Intellectual property and the law of land: a reply to Richard Epstein.
Menell, Peter S.
In his response (pp. 58) to my Fall Regulation article
"Intellectual Property and the Property Rights Movement,"
Professor Richard Epstein misses the gist and key implications of my
essay on the extension of the "property" tent to encompass
intellectual property. His article implies that I lack sympathy for
Susette Kelo's plight, yet my original article is agnostic about
the Supreme Court decision expanding what constitutes the public use
requirement. I merely highlighted the stark difference between the Kelo
case and eBay v. MercExchange. I also did not take issue with the
enforcement of intellectual property laws to combat the threats to
public health posed by counterfeit drugs and surgical devices. Rather I
observed that some property rights activists who seek to enforce those
intellectual property rights uncritically deploy property rhetoric to
advocate their cause. My essay purposefully does not place nearly as
much emphasis on Professor Epstein's 2001 Indiana Law Review
article as he would like--for reasons that will become clear below (but
I did include the article in my "Readings" list). While
attacking points that I did not make, Professor Epstein makes no
reference to the clear target of my essay: the views he espoused in his
2006 Progress & Freedom Foundation paper "The Structural Unity
of Real and Intellectual Property." That same argument, in
advocate's garb, appears in Professor Epstein's recent eBay
brief.
Let us consider the key issues raised by my essay. My central point
is that intellectual property deserves its own edifice. Professor
Epstein's response fully acknowledges that governance of
intellectual property involves a complex public policy balance that
differs in fundamental ways from the realm of real property governance,
hence his opposition to the 1998 copyright term extension and his
thoughtful concerns about the scope of gene patents. He also seems to
acknowledge that the dynamism of technology justifies a more flexible
legal and policy framework--as when he discusses Intel v. Hamidi. Yet he
often contradicts those concerns, reverting to equating cyberspace with
physical space or intangible property with tangible property
There are, to be sure, important similarities between the
governance of intellectual property and real property, just as there are
similarities between the governance of intellectual property and
entitlement programs. But it is better to look to first principles of
economic analysis and to comparative institutional analysis than to
freighted analogies. I believe that the governance of all resources can
usefully be understood within a dynamic, multi-institutional framework
(see the 2002 article that I coauthored in the St. Louis University Law
Review)--but that framework needs to be far richer than the version of
the "land" system that Professor Epstein propounds. (This is
reflected in his directing the Supreme Court to an anachronistic Blackstonian encroachment case in the eBay brief while failing to take
note of more modern and less absolutist good faith improver statutes and
doctrines.) Professor Epstein acknowledged as much in his 2001 article
where he wrote: "The task of analogy becomes still more difficult
when we deal with the law of animals, oil and gas, water rights (which
itself is governed by multiple different regimes), or air rights."
What does he cite in support of this proposition? The 1998 textbook
Property Law and Policy: A Comparative Institutional Perspective that I
co-authored with John P. Dwyer. Epstein concludes by noting that
"we can understand how and why [intellectual property] systems both
follow on, and diverge from, the law of land."
This is the key issue. My essay in the fall issue of Regulation
questioned overreliance on claims of "structural unity"
between real and intellectual property systems--a failing of Professor
Epstein's 2006 Progress & Freedom Foundation paper, not his
2001 law review article. Rather than respond to my criticism of his more
strident 2006 position, Professor Epstein circles back to his earlier,
more balanced view. If he is now saying that his 2006 paper does not
really express his views, then that clarification is worth noting.
Professor Epstein entirely overlooks the more provocative claim in
my essay--that "conceiving of intellectual property and real
property in the same frame of reference seems more likely to lead in
exactly the opposite direction from where the [Property Rights Movement]
seeks to go--that is, the notion that individual land parcels can be
viewed as discrete islands without any ecological or social
interdependency that might justify government intervention."
Professor Epstein apparently finds that characterization a bit harsh
(true--he does see the wisdom in "the relaxation of Blackstone
rules with respect to overflight rights or electromagnetic
transmissions" and necessity), but his writings and advocacy on
takings jurisprudence as well as his broad brush approach to remedies in
eBay do stress a particularly strong form of exclusivity and freedom of
property owners from governmental regulation and exercise of discretion.
