, whereas we could not all productively graze our
herds on a given acre of land or enjoy a particular chocolate ice cream
cone without adversely affecting the use and enjoyment of others.
Intellectual property protections use the provision of rights (of
varying degrees of exclusivity) to promote technological innovation and
expressive creativity. But as noted earlier, progress in technology and
the arts is a cumulative process in ways that development of land is
not. Intellectual property laws seek to balance the interests of
pioneering innovators and subsequent improvers in the pursuit of
progress.
Exclusive rights of the character associated with real property
would stand in the way of technological and expressive progress in many
areas of creativity. Thus, Congress has not declared the first inventor
the fee-simple absolute owner of his intellectual creativity. To do so
would violate the Constitution's "limited time"
condition. But putting that attenuated constraint aside, Congress has
limited the duration and the rights of intellectual property owners in
significant respects to achieve an appropriate balance between
incentives to create and opportunities for later improvers.
Patent rights tend toward the more exclusive end of the control
spectrum, although the relatively short duration of patent protection
(20 years from the filing of an application) and the ability for
subsequent inventors to patent improvements (although they will need to
license underlying patented inventions in order to practice their
improvements) mitigate such strength. Copyright law takes a more varied
approach to exclusivity. At the most basic level, copyright law allows
independent creation of copyrighted works. The statute includes numerous
exceptions, compulsory licenses, and other limitations on copyright
owners' rights in the service of cumulative creativity and other
social ends. Trademark law goes further yet, allowing a broad range of
uses of valid trademarks by news organizations as well as competitors
(comparative advertising) and parodists. Trade secret law does not
prohibit reverse engineering or independent creation of information
protected as trade secrets.
Courts have long recognized inherent limits on exclusivity of
intellectual property rights. In the early 19th century, Justice Story
wove the doctrines of experimental use and fair use into the patent and
copyright regimes. Jurists since that time have embellished upon those
doctrines in the pursuit of the appropriate balance between protection
and unauthorized use. Thus, it is a substantial exaggeration to suggest
that "exclusivity" of rights in the intellectual property
context mirrors that concept in the real property context.
The transferability of intellectual property rights also diverges
from the real property model in significant respects. The patent and
copyright misuse doctrines, for example, limit the freedom of
intellectual property owners to leverage their rights into other markets
or to inhibit innovation. Trademark law imposes substantial restrictions
on assignment and licensing. Antitrust law plays a much greater role in
policing intellectual property licensing than in real property
transactions.
Beyond exclusivity and transferability, the structures of real and
intellectual property differ markedly along several other critical
dimensions. The PRM generally believes that most, if not all, tangible
resources should be owned. Yet intellectual property law tends to
operate from the opposite default--market failure justifies intellectual
property protection and intellectual property rights should only be
created to the extent needed to override appropriability problems.
Patent law excludes protection for abstract concepts and scientific
principles. Copyright law does not extend to unoriginal compilations,
even when they require substantial effort. Patent and copyright aspire
for knowledge to be unowned--in the public domain--after their term has
expired. The same cannot be said for tangible property systems.
A further structural difference between real and intellectual
property relates to the nature of boundaries and the implications for
transaction costs. Whereas tangible property can usually be defined with
reasonable clarity and can be verified at relatively low cost, various
types of intellectual property--especially software and business method
patents--have notoriously fuzzy boundaries. Such boundary definition
problems, and the due diligence, transaction, and dispute resolution
costs that they entail, raise serious questions about the desirability
of some types of intellectual property.
Real and intellectual property differ significantly in terms of
enforcement costs. Whereas land and other forms of tangible property can
be enclosed and monitored, the flow of knowledge is particularly
difficult to observe. For that reason, trade secrets are notoriously
difficult to protect. Digital technology and the Internet have made the
products of traditional content industries--sound recordings, sheet
music, movies--much more vulnerable to unauthorized distribution.
Professor Epstein's equation of real and intellectual property
skates over those significant differences.
LIBERTARIAN DISCORD
Libertarianism exhibits profound schizophrenia with regard to the
concept of intellectual property. Whereas Professor Epstein sees nearly
every resource--whether tangible or intangible--as property that should
be protected by exclusive rights, many libertarians have serious
reservations about extrapolating property rights in tangible resources
to the realm of intangibles. Friedrich Hayek, perhaps the most
influential libertarian theorist of the 20th century, raised serious
doubts about the equation of tangible and intangible resources. In The
Fatal Conceit, he wrote:
The difference between [copyrights and patents] and other kinds of
property rights is this: while ownership of material goods guides
the use of scarce means to their most important uses, in the case
of immaterial goods such as literary productions and technological
inventions the ability to produce them is also limited, yet once
they have come into existence, they can be indefinitely multiplied
and can be made scarce only by law in order to create an inducement
to produce such ideas. Yet it is not obvious that such forced
scarcity is the most effective way to stimulate the human creative
process.
