What is a life worth? Despite its prima facie callousness, determining the value of a human life is necessary for good public policy.
Brannon, Ike
AN UNPLEASANT BUT NECESSARY JOB of policymakers is to place a value
on saving a human life. Because society has limited resources that it
can spend on health and safety improvements, it should obtain the
greatest benefit for each dollar spent, and ascertaining an appropriate
value is necessary to that effort. As one would expect, the correct
numerical value to place on a life, typically called the value of a
statistical life, or VSL, is a matter of great controversy.
Hundreds of analyses using widely varying methodologies have been
conducted to determine this value. Despite their differences, most of
the studies center on one basic idea: The VSL should roughly correspond
to the value that people place on their lives in their private
decisions. Though most people may say they will spare no expense to
avoid a possibly fatal risk, their spending patterns dictate otherwise;
we do not all drive armored trucks to work, but instead drive somewhat
less safe--and considerably less expensive--cars. Our willingness to
accept some risk in exchange for a more easily affordable vehicle
suggests there is some limit to how much we will spend to protect our
lives.
This article will examine how economists assign a number to the
value of a statistical life, and will consider criticisms of both their
methodologies and the very concept of a VSL.
DIFFERENT METHODS
Economists and other researchers have used a variety of analyses to
determine the value of a statistical life. Below are some of the most
common methods, along with some problems frequently ascribed to them.
REVEALED PREFERENCES METHOD Two jobs can differ in any number of
ways: One can be in a nicer city, or it can be in a more pleasant
working environment, or it can have better fringe benefits, or it can
offer better opportunities for advancement than the other job. Or, it
can be safer. To estimate the value of a statistical life, economists
can exploit the difference in pay between two jobs and determine how
much of that difference stems from the difference in the risk of injury
or death. Then, the researchers simply multiply that number by the
inverse of the risk difference and call the result the value of a
statistical life.
For example, if I make $40,000 and my twin brother makes $42,000 at
a job that is identical to mine in all respects except for a 1 percent
greater chance of death, then an economist assumes that the $2,000
difference is a premium my twin brother requires to accept the riskier
job. If he requires $2,000 for a 1 percent greater risk, then I can
infer that he is placing a value on his life of $2,000 x (1/0.01), or
$200,000.
There are problems with this approach. University of Wyoming professors Jason Shogren and Tommy Stamland argue that nearly all
revealed preference studies are biased upwards to some degree. They
observe that the wage at a particular job is just enough to entice the
marginal worker. The other workers require less money to accept the
risk. Thus, the "average" VSL is well below the
"marginal" VSL obtained with this method.
Another problem is the need to decide the relevant time period over
which fatality rates should be measured when assessing risk. Should we
use the actual death rate for an occupation over the previous year or
the previous five years? Death rates fluctuate quite a bit from year to
year (think about the death rate for commercial pilots in 2001 as
compared to 2000), and this choice can crucially affect the estimated
VSL. Also, do we use the actual death rates or the workers'
perceived chances of death? After all, wage premiums are presumably based on perceived risk, not actual risk, and the two can diverge.
Another consideration is that most occupations do not really carry
a risk associated with work. Should we include those occupations as well
in our economy-wide estimate of a risk premium? And is it all right to
assume that we can merely multiply the risk premium by the inverse of
the risk assumed? Economists who have studied this issue in depth have
found that if the risk doubles, the risk premium does not necessarily
double. Alan Krupnick of Resources for the Future shows that in most
instances the VSL imputed from comparing the difference in wages
associated with a 0.1 percent to a 0.6 percent risk would be higher than
the VSL imputed from comparing the wage differences between a 1.1
percent and 1.6 percent risk. This non-linearity in our valuation of
risk reduction may simply be the result of sorting--those people facing
higher risks in their job do not require the same amount of money to
assume an incrementally higher level of risk. The fact that we see
evidence of the same phenomenon when we calculate a VSL using the
contingent valuation approach (described below) leads some to theorize that it may be more complicated than mere sorting.
Researchers who estimate a VSL using the revealed preference method
have come up with a wide range of values, from roughly zero (or even
negative) to over $100 million.
