Another country.
Cooke, Bryan
The past is a foreign country; they do things differently there. L
P Hartley, The Go-Between. (1)
At first glance, this quotation has the rather mothballed dignity
of a platitude. Who, after all, needs to be told that the past is
distinct from the present--a distinction without which enquiring into
history would be like trying to learn a language that we already knew?
But Hartley's statement expresses a thought that only time,
carelessness and a forgetting of context has let ossify into a cliche.
(2) In order to retrieve this thought, we should try to think about what
these words entail: the past as another country in the way America is
another country for Henry James' Europeans, as Arabia (a dream
country, a hope of a country) is for T E Lawrence and the Arab Revolt,
the way East and West Berlin are other countries in John Le Carre's
Cold War novels.
But does anybody actually relate to the past as they would to
another country--as we might treat that place over the waters where they
speak and rejoice, complain and give thanks in idioms that appear at
once familiar and unfathomable? Can the past be another country in which
we might seek out an epiphany or a tan; a modicum of pre-lapsarian
vitality or an alternative way of symbolising the fundamental
experiences of humanity? Do we really treat the shifting moments in the
history of ideas in a manner that a prevalent travellers' ethos
suggests that we should, i.e. as a place where we go (with a degree of
respect if not wonder) to learn another language, as a doorway to
another way of life?
In what follows I would like to show how thinking about some of the
different attitudes to the two different kinds of
'countries'--those from which we are separated by space and
those from which we are divided by time--can illuminate some of the
assumptions that underlie many debates about the role of history in
education. Comparing different modern attitudes to history and travel, I
will discuss the question of why we might teach history in the first
place, and why we might think it worthwhile to do so. In addition, I
will use this comparison to try to show how attempts to ensure that
teaching achieves certain outcomes (almost irrespective of what those
outcomes are) can ironically end up preventing students from having any
real encounter with the past, by imposing a kind of prophylactic between
them and the historical material upon which they are supposed to be
reflecting. In referring to a 'real encounter' I am not
naively suggesting that the goal of history should be historical
simulations of sufficient verisimilitude to fool a real Cathar or an
actual Victorian chimney-sweep. (3) The only necessary (although
obviously not sufficient) condition for such an encounter to take place
is that any confrontation with historical materials is not totally
subordinated in advance to the function of flattering one of the
prevailing ideologies of the age. Such flattery can be directed at any
number of contemporary prejudices, the prejudices of the ostensible left
as much as the putative right; the vanity of the students as much as the
designers of curricula. But history cannot, I argue, be history without
entailing a risk--which can never be completely eliminated without
turning teaching into 'management', as the corporate world
uses the term. Such a replacement would itself be an unfortunate step
towards the substitution of democratic and humanistic ideals for
technocratic/managerial ones; a process that may be going a little too
smoothly of its own accord without making peremptory concessions.
Why teach history? The problem with the question is that it seems
to fish for answers which are more edifying than explanatory. In what
follows, however, I shall try to limit my answers to the latter mode.
First, one of the most prominent reasons given for teaching history
is that history is a kind of anthropological constant for which our
current pedagogical approaches simply provide a contemporary outlet. All
human societies have told stories about the past, often in the form of
myths that invoke a distant or even 'immemorial' time. These
stories, conceived functionally, play an integral role in making sense
of the world of the storytellers and their audience. The stories
(histoira) and myths thus become part of the world's fabric--a
frame for reality that is at the same time a part of the landscape and
the action. (4)
Second, there is the idea that we can, in fact, learn something
from history; an idea that has sometimes involved the postulation of a
kind of interpretative key through which one could separate the lessons
of history from the mass of mere detail, but that has its least
extravagant and most pithy expression in the saying 'those who
forget the past are doomed to repeat it'. However, the idea that we
can actually learn something from history has been considered risible as
often as it has been considered respectable. (5)
Third, history has, in the last few centuries, frequently been
considered an indispensable and even defining part of 'civic
education'--which in itself is an ambiguous concept. The
ambiguities stem from the fact that it is impossible to define it
without giving an indication of the kind of society in which the person
giving the definition lives. The 'civic' in civic education
means education pertaining to the 'city' (Latin: civitas). It
harks back to a time when the city was the basic political unit (Greek
polis, also city); in the way that makes the Peloponnesian War, at its
heart, a tale of two cities. Civic education, then, would be that which
teaches us to be a citizen, which readies us for public life or, more
broadly, the life in common. (6) But the idea of civic education carries
two fundamental ambiguities even in its name. First, by 'civic
education' do we refer to education for the city, or by the city?
Second (and I mean to use this loosely so that it applies to secular
contexts as much as religious ones), to 'the city of Man' or
the 'city of God'?