Along those lines, several libertarian theorists see scarcity, and
not the act of creation, as the fundamental justification for property
rights. They view the recognition of property-type rights in
intellectual creativity as inhibiting the freedom of others to use
tangible resources and to engage in free expression. They worry that
intellectual property impedes the process of creative destruction that
moves society forward.
The concern over such freedom took root within the computer
programming field in the 1980s. Prior to that time, computer programmers
enjoyed largely unfettered freedom to use and adapt computer code.
Competitive pressures, however, led computer vendors to assert greater
control over the use of software. Such restrictions spurred Richard
Stallman, a researcher in the Artificial Intelligence Laboratory at the
Massachusetts Institute of Technology, to develop a technical and legal
strategy aimed at restoring freedom to use and adapt computer code. That
effort grew into the open source movement, a collaborative production
and design framework that eschews proprietary restrictions on
innovation. Over the past decade, a phalanx of
"cyberlibertarians" has questioned the role of intellectual
property in cyberspace.
Thus, libertarians are deeply divided on whether, and in what
circumstances, intellectual property recognition is justified. Professor
Epstein cannot claim the libertarian mantle on such questions.
POLITICAL DIFFERENCES
Stepping away from the above philosophical issues, a number of
interesting political dynamics surround intellectual property and the
PRM. Below are comments on some of those dynamics.
The PRM closely aligns with conservative, anti-government
Republican politicians and political action groups. Intellectual
property owners, by contrast, reflect a much wider range of political
stripes. Information technology companies are relatively agnostic
regarding political allegiance, whereas the pharmaceutical industry has
been more aligned with the Republican Party. Content industries have
long maintained closer ties with Democratic lawmakers and
administrations. Hollywood producers, directors, and actors have
generally favored Democratic politicians and causes--such as the
environmental movement.
The foregoing suggests that the property rights movement and
intellectual property interests are unlikely to build deep or stable
political ties. Although they both see "property rights" as
key to their future, their conceptions differ markedly. The PRM's
absolutist view of property rights contrasts with the much more flexible
and pragmatic needs of a dynamic and effective intellectual property
rights system.
PROTECTION OF REAL PROPERTY
Will trying to expand the "property tent" to include
intellectual property promote the PRM's goals of strengthening
property rights and minimizing government interference with free markets
and individual liberty? Conceiving of intellectual property and real
property in the same frame of reference seems more likely to lead in
exactly the opposite direction from where the PRM seeks to go--that is,
the notion that individual land parcels can be viewed as discrete
islands without any ecological or social interdependency that might
justify governmental intervention. As ecologists and scholars from
Pinchot to Leopold to Sax have emphasized, however, the interdependency
of land and other natural resources cannot be denied and such
interdependency justifies a governmental role in resource policy. The
case for governmental intervention and collective limitations on land
and resource use expands with the pressures of population density and
resource use, collective interests in resource management and
stewardship, and the accretion of scientific knowledge about human
impacts on ecosystems. Bringing intellectual property into the
"property tent" will call attention to the interdependency
conception of resources.
Several characteristics of intellectual resources and the nature of
innovation bear this out. First, the cumulative nature of innovation
means that almost all innovations are linked to other innovations to
some degree. Inventors today "stand on the shoulders of
giants" in pushing the frontiers of science and technology. A
similar phenomenon connects expressive creativity. Authors, artists, and
musicians build on and respond to the creativity of those who came
before. Therefore, intellectual property policy correctly resists the
conception of intellectual resources as discrete and insular.
Intellectual resources are inherently interdependent. In this way,
intellectual resources come closer to the Leopoldian conception of the
land resource as being a web of interrelated elements than it does to
the PRM conception of every parcel as an island. Granting strong,
exclusive rights to inventors and authors rests on unrealistic optimism
about transaction costs. Coasean bargaining is unlikely to provide the
optimal usage and advance of knowledge in all circumstances.
That is not to say that property rights have no role to play in
promoting progress. They play an essential role, but care must be taken
to tailor the scope of protection, rights, and remedies to particular
creative contexts. Dogmatic belief in the most extensive bundle of
property rights overlooks much of the challenge of spurring
technological and expressive creativity.
Second, the optimal system for promoting creativity changes with
society and technology. The optimal system for promoting traditional
pharmaceutical innovation might not be appropriate for genomic research.
Similarly, the appropriate balance for copyright protection in the era
of mechanical reproduction of works of authorship might not be optimal
for the digital age. Further, the digital age will continue to evolve,
requiring adjustments in the intellectual property system. The need for
legal rules and institutions to adapt to such dynamism will push against
the PRM's static conception of property rights. The need to evolve
intellectual property systems could be hampered by an overly restrictive
interpretation of the Takings Clause.
Third, the trend of digital technology toward greater collaborative
creativity and costly enforcement seems unlikely to support traditional
conceptions of ownership and control. A growing number of successful
business models on the Internet downplay proprietary rights and use
ancillary methods for deriving revenue. We increasingly see open source
development of infrastructure, advertising-supported content and
services, and keyword advertising. The debate over "network
neutrality" parallels debates over public provision of highways and
other resources. Because of the inherent nature of network resources,
the PRM will face an increasingly uphill battle trying to colonize cyberspace. Other economic models--such as open source will undoubtedly
play a major role in this domain.