CONTINGENT VALUATION METHOD Economists also estimate the value
people place on their lives by just asking them. Of course, this
approach is a little bit more sophisticated than that because the likely
answer to the question, "How much money would you need to allow us
to kill you?" would be an infinite amount of money. In a contingent
valuation estimation of the value of a statistical life, the economist
surveys a number of people and asks each person the amount of money that
he would require to accept a marginally higher chance of dying in the
near future. Generally, the subject answers yes or no to a series of
questions; for example, the opening question might be, "Would you
accept $1,000 to move from a one in 10,000 chance of death to a five in
10,000 chance of death?" If the answer is yes, then the next
question might be whether the person would accept $800 to assume the
higher risk, and so on until the person says he would refuse the money
for the risk. After surveying a few hundred people in this manner, the
researcher imputes the implicit value that each subject places on the
value of a life, as is done in the revealed preference method
(multiplying the final dollar figure by the inverse of the additional
risk taken) and averages the valuations.
Of course, problems exist in this approach as well. First, many
economists dislike it because of its subjectivity. All of the questions
are hypothetical, so why should the answers given by the subjects
actually reflect the tradeoffs that they are willing to make? Indeed, a
problem endemic to such studies is the so-called "protest"
vote in which someone insists that no amount of money would entice him
to accept a higher risk. If the project consisted of 100 subjects and
one person insisted his life is worth $100 billion, should it be
included in the final average? Should researchers throw out that
observation, or truncate the sample, or use a median rather than a mean
to dampen the rogue subject's response? On this matter, there is no
consensus other than that the high value should not remain in the
estimate.
Critics also question whether people accurately perceive the actual
changes in the small differences presented to them in the surveys. A
majority of people suffer from innumeracy and have trouble
distinguishing a three in 10,000 risk from a seven in 10,000 risk. For
those people (and maybe the rest of us as well), their answers are
little more than guesswork. Should we include their answers? Would an
estimate of VSL be reflective of society if the mathematically
challenged were not included?
CONSUMER MARKET BEHAVIOR METHOD A small literature has developed in
recent years that infers our implicit valuation of life from our product
choices rather than our labor-market choices. For example, we know that
antilock brakes reduce the incidence of crashes and death. If we can say
for certain that buying a car with that option reduces the probability
of death by one in 100,000 and the option costs $300, then we can infer
that the person is placing an implicit valuation on his life of at least
$300 x 100,000, or $30 million.
Again, there are many criticisms of this approach. People purchase
thousands of devices that improve safety to some degree. If the VSL
estimated from, say, buying a bicycle helmet is vastly different than
the VSL derived from the decision on whether to buy antilock brakes,
then how can we interpret those numbers?
Another question is whether we separate safety characteristics from
other product attributes. A bicycle helmet that costs $80 and is
slightly safer than a $40 helmet may also be more comfortable, more
stylish, or available at a store closer to the consumer's house.
How are we to determine the extent to which the buyer's decision
was influenced by safety considerations?
Many of the criticisms of the revealed preference studies also can
be made here. Do consumers accurately perceive the safety improvements
inherent in a purchase? Is it sensible to compare VSLs obtained from
different products that have different levels of risk reduction?
META-ANALYSIS METHOD Enough studies have been done that a number of
meta-analyses have been performed on the existing studies in order to
find some "representative" value of a statistical life.
Meta-analyses can vary wildly in sophistication; the basic difference
between a meta-analysis and a simple averaging of a range of studies is
that the meta-analysis attempts to control or adjust for the exogenous factors that could potentially affect the estimated VSL. For example,
from revealed preference studies we know that the extent of the assumed
risk affects the resultant VSL. A typical worker who assumes a one in
1,000 chance of death on a job has a lower VSL than an identical worker
with a one in 10,000 chance of death. A sophisticated statistical
meta-analysis can take into account the relative differences in risk
assumed in different studies and "wash out" the effects of
those differences on the final VSL.
Meta-analysis may seem like a good tool to establish a consensus,
but in reality it is very difficult to perform well. For starters, a
meta-analysis can only be done on similar studies that employ the same
statistical estimation technique; a revealed preference study cannot be
in a meta-analysis with a contingent valuation study. In addition, if
studies within a particular method differ greatly in their approaches,
it may not be possible to combine all reputable studies using the same
method in a single meta-analysis.
FORENSIC ECONOMICS METHOD When estimating the value of a
statistical life for regulatory purposes, economists are most
comfortable with calculating a number that is the by-product of
decisions that people make every day that manifest their willingness to
pay for increased safety. Outside of the realm of regulation, economists
often place a value on a life after a tragic death has resulted in the
loss of future income to a household. For such matters, the procedure of
calculating the value of a lost life is fairly straightforward: The
economist calculates the present value of the future stream of income
that would have accrued to the decedent, adjusted for taxes,
consumption, and the cost of living for his community.