In common usage, civic education means education for the
'city'. It is that aspect of education through which we become
citizens: who can, at least in some minimal sense, act for the good and
discharge our duties to the city, nation, 'society' or
community. These duties can require anything from a total subsumption of
the whole of one's life as in a totalitarian society) to the
simultaneously nugatory and subtly strenuous requirements of our own
liberal-democratic/capitalist consumerist societies. (7)
But we can also read 'civic education' as education
'by the city': that which we learn by immersion within a
political community, whether this is a deliberate component of formal
education or otherwise. (8) This brings the idea of civic education
closer to the sense of--to use a modern idiom--socialisation. Thus de
Tocqueville talks constantly about 'democratic mores', and
means by this the kind of attitudes that prevail in the citizens of a
democracy simply qua democracy. (9) This sense of 'civic
education' does not suggest the existence of mass-conformity
allowing as it does for civic dissension, dissidence and deviance), only
of there existing a 'spirit of the laws' (Montesquieu) against
which conformity or non-conformity is to be judged. Hence there is still
something that, say, all 20th-century Americans have in common, despite
their divisions along lines of class, ideology, life-experience and
opportunity. And this common substance is something that these Americans
do not share with Socrates, but which he shares even with those of his
fellow Athenians with whom he has least in common. This
'in-common' is the result of education by 'the
city'--the imprint, in the words of Cornelius Castoriadis, of the
two different 'social imaginaries'. (10)
The extent to which formal education overlaps with 'education
by the city' is a subject of contention. Thus, we can imagine
people alternately rejoicing or deploring the extent to which our
present system of formal (primary and secondary) education is given over
to making sure adolescents 'get along well with their peers'
as a fons et origio of their 'getting on in the world'. At the
same time we can imagine parents who want precisely for schools to be
refuges from whatever vices or stupidities they perceive as reigning
'out there' in the world, such that formal education can be
seen as existing to offset education 'by the city' as much as
to complete it.
One of the rare points of agreement for educational doctrines in
current, liberal democratic society is that a society that rendered
education indistinguishable from 'civic' education (as this
would have been in, for instance, ancient Sparta) (11) would be
undesirable because it would constitute a totalitarian nightmare. Thus,
even those who vociferously argue that education should be principally
directed towards the 'public interest', or who would demand an
avowedly nationalistic/ socialist/'green' or neo-liberal
centre to the curriculum would surely shudder at the thought that their
children would learn 'liberal democratic' mathematics, or
'capitalist metaphysics' insofar as this could not help but
recall such monstrosities as 'Soviet biology', 'Aryan
physics' or 'The History of the World according to National
Socialism'.
The consensus, therefore, holds that some aspects of education are
fields in themselves which can only be brought into conformity with
'civic responsibilities' (or any values beyond those imminent
to the field) by fortunate accident or by predetermining their content
in
a way that is incommensurable with their freedom. At least, this is
virtually undisputed in the case of the natural sciences. (12) The case
of the humanities (including history) is more complicated and of course
more controversial. Here again no one contests that education would be
travestied if it became nothing more than a conduit for certain
'values' or ideals. Were this to happen, education would
become, simply, propaganda. At the same time, we often hear people
arguing that because there is no such thing as a neutral or
disinterested scholarship, the partisans of different visions of a just
society must fight to make sure that their interpretation will reign in
pedagogical practice, because it is inevitable--in an axiological jungle--that some interpretation or set of 'values' will
dominate the curriculum. This attitude then says: 'either we
dominate the curriculum or the other side will, so we had best get
moving.'
But if it is legitimate to suspect that claims to universality and
objectivity may serve as a mask for particular interests, it is surely
just as legitimate to suspect that denials of universality or
objectivity may exist simply to excuse irrational partisanship by
inuring it from rational criticism or reflection. If I proclaim that all
courts are corrupt I may be empirically correct, but I have also
conveniently excused myself from having to submit to judicial
proceedings whose findings may not be in my favour. Between one horn of
this dilemma and the next we therefore encounter the issue of how
education in the humanities can retain (and be considered in terms of)
its explicitly 'civic' dimension (say, by showing some obvious
connection to the 'pressing concerns of the present age'),
without being obliterated by its reduction to such a function.
Insofar as most modern educational ideas are a kind of palimpsest of older ones, it should not be surprising that some of the most
important and persistent concepts of education are variants of the idea
of education as cultivation or Bildung. (13) These concepts still inform
contemporary ideas of education despite the fact that the worldview (and
specifically the vision of the cosmos from which they emerged and in
which they made sense) has been subsequently disavowed. By this loose
sense of an idea of Bildung, I mean anything that sees the educational
process as geared towards the formation of 'character', even
if this is now looked at as something like the realisation or
development of the 'personality'. The common thread of all
these visions of education is that the goal (whether it is autonomy,
virtue or self-realisation) is to be achieved through a process of
habituation that is less like an imposition or a moulding and more
like--to use the traditional metaphor--exposing a plant to the sunlight
that it requires in order to flourish. One way to see this, which is
closest to its roots in Aristotle's concept of paideia, is to see
the process of education as drawing out a nature that flourishes under
the right conditions, but that atrophies in their absence.