I suggest that the dynamic aspects of technology and hence technology
policy (including copyright protection as distribution platforms evolve)
will push toward flexibility in rights structures that Professor Epstein
has consistently and emphatically resisted. I suggest that
"[e]fforts to shoehorn legal protection for [intellectual property]
resources into the real property mold will undoubtedly fail and may well
hasten the demise of the rigid conception of private property rights in
land and other tangible resources." The Supreme Court's
decision in eBay bears out at least part of that conjecture.
Professor Epstein invites me to say a bit more about the substance
of the issues raised by the eBay case. Citing Hume, he sees security of
expectations in voluntary transactions as the overriding principle for
thinking about patent remedies. Like many observers of the patent system
over the past decade, I am struck by the unprecedented expansion in
patentable subject matter, the inherent problems of evaluating novelty
and non-obviousness in the software and business method fields, the
quality control problems of the Patent Office, the fuzzy boundaries
surrounding many patents (compare the metes and bounds of a real
property deed to the ambiguous phrasing of many software patent claims),
the strategic use of patent litigation to derail or hold up new
ventures, and the great uncertainty wrought by a system in which
competitors might not learn about patents until after they have invested
millions. All those problems are exacerbated by patent law treating all
inventions the same--everything from costly, time-consuming, and
unpredictable pharmaceutical breakthroughs to prosaic business methods
that can be hatched over a casual lunch with claims drafted by
dinnertime.
Consider Research in Motion's security of investment in its
independently developed Blackberry technology when a questionable patent
for wireless e-mail emerged and the non-practicing entity threatened to
enjoin the vast enterprise. Had the district court taken a more flexible
approach to remedies, there may have been an opportunity for the
reexamination of the patent by the Patent Office to go forward. Instead,
Research in Motion, facing a devastating loss from injunctive relief,
settled the case for $612.5 million.
Just as Professor Epstein praises water law for adjusting property
rights to fit better the nature of the underlying resources, he should
agree that the overly uniform structure of patent law across all
innovation may be a significant problem. The remedy lever, appropriately
developed through judicial fact-finding and the evolution of
context-specific standards, can foster more appropriate incentives
(calibrating rewards with creativity) without sacrificing the security
of appropriate expectations. As I have suggested elsewhere (see my
recent article in the Michigan Telecommunications and Technology Law
Review), more fundamental adjustments to the patent system are called
for to distinguish among the very different fields of inventive activity
covered by patent law. But given the various political and other
impediments to such a direct cure to the patent system's root ills,
more flexibility at the remedy stage looks to be a good utilitarian
compromise. I doubt that courts will stand in the way of practicing or
licensing patent holders enjoining infringers except in extraordinary
circumstances (such as where de facto industry standards or antitrust
concerns are present). The distinct possibility that non-practicing
patent holders will be limited to a "reasonable royalty" (and
if the current reform legislation passes, based only on their
contribution to the market value over the prior art and the
product's other features--and not the product's entire market
value unless the patent's contribution is the "predominant
basis" for market demand for the product) rather than a rigid
hold-up right seems to me a step in the right direction.
Readings
* "A Method for Reforming the Patent System," by Peter S.
Menell. Michigan Telecommunications and Technology Law Review, Vol. 13
(2007).
* "Intellectual Property and the Property Rights
Movement," by Peter S. Menell. Regulation, Vol. 30, No. 3 (Fall
2007).
* "Intellectual Property: Old Boundaries and New
Frontiers," by Richard A. Epstein. Indiana Law Journal, Vol. 76
(2001).
* "Reunifying Property," by Peter S. Menell and John P.
Dwyer. St. Louis University Law Review, Vol. 46 (2002).
* "The Structural Unity of Real and Intellectual
Property," by Richard A. Epstein. The Progress & Freedom
Foundation, Aug. 21, 2006.
Peter S. Menell is professor of law at the University of
California, Berkeley School of Law and director of the school's
Berkeley Center for Law and Technology.