This approach may seem straightforward, but it is dependent on a
number of contestable assumptions. For example, what assumptions should
be made about lifetime income growth and retirement age for the
deceased? Is it correct to use population averages or should we consider
certain factors that might have influenced income growth and retirement
age, such as education or the age of children of the deceased? As anyone
who followed the travails of the special administrator of the
government's official 9/11 survivors fund can attest, this approach
can invite any number of controversies and is far from providing a value
for a life that is free from criticism.
QALY AND VSLY A common critique of the role of VSL in regulatory
analysis is that it fails to distinguish between the life saved of
someone young as opposed to someone close to the end of a life. For
instance, many would argue quite sensibly that a society should be
willing to pay more for a regulation that saves the lives of 10 young
children than for one that saves the lives of 10 senior citizens.
There are two variants of the VSL that make such adjustments: the
quality-adjusted life-year (QALY) and the value of a statistical
life-year (VSLY). Both attempt to calculate the value of one additional
year of life saved, with the former adjusting for the quality as well as
the amount of life saved, and the latter adjusting the value of a
life-year saved by discounting life-years saved in the future, as is
commonly done in finance. Both approaches seem intuitively more
appealing to many policymakers than VSL calculations. John Graham, the
administrator of the Office of Information and Regulatory Affairs, has
expressed a preference for using such measures to complement or even
replace the VSL when performing cost-benefit analysis.
Both the QALY and the VSLY are fundamentally different than the
VSL. The VSL is in essence a metric derived from decisions made by
people either directly in a survey or observed indirectly in their
market choices. Its use in cost-benefit analysis makes perfect sense.
Neither the VSLY nor the QALY are calculated in that way--no one is
observing the behavior of anyone when arriving at this metric. They are
applicable only in the context of cost-effectiveness analysis, where the
researcher is merely trying to rank a number of different policies or
treatments. For instance, if researchers are trying to decide which of a
number of different medical procedures should be done, they may decide
that the hospital feels that only procedures that cost less than
$100,000 per year of life saved, or QALY saved, make sense.
Thus, if a hospital performs a bone marrow transplant that prolongs
the life of a patient by one year, and analysts estimate that the
patient is at 80 percent of his previous life quality for the remaining
year, then they would conclude that 0.8 of a life year was saved. If the
procedure costs less than $80,000, then they would conclude that it was
cost effective under the $100,000 rule (which, incidentally, is a rule
of thumb that quite a few hospitals have been known to use).
In the case of a VSLY, let us assume that we have a regulation that
prolongs the life of a young person by two years, on average, at the end
of his life, as might be the case with bans on smoking inside of
restaurants. It is not appropriate to compare that regulation to a
regulation that prolongs the life of a person by one year today. The
VSLY requires the regulator to discount the two years saved 50 years
down the road so as to fairly compare it to the life-year saved today.
In this case, using a seven percent discount rate (to reflect the cost
of capital) we would find that the life-years saved 50 years down the
road are only worth 0.07 of a life-year saved now, just as two $1 bills
received 50 and 51 years in the future would only be worth seven cents
to someone today.
IS THERE A CONSENSUS?
While the estimated VSLs vary wildly between studies, a broad
consensus is beginning to coalesce around a fairly narrow range of
values, thanks to a number of very influential studies.
Economists Janusz Mrozek and Laura Taylor published a meta-analysis
of a large number of revealed preference studies that was almost
universally praised by researchers in the field for its thoroughness and
inclusiveness. After controlling for all possible factors that could
bias or influence the VSL, they estimated a number between $2 million
and $3 million.
More recently, Kip Viscusi of Harvard, in his own meta-analysis,
concluded that the number was closer to $7 million. Viscusi is one of
the leading authorities in the field as the editor of the Journal of
Risk and Uncertainty, the preeminent journal in risk analysis, as well
as the author of numerous books and articles on risk analysis. Given his
stature, this paper has been taken very seriously by regulators. But
Viscusi analyzes occupational deaths not by occupation but by industry.
That distinction is important; grouping workers by industry essentially
treats the risks faced by secretaries that work for a mining company
identical to the risks faced by miners, a result that obscures the true
risk premium received by workers. There is not necessarily any
systematic bias in his analysis as a result, but the studies he
considers generally have higher standard errors.
On the contingent valuation front, Alan Krupnick, Maureen Cropper,
and a number of economists affiliated with Resources for the Future
conducted a series of sophisticated surveys in the United States,
Canada, and Asia that received kudos from other researchers for
sophistication and rigor. The resulting series of papers, which have
just begun to be published, conclude with a number surprisingly close to
the Mrozek and Taylor value, with a range of between $2 million and $3
million.
A paper by John Leeth of Bentley University and John Ruser of the
Department of Commerce may prove to be the last word when it comes to
revealed preference studies. They obtained an incredibly complete and
disaggregated data set on death and injury rates broken down by
occupation, as well as a complementary data set with wage and employment
data for the same disaggregated occupations. Leeth and Ruser estimate a
VSL in the range of $2.6 to $4.7 million.
WHAT ARE THE FEDS USING?
Scholars have spent many years researching and arguing about the
correct approach to determining the value of a statistical life, and the
field
is only now beginning to gravitate toward a fairly narrow range of
numbers. But the federal government has been doing cost-benefit analyses
of various regulations for decades and, as a necessary component of
those analyses, has assumed different values in order to compare costs
to benefits. So what values do the reds use?
The Department of Transportation uses a figure of $3 million, which
it left unchanged after a 2002 review of the literature. Transportation
officials cited the Mrozek and Taylor research as a significant
influence of its decision.
The Environmental Protection Agency currently uses a mean value of
$6.3 million for its cost-benefit analysis, with an interval between $1
million and $10 million. While some degree of flexibility is to be
applauded (as I will explain below), in reality every regulation issued
by the EPA that spent less than $8 million to save a life has been
approved. The EPA commissioned a large number of studies on the matter a
few years ago, in an effort to establish a reliable, uncontroversial
number to use in its analyses. Unfortunately, that work has led to
nothing of the sort.
Having different agencies use different valuations may seem
illogical, but there is a hint of logic in this. Cass Sunstein of the
University of Chicago has argued that people place different values on
avoiding different types of risks--for instance, people fear dying of
AIDS or in a plane wreck much more than dying in an automobile accident.
Hence, it may make some sense for different authorities to apply
different VSLs to different risks.
CONCLUSION
It is not uncommon for well-meaning people to object strenuously to
placing a value on a human life, judging such a practice to be callous
and demeaning of the value of existence. Is not every life worth an
infinite value to the person living it? Lisa Heinzerling, a Georgetown
University professor and the co-author of a book critical of the use of
VSL, claims that the difficulty in estimating such an amorphous entity
as the value of a statistical life leaves policymakers in the position
of being easily manipulated by the wonks who attempt to estimate VSLs in
the first place. It would be much better, she argues, to have
"informed public debate drawing on moral, philosophical, and
societal considerations beyond market-based assessments."
While more informed debate on regulatory matters might make sense,
it is also necessary to realize that society cannot spend an infinite
amount of money to protect and extend each person's life, and some
choices have to be made in the realm of health and safety regulation. We
have to decide to what extent we are willing to expend resources to
prevent unnecessary death rather than improve education, increase
handicap access, or ensure a cleaner environment. To resist placing a
dollar value on a statistical life is to abdicate any sense of rational
decision-making in the regulatory realm.
READINGS
* "Age, Health and the Willingness to Pay for Mortality Risk
Reductions: A Contingent Valuation Survey of Ontario Residents," by
Alan Krupnick, Maureen Cropper, Anna Alberini, Nathalie Simon, Bernie
O'Brien, and Ronald Goeree. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, Vol.
24, No. 22 (March 2002).
* "Are Poor People Worth Less than Rich People? Disaggregating
the Value of Statistical Lives," by Cass Sunstein. AEI-Brookings
Joint Center for Regulatory Studies Paper 04-05, 2004.
* "Compensating Wage Differentials for Fatal and Non-Fatal
Injury Risk by Race and Gender," by John D. Leeth and John Ruser.
Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, Vol. 27, No. 3 (December 2003).
* Priceless: On Knowing the Price of Everything and the Value of
Nothing, by Lisa Heinzerling and Frank Ackerman. New York, N.Y.: The New
Press, 2004.
* "A Review of the Record," by John F. Morrall III
Regulation Vol. 10, No. 5 (November/December 1986).
* "Skills and the Value of Life," by Jason Shogren and
Tommy Stamland. Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 110 (2001).
* "Value of Risk Reduction Implied by Motorist Use of
Protection Equipment: New Evidence from Different Populations," by
Glenn Bloomquist, Ted R. Miller and David Levy. Journal of Transport
Economics and Policy, Vol. 30, No. 1 (January 1966).
* "The Value of a Statistical Life: A Critical Review of
Market Estimates throughout the World," by Kip Viscusi and Joseph
E. Aldy. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, Vol. 27, No. 1 (2003).
* "What Determines the Value of a Life? A Meta-Analysis,"
by Laura Taylor and Janus Mozrek. Journal of Policy Analysis and
Management, Vol. 21, No. 2 (2002).
Ike Brannon is an economist who works for the U.S. Congress.