The use of a teleological concept of 'nature' (of nature
having a fundamental purpose) is almost always rejected in modern
educational theory as the relic of an outmoded metaphysics. (14) But an
almost equivalent conception can still persist under the auspices of
developmental (or dynamic) theories of the psyche, the body or the self.
It is here that the issue of the 'city of God' enters the
question of civic education. In the Stoic conception of education, for
example, the drawing out of natural potentials through education takes
human beings beyond the contingent city of their birth, and in a sense
offers them dual citizenship: a student becomes, through her education,
not only a member of the political community of her birth but also a
citizen of the cosmos--a participant in the underlying reality of all
things. The Stoics thought that a life lived according to nature
rendered the person who lived it a citizen of the world (or the
cosmopolis) who could stand above whatever corruptions might be present
in the 'earthly' city, while still discharging their
responsibilities to it. (15) I maintain that these conceptions of
education are still with us. However much we might deny the existence of
a 'cosmos' in the post-Copernican world, (16) we still suggest
something like this 'dual citizenship' whenever we insist that
education is something that cannot (or should not) be exhausted by
'civic education' (in the sense of education tailored to
fit--without excess--the needs of the 'secular' city). Such a
sense of 'dual citizenship' is also evoked when we assert that
we can learn truths which, in transcending our particular society or
time, can at least strive to be universal. We again presuppose something
like this whenever we assume--as, I would argue, we do all the
time--that 'education' is good for both an individual and for
her society without having its content predetermined by the good of
either.
The way we see the connection between the 'two cities'
depends on the particular philosophical vision we have of the
relationship between society, individual and cosmos (or world). Thus,
for Plato and Aristotle, there is a connection between the order of the
city and the order of the soul--such that the fates of each of these are
seen as inextricably interdependent. (17) While this talk of
'souls' and 'orders' may seem hopelessly archaic or
quaint, there are eminently discernible vestiges of these notions in
later educational ideas. Thus, for instance, both Rousseau and Marx
think of a just society as at once the ultimate goal of all education
and in another sense the conditio sine qua non for 'education'
being truly cosmopolitan or 'humanistic', as opposed to merely
and tragically (and parochially) Prussian or American, bourgeois or
aristocratic. For these two thinkers, education is something that in its
true form would be the civic education of a just society--where a just
society would require 'civic education' and 'cosmopolitan
education',(the education of a citizen in her 'civic
responsibilities' and the education of a human being in those
things that best bring out her individual potentials) to overlap to the
point of being indistinguishable. (18)
If we now think about our own time's version of the Bildung
model mentioned above (the idea of education as the cultivating and
drawing out of potentials), we can see what I think is a nigh-on
ubiquitous vision of how education can be something that is at once good
for the individual and good for the community, while still having a
content independent from or 'non-identical' (19) with what the
community or the individual thinks is good. One common way of thinking
about this teaching would be to see education as geared to the community
via the drawing out of the individual student's talents, which will
then somehow (at least ultimately) prove useful to the community. Thus,
a pervasive neo-liberal ideology argues that everyone's pursuits of
their own goals can lead ultimately to the benefit of society, and even
that the prosperity of one society can then flow over to benefit others.
Education (in the Bildung sense) would then be chiefly about drawing out
latent talents which could help the individual pursue her individual
goals in a way that would ultimately lead to the greater good. At its
most tawdry, such an educational vision could look to history teaching
as having little point beyond activating the child's potential to
be (or not to be) a professional historian--a new Simon Schama or Howard
Zinn. This at least would be the belief and hope of the obsessive
middle-class parent who sees school as an institution for bringing out
the musician/actress/sportsman/CEO/best-selling novelist/surgeon lurking
in the recesses of their child's (impeccable) genome.
Of course, we can render a less cynical version of the modern
'education as Bildung' model. But if we wish to put forward
this issue of unleashed 'potential' in less crass terms we are
left with the question: what kind of potential is supposed to be
released from the teaching of history, if it is not something circular
like the child's (potentially remunerative) ability for studying a
specific subject? Surely, we would have to refer to some inherent
potential for insight or to understanding, the ability to see something,
to have certain possible objects of experience--historical objects--come
forth into the light. But what kind of things are these? After the
manner of phenomenology, (20) we could ask: what is the region of being
that the study of history illuminates? And how does this illumination
relate