Witness the resolution of eBay v. MercExchange. At oral argument,
the property rights rhetoric seemed to attract the attention of Justice
Scalia:
[W]e're talking about a property right here and the property right
is explicitly the right to exclude others from use of that. That's
what a patent right is. And all he's asking for is give me my
property back.
In the end, however, even the Supreme Court's most stalwart
property rights defenders resisted the effort to pull intellectual
property into the traditional property tent. In a unanimous decision authored by Justice Thomas, the Court ruled that injunctions should not
be presumed in patent cases; rather courts should exercise equitable
discretion in determining relief. Chief Justice Roberts's
concurrence, joined by Justices Scalia and Ginsburg, no doubt gave the
PRM some solace by noting that the "long tradition of equity
practice" of granting injunctive relief in the vast majority of
patent cases upon a finding of infringement reflects "the
difficulty of-protecting a right to exclude through monetary remedies
that allow an infringer to use an invention against the patentee's
wishes." But Justice Kennedy, in a concurrence joined by Justices
Stevens, Sourer, and Breyer, offered a more nuanced and flexible
approach toward the exercise of discretion in enforcing intellectual
property rights by emphasizing the particular characteristics of
business method patents. Only time will tell how strongly intellectual
property rights will be enforced, although early lower court decisions
applying eBay suggest that a shift away from near-automatic issuance
of-injunctions in patent cases is underway.
Thus, the growth of intellectual property seems unlikely to support
the PRM's core agenda. Intellectual property has never fit the real
property mold particularly well and the inherent attributes of
intellectual resources as well as the increasingly interdependent nature
of information ecosystems points away from the PRM's conception of
property. By expanding the property tent to encompass intellectual
property, property rights enthusiasts run the risk of diluting the
distinctive attributes of real property that brought it special
attention at the founding of the nation. Such a conception has been on
the decline and the growing importance of intellectual property seems
likely to hasten that trend. As Justice Benjamin Cardozo remarked in
describing the development of water rights in the American West,
"Here we have the conscious departure from a known rule, and the
deliberate adoption of a new one, in obedience to the promptings of a
social need so obvious and so insistent as to overrun the ancient
channel and cut a new one for itself." The rise of intellectual
property, like water resources, highlights both the complexity and
interdependence of resources in modern societies. Efforts to shoehorn
legal protection for such resources into the real property mold will
undoubtedly fail and may well hasten the demise of the rigid conception
of private property rights in land and other tangible resources.
CONCLUSION
The property rights movement is too limited and grounded in
absolutist ideology to support the needs of a dynamic,
resource-sensitive intellectual property system. It is not particularly
helpful to think of real and intellectual property as "structurally
unified." To the contrary, the landscape of intellectual property
itself is quite variegated. Functionally-oriented property rights
analysis can be useful to legal and policy debates, but property rights
rhetoric is misleading philosophically, historically, and functionally.
Suggesting that "intellectual property" must be treated as
part of a monolithic "property" edifice masks fundamental
differences and distracts attention from critical issues.
Readings
* "Against Intellectual Property," by N. Stephan
Kinsella. Journal of Libertarian Studies, Vol. 15 (2001).
* "Copyright and Incomplete Historiographies: Of Piracy,
Propertization, and Thomas Jefferson," by Justin Hughes. Southern
California Law Review, Vol. 79 (2006).
* "Do Patents Work? The Empirical Evidence that Today's
Patents Fail as Property and Discourage Innovation, and How They Might
Be Fixed," by James Bessen and Michael J. Meurer. Forthcoming,
2008.
* "Intellectual Property as Property: Delineating Entitlements
in Information," by Henry E. Smith. Yale Law Journal, Vol. 116
(2007).
* "Intellectual Property Law," by Peter S. Menell and
Suzanne Scotchmer. In Handbook of Law and Economics, edited by A.
Mitchell Polinsky and Steven Shavell. Amsterdam, NL: Elsevier, 2007.
* "Intellectual Property: Old Boundaries and New
Frontiers," by Richard A. Epstein. Indiana Law Journal, Vol. 76
(2001).
* "Property, Intellectual Property, and Free Riding," by
Mark A. Lemley. Texas Law Review, Vol. 83 (2005).
* The Economic Structure of Intellectual Property Law, by William
M. Landes and Richard A. Posner. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Press, 2003.
* "The Property Rights Movement's Embrace of Intellectual
Property: True Love or Doomed Relationship?" by Peter S. Menell.
Ecology Law Quarterly, Vol. 34 (2007).
* "The Structural Unity of Real and Intellectual
Property," by Richard A. Epstein. The Progress & Freedom
Foundation, Aug. 21, 2006.
BY PETER S. MENELL
University of California, Berkeley School of Law
Peter S. Menell is professor of law at the University of
California, Berkeley School of Law and director of the school's
Berkeley Center for Law and Technology.