Has the pendulum swung too far? Post-Enron responses to possible corporate crime have created a climate of fear for honest corporate officers.
Chang, Howard H. ; Evans, David S.
The prosecution of corporate fraud has garnered increasing
attention in recent years. A number of high-profile cases have captured
headlines, sent the involved firms into death spirals, destroyed the
careers of numerous managers, and sent many executives to jail. Several
firms have jettisoned their CEOs and left dismissed employees to fight
charges for themselves in return for the firms receiving relief from
criminal indictments.
Enron is the poster child. It was Fortune's "Most
Innovative Company in America" six years running. The ingenuity, at
least in its latter years, went largely into massive accounting fraud
that made the company appear far more valuable and its endeavors far
more successful than they were in fact. Thus far, 20 Enron employees
have been sentenced to jail after trials or plea bargains.
The smoke and mirrors were so obvious in hindsight that few doubt
that at least some of those employees were guilty of reprehensible behavior. The bankruptcy proceedings recovered $9.4 billion for a
company that had been worth seven times that shortly before. Thousands
of employees and investors lost their savings. The debacle, and others
that followed including the collapse of the WorldCom house of cards,
made the public more distrustful of the captains of industry and the
books they keep.
When guilt is certain, justice is easy. But prosecutors make
mistakes in bringing cases--sometimes through carelessness, other times
through zealotry--and judges and juries err in finding guilt. Arthur
Andersen, Enron's auditor and accountant, exemplifies the nightmare
with which corporations and executives now live. The U.S. Department of
Justice filed criminal charges against the partnership in March 2002.
The complaint did not claim that Andersen had participated in any
fraudulent activities, but instead that the firm had destroyed documents
relevant to the Enron investigation. The world's largest accounting
firm began collapsing in the wake of the indictment. It was largely
destroyed as a viable business after a jury--originally deadlocked but
requested to reach a decision under an Allen charge--returned a guilty
verdict in June 2002. Its partners lost much of their financial wealth
and the firm itself finally closed its doors in the United States by
August 2002.
The Supreme Court reversed the decision unanimously in June 2005 on
the grounds that the judge's jury instructions enabled the jury to
find guilt on the basis of virtually no culpability on the part of
Arthur Andersen. The government prosecution went overboard to remove all
mental elements from the basic charge, a deviation from basic criminal
law principles that was slapped down by the Supreme Court. One cannot
have too much sympathy for the Andersen partners in charge of
Enron--they missed a massive fraud on their watch. But a corporate death
sentence for what was a highly regarded firm, carried out for all
intents and purposes before its appeals were exhausted, defies bedrock
principles of justice.
Arthur Andersen and Enron are bookends that motivate the thesis we
advance in this article. The pursuit of corporate fraud faces the
classic tradeoff between absolving the guilty and convicting the
innocent. On the one hand, when the judicial process falsely convicts
companies and their executives, it reduces and sometimes destroys the
value of assets ex post. More importantly, it encourages companies and
their executives to behave more conservatively ex ante and thereby
reduces the rate of innovation and dynamic competition. On the other
hand, when the judicial process falsely exonerates companies and their
executives, it not only permits wrongdoing to continue but also tends to
increase the incentives for others to engage in wrongdoing. That imposes
substantial costs on the economy. The judicial process needs to balance
those two sources of errors and their costs.
We argue that the balance struck by the prosecutorial and judicial
system has tipped too far toward pursuing criminal indictments against
companies and their executives. The result is harm to the general
public, whose members depend on a dynamic, competitive economy for their
welfare. As a result, the United States has an increasingly hostile
business environment that is likely reducing valuable risk-taking
behavior and shifting entrepreneurial activity to other countries. In
creating a climate of fear for corporations and their executives, Enron
and WorldCom have, perhaps, imposed more significant costs on the
economy at large than they foisted on their investors.
JUSTICE IS NOT PERFECT
At least since biblical times, the administration of justice has
recognized that perfection is a lark and that one must balance the
benefits of convicting the guilty against the costs of convicting the
innocent. As the Supreme Court put it In Re Winship (1970) confirming a
constitutional right to the "beyond a reasonable doubt"
standard in criminal cases, "There is always in litigation a margin
of error, representing error in fact-finding, which both parties must
take into account. Where one party has at stake an interest of
transcending value--as a criminal defendant his liberty--this margin of
error is reduced as to him by the process of placing on the other party
the burden of ... persuading the fact finder at the conclusion of the
trial of his guilt beyond a reasonable doubt."
Law and economics scholars have formalized the analysis of this
tradeoff with the "error-cost approach" that was pioneered in
writings more than a quarter century ago by Richard Posner and Frank
Easterbrook. The idea is that the legal system should minimize the cost
of errors, which requires accounting for the likelihood of
errors--convicting the innocent and acquitting the guilty--and the cost
of those errors. That analytical framework has been adopted by the
Supreme Court in several key antitrust decisions, including Twombly and
Leegin that were handed down in June 2007, that relaxed antitrust
liability because of the costs of mistakenly condemning efficient
economic activity.
In many corporate fraud cases, errors are quite likely in either
direction. If a case reaches a jury, the complex financial and
accounting issues that are common in corporate fraud cases are likely to
be beyond the ability of jurors to comprehend adequately. Empirical
research demonstrates that jurors have substantial difficulty
understanding economic, financial, accounting, and other complex issues
that are common in corporate fraud allegations. The error rate in such
cases is therefore likely to be high and juror decisions may be based
largely on their perceptions of the defendants.
Systematic studies confirm that our justice system is error-prone
in evaluating guilt or innocence. The largest study was undertaken by
Harry Kalven and Hans Zeisel at the University of Chicago in 1954-1955
and used a sample 3,576 criminal trials presided over by 555 state and
federal judges. The jury agreed with the judge 78 percent of the time
and disagreed 22 percent of the time overall, with roughly the same
rates of disagreement for acquittals and convictions. In more than 20
percent of the cases, either the judge or the jury had it wrong.
Other research has focused on how well jurors understand specific
aspects of a case. To take one example, the Special Committee of the ABA
Litigation Section conducted a detailed case study in four complex cases
to assess jury comprehension. The four cases were tried in federal
district court between 1985 and 1988, with three civil cases involving
employment discrimination, price fixing, and trade secrets, and one
criminal case involving conspiracy to commit insurance fraud. Based on
analysis of videotaped deliberations, the study concludes that
"many jurors were confused, misunderstood the instructions, failed
to recall evidence, and suffered enormously from boredom and
frustration." In three of the four cases, the alternate jury
reached a different verdict from the actual jury, which itself strongly
suggests that juries in complex cases are prone to error.
The error rate for corporate fraud cases is likely to be as high,
and perhaps higher, than the statistics above indicate. Corporate fraud
cases tend to be some of the most complex cases in which intuitive
judgment is the least helpful. They generally involve highly technical
securities and accounting regulations, massive amounts of financial
information, and other technical documents. The inability of jurors to
understand the financial and accounting intricacies in such cases may
lead them to focus instead on irrelevant or tangential matters. The
jurors in the corporate fraud case against HealthSouth CEO Richard M.
Scrushy received a 36-page jury verdict form and 78 pages of instruction
that reportedly confused them. They acquitted Scrushy after deliberating
for 21 days. It was reported that Scrushy benefited from the fact that
he was popular public figure in Birmingham, Ala., and in particular that
he had "a very high reputation in the African-American
community" for his support of African-American churches.
Given the innate complexity of corporate fraud cases and the
general findings of jury research, it is hard to be sanguine about the
reliability of jury verdicts. A survey of recent corporate fraud cases
examined 44 jury decisions at trial. Of those, 18 were convictions, 11
were acquittals, and 15 resulted in hung juries. Thus, 41 percent of the
cases that went to trial resulted in guilty verdicts. There is little
reason to believe that the 18 convicted were all guilty or that the 11
acquitted were all innocent.
PLEA BARGAINING The vast majority of corporate fraud cases are
resolved via plea bargains--jury convictions accounted for less than 10
percent of all convictions. However, the reliability of the judicial
system has a critical effect on the extent to which plea bargains
accurately account for the likelihood of guilt or innocence. When
verdicts are highly uncertain, both sides have an incentive to reduce
their risk by reaching an agreement. However, it appears likely that the
current system encourages false plea bargains by innocent companies and
executives.
In the view of many commentators, the U.S. system of prosecuting
corporate fraud conveys so much power to prosecutors that it has become
like the inquisitorial system common in European countries, but without
the safeguards built into those systems to provide some constraints on
prosecutorial power. The ability of prosecutors to file criminal charges
against a company provides great leverage. Companies are subject to a
variety of state and federal regulations and license requirements that
effectively make it difficult, if not impossible, for them to function
once they have been indicted. Government sanctions can range from
license suspension or revocation to exclusion from participation in
government programs or from bidding on government contracts. For
example, even if Arthur Andersen had survived its felony charge, it
might nonetheless have been prohibited from practicing before the
Securities and Exchange Commission. Also, a pharmaceutical company
indicted on charges of Medicare fraud would not be able to participate
in Medicare or Medicaid. Thus, when a prosecutor threatens to bring a
corporate indictment, the company and its board must choose between
settlement and a corporate death sentence inflicted almost the day the
complaint is filed with the court and long before the justice system can
review the case.
Companies have very strong incentives to reach plea bargains even
if they are innocent and even if they believe they have a significant
chance of prevailing at trial. Their executives can be collateral damage as their directors trade-off their obligations to shareholders to their
obligations to employees. The Justice Department plea bargain with
accountancy KPMG illustrates the problem well. In accordance with the
2003 Thompson memorandum, the Justice Department required KPMG to renege
on its obligation to pay the legal expenses of its employees who were
accused of fraud as part of the plea bargain. Judge Lewis Kaplan
recently dismissed charges against a number of KPMG employees on the
grounds that this infringed their rights to a defense. Then state
attorney general Eliot Spitzer's insistence that companies fire
their chief executives as a condition of entering a plea bargain has
been widely reported.
Corporations and their employees commit fraud. Detecting fraud and
punishing those responsible is important. The problem at the moment is
that the system for accomplishing this is subject to considerable error
and it encourages plea bargains almost regardless of the merit of the
underlying allegation brought by prosecutors.
THE COSTS OF FALSE CONVICTIONS AND PLEA BARGAINS
False convictions can result in innocent executives losing their
wealth, serving jail time, and having their careers ruined. Serious as
those errors are, they are not our focus. Our concern is mainly how the
existence of false convictions--including those reached through plea
bargains--affects the incentives of firms and their executives to engage
in risky but efficient behavior. To begin with, false convictions will
tend to reduce the supply of talent to publicly traded corporations.
Future managers will be more likely to go into fields that have less
litigation risk--particularly when that litigation risk might involve
career destruction and jail time. Existing managers will be more likely
to avoid risky behavior. Perhaps more importantly, they will tend to
divert their energies away from risk-taking entrepreneurial initiatives,
toward regulatory and legal compliance. The effect of those distorted
incentives will be to make publicly traded corporations less effective
and less attractive to potential management candidates.
As we discussed above, there is a considerable danger of
prosecutorial overreach and a significant error rate inherent injury
trials. Given this, company decisionmakers have strong incentives to
avoid any nontrivial risk of prosecution. In the view of many, the
Sarbanes-Oxley Act has exacerbated those incentives by increasing the
risk of criminal prosecution. Forbes quoted the head of the American
Institute of Certified Public Accountants as describing Sarbanes-Oxley
as "the criminalization of risk-taking, which is the same as
criminalizing capitalism.... Executives now face millions of dollars in
fines and 25 years in prison for things as common as estimation errors
and writedowns."
Consider the "special purpose entities" that were behind
the Enron charade. Suppose a company had the opportunity to set up an
entity that would likely be extremely profitable but had some measure of
attendant risk. Suppose further that the company's auditors and
legal counsel advised that they believed that establishing the entity
was appropriate and legal, but that there was no clear authority that
established that with certainty. Would the company's CEO choose to
set up the special purpose entity? Would she trade-off a gain of, say,
10 percent in company profit, with a commensurate or greater gain in her
own compensation, for a risk of going to prison and having her career
effectively ended? There are no hard data to prove it, but we believe
that successful corporate executives are extremely risk averse about any
activities that could result in jail time or the destruction of their
careers. They may be willing to bet some or much of the company, and
much of their own compensation, on developing a new blockbuster product,
but we believe they would be extremely unwilling to risk their personal
liberty.
One of the provisions of Sarbanes-Oxley was to mandate that audit
committees consist exclusively of independent directors. The independent
directors of a company are, by definition, outsiders. In addition, their
primary business and financial interests lie outside the firm. Suppose
they are faced with a choice of(l) a riskier and more profitable path
for the company, but a path where failure could lead to investigations
and prosecution, or (2) a safer but less profitable course of action.
Their aversion to even a small chance at prosecution will provide strong
incentives to choose the less risky option, particularly given the fact
that as outsiders they do not have the same financial stake in the
company's success or profitability. The risks of being a corporate
director will likely also make it more difficult to attract directors
and lead to less effective corporate oversight.
Those costs are hidden, although indirect evidence from some
empirical studies suggest the costs are quite significant. One study by
Ivy Zhang estimated that the U.S. stock market lost $1.4 trillion in
value, which is over 10 percent of annual U.S. GDP, as a result of the
legislative events leading up to the passage of Sarbanes-Oxley. A
ballpark estimate of the implementation costs of Sarbanes-Oxley is
around $100 billion so, assuming the $1.4 trillion figure is correct,
most of the estimated costs are indirect costs from the legislation.
Parts of the indirect costs are the increased cost of false convictions
resulting from Sarbanes-Oxley and the subsequent deterrence of efficient
decisionmaking by corporate executives.
In a 2005 working paper, Daniel Cohen, Aiyesha Dey, and Thomas Lys
considered whether there was a decline in risk-taking behavior following
the passage of Sarbanes-Oxley. The authors relied on two proxies for
risk-taking behavior: research and development expenses and capital
expenditures. They concluded that "subsequent to the passage of
[Sarbanes-Oxley], firms lowered research and development and capital
expenditures" and that "such effects would result in large
changes in firm values."
Another effect of Sarbanes-Oxley has been to affect firms'
decisions on whether to be publicly traded companies in the United
States. If a firm is listed on a foreign stock exchange or is privately
held, then it is outside the reach of Sarbanes-Oxley. The available
evidence suggests that companies have had a greater likelihood of
staying or going private, and of choosing a non-U.S, stock exchange for
an IPO, following Sarbanes-Oxley. This indicates a significant penalty
for firms that are publicly traded on American stock exchanges. If
Sarbanes-Oxley and the accompanying greater likelihood of criminal
prosecution for corporate fraud were helpful for companies in signaling
that their financial disclosures were reliable, then we would see the
opposite effect. Instead, it is likely that the greater compliance costs
of Sarbanes-Oxley and the decreased tolerance for profitable but risky
ventures under Sarbanes-Oxley are substantially detrimental.
THE COSTS OF DIALING BACK
Letting corporate fraud go unchecked would be extremely costly.
Investor confidence in the financial markets is central to the ability
of companies to raise capital and function effectively. Without that
confidence, the economy as a whole is fundamentally undermined. Publicly
traded U.S. companies accounted for over $12 trillion in market
capitalization as of October 12, 2006. Even a small loss in investor
confidence can translate to a very large loss in social welfare.
However, there are a number of reasons to believe that market solutions
are pretty good at limiting corporate misbehavior--the recent spate of
corporate shenanigans notwithstanding--and that heavy-handed regulation
and zealous prosecution are a bit like using an elephant gun to shoot a
tarantula.
Basic market forces provide significant oversight for corporate
fraud. No investor is compelled to buy stock in a public company.
Companies compete with each other to offer an attractive investment
proposition. Along with projected cash flows and business risks,
investors will also assess the accounting practices and the degree of
public disclosure provided by the company. If a company's financial
statements are excessively opaque, investors will be much less inclined
to hold stock in that company. Novice investors have no hope of piercing
the veil of corporate fraud, but stock prices are largely determined by
sophisticated investors who surely do.
Economists have studied the effectiveness of market forces
primarily by examining whether government regulations such as the 1934
Securities Exchange Act had any significant impact. The key studies have
found little evidence that the regulations have been responsible for
increased market efficiency or disclosure of information.
Of course, market forces do not work perfectly--they were in place
when investors were bidding up Enron. But the lessons of Enron and the
other corporate scandals will likely lead investors to be more wary in
the future. There were certainly many warning signs to which investors
could have paid attention. For example, one Fortune article that
preceded the investigation noted that "the company remains largely
impenetrable to outsiders." One stock analyst called Enron a
"big black box" and another noted, "The ability to
develop a somewhat predictable model of this business for the future is
mostly an exercise in futility." Analysts and investors were
willing to give Enron the benefit of the doubt then. In part, that was
because the dot-com bubble allowed excessive valuations for technology
companies that were mostly bad business models but not fraudulent ones.
But just as the market learned from the dot-corn bubble, it has the
capacity to learn from Enron and require more details of companies
promising revolutionary products.
Another benefit of market-based oversight is that it is a much more
sophisticated and flexible instrument for assessing whether companies
are adopting the right degree of financial disclosure. For example,
companies make a trade off when they decide how much information to
provide investors. If they offer too little information, investors
cannot make an informed decision about whether to invest; if they
provide too much information, the firm may reveal its business secrets
to competitors. Enron asserted that its secrecy was needed to preserve
its competitive advantage. The market would likely demand more
disclosure from a future Enron, but market forces will help determine
exactly how much disclosure and of what kind.
The lack of true independence of outside auditors was another issue
in Enron and other corporate fraud cases. Here also, market-based
oversight provides strong incentives for firms to signal the accuracy of
their financial statements by hiring auditors with strong reputations
for independence. Auditors will have a similar incentive to signal that
they are independent by, for example, instituting additional controls to
prevent inaccurate financial statements from being approved. Competition
among auditors will help ensure quality of auditing services demanded by
the market.
Similarly, stock exchanges compete with each other to match up
companies with investors. Each stock exchange sets its own rules on the
type and extent of financial disclosure of companies listed on the
exchange. For instance, the NYSE competes with NASDAQ, the London Stock
Exchange, and Deutsche Bourse, among others, to attract companies and
investors. An exchange will, under competition, respond to market
incentives to provide a signal that the companies trading on the
exchange provide accurate financial statements.
Another form of competition to provide market oversight takes place
among different states within the United States. Companies can
incorporate in any state and can choose the state that provides the most
benefit for those companies. More than 50 percent of all U.S. publicly
traded firms and 60 percent of the Fortune 500 have chosen to
incorporate in Delaware. The Delaware state government touts itself as
business-friendly because of its "modern and flexible corporate
laws, highly-respected Court of Chancery, a business-friendly State
Government, and the customer service oriented Staff of the Delaware
Division of Corporations." As with the stock exchanges, the states
respond to market incentives to provide a signal of accurate financial
statements.
One final and important factor limiting any social harm from false
acquittals and phony plea bargains is the availability of civil
litigation as recourse for investors harmed by corporate fraud. Class
action securities litigation provides a vehicle for investors to recover
damages in the event that a company is found liable for fraud or
misrepresentation. The existence of such litigation, aggressively
pursued, further limits the cost of false acquittals and reduces the
need for criminal prosecution. Of course, there are many commentators
who believe there are socially excessive incentives for class action law
firms to engage in securities fraud litigation. Our analysis of the
likelihood of errors applies to civil litigation as well. However, we
believe that civil litigation is less likely to deter innovative and
risk-taking behavior by corporations and their executives than is
criminal prosecution. Therefore, putting aside the issue of whether we
have the right system in place for civil litigation, it seems desirable
to shift the current balance from criminal to civil.
In their totality, the range of other mechanisms for deterring
corporate fraud would appear to substitute very effectively for any
reduced deterrence from increasing false acquittals. It is true that
reduced investor confidence in general in the stock market can lead to
huge efficiency costs. But it is the very fact that those costs can be
so great that leads to the existence of all the oversight mechanisms
that have arisen. If there is a lot to lose from investors not being
willing to invest in the market, then there are a lot of incentives for
market participants to ensure that investor confidence is enhanced. And,
as we have discussed, while market-based and other oversight mechanisms
are by no means perfect, they are also almost certainly more precise and
less prone to error than deterrence by jury trials for anything beyond
the simplest of corporate fraud cases.
One might still ask why the market-based oversight mechanisms did
not prevent the wave of corporate scandals we have discussed. As we
noted, market forces do not work perfectly. But they do work quite well.
A review of the performance of U.S. corporate governance by Bengt
Holmstrom and Steven Kaplan concludes, "Despite the alleged flaws
in its governance system, the U.S. economy has performed very well, both
on an absolute basis and particularly relative to other countries."
Along with other commentators, they view the recent corporate scandals
as an anomalous period. There is little evidence that the additional
criminalization of corporate behavior provided by Sarbanes-Oxley has
been helpful.
SEEKING THE RIGHT BALANCE
The pendulum has already tipped against prosecutorial zealotry toward corporations in the past few months. Under considerable pressure,
the Justice Department has said it would limit the use of deferred
prosecution agreements--a method of holding the dagger of criminal
indictment over the heads of companies to extract concessions from
them--that was part of the Thompson memorandum. Judge Kaplan has been
especially vocal about prosecutorial overreach in his handling of the
KPMG case. Meanwhile, the aggressive tactics of now-governor Eliot
Spitzer in attacking his political opponents in New York has raised
questions about the heavy-handed methods that brought down many
companies and their executives during his tenure as state attorney
general. And even Governor Spitzer is concerned that excessive corporate
regulation is causing the world's financial center to shift from
Manhattan to London.
Nevertheless, more needs to be done to reduce the threat of
criminal prosecution of companies and their executives.
First, while we would not exclude the possibility of some
exceptions, corporations should not be subject to criminal indictment.
Putting aside issues of due process, criminal indictments essentially
force companies to enter into plea bargains and cease potentially
efficient activities. This process necessarily leads to errors unless
one assumes that prosecutors always get it right. Moreover, the
possibility of this threat provides companies and their executives with
reduced incentives for engaging in risky but innovative and
entrepreneurial behavior. Deferred prosecution agreements should be used
sparingly and conditioned only on the offenses charged.
Second, criminal prosecutions of corporate fraud should be
restricted to simple cases in which it is clear that a certain behavior
is unlawful and the overriding issue is whether that behavior has taken
place. Corporate fraud that involves complex facts and behavior should
not be subject to criminal prosecution. The risk of error by juries and
the incentives for inappropriate plea bargains and the resulting
penalties are too great.
Third, with the exception of simple fraud such as embezzlement,
corporate fraud claims should be heard by judges rather than juries.
(This is a complex constitutional topic but suffice it to say that it is
unsettled whether there could be a "complexity" exception to
the Seventh Amendment, which gives both plaintiffs and defendants rights
to a trial by jury.) Consideration should at least be given to
adjudicating complex corporate fraud before specialized courts or
administrative panels that have the capacity to understand the
accounting and other issues involved.
Fourth, for complex corporate fraud cases, the courts should place
greater scrutiny on prosecutors at all stages of litigation--from motion
to dismiss to summary judgment. As long as we rely on jurors to
adjudicate these cases, the courts should make special effort to
eliminate questionable claims before they get to the jury.
Readings
* "David Pays for Goliath's Mistakes: The Costly Effect
Sarbanes-Oxley Has on Small Companies," by Nathan Wilda. John
Marshall Law Review, Vol. 38 (Winter 2004).
* "Economic Competition Between Professional Bodies: The Case
of Auditing," by Paul V. Dunmore and Haim Falk. American Law and
Economics Review, Vol. 3, No. 2 (2001).
* "Economic Consequences of the Sarbanes-Oxley Act of
2002," by Ivy Xiying Zhang. AEI-Brookings Joint Center Related
Publication 05-07, June 2005.
* "Empowering Investors: A Market Approach to Securities
Regulation," by Roberta Romano. Yale Law Journal, Vol. 107 (1998).
* "Enron's Legacy," by Kathleen F. Brickey. Buffalo
Criminal Law Review, Vol. 8 (2004).
* "In Enron's Wake: Corporate Executives on Trial,"
by Kathleen F. Brickey. Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, Vol.
96, No. 2 (2006).
* "Indicting Corporations Revisited: Lessons of the Arthur
Andersen Prosecution," by Elizabeth K. Ainslie. American Criminal
Law Review, Vol. 43 (2006).
* "Market vs. Regulatory Responses to Corporate Fraud: A
Critique of the Sarbanes Oxley Act of 2002," by Larry E. Ribstein.
Iowa Law Journal of Corporation Law, Vol. 28, No. 1 (2003).
* "Sharing Accounting's Burden: Business Lawyers in
Enron's Dark Shadows," by Lawrence A. Cunningham. The Business
Lawyer, Vol. 57, No. 4 (2002).
* The American jury, by Harry Kalven and Hans Zeisel. Boston,
Mass.: Little, Brown, 1966.
* "The Costs of Being Public After Sarbanes-Oxley: The Irony
of 'Going Private,'" by William J. Carney. Emory Law
Journal, Vol. 55 (2006).
* "The Exchange as Regulator," by Paul G. Mahoney.
University of Virginia Law Review, Vol. 83 (1997).
* "The Sarbanes Oxley Act of 2002: Implications for
Compensation Structure and Risk-Taking Incentives of CEOs," by
Daniel Cohen, Aiyesha Dey, and Thomas Lys. Working paper, July 8, 2005.
* "The State of U.S. Corporate Governance: What's Right
and What's Wrong," by Bengt R. Holmstrom and Steven N. Kaplan.
ECGI-Finance Working Paper No. 23/2003, September 2003.
BY HOWARD H. CHANG
AND
DAVID S. EVANS
University College
Howard H. Chang holds a master's degree in economics from Yale
University. David S. Evans is executive director of the Jevons Institute
for Competition Law and Economics at University College London. He also
is a lecturer at the University of Chicago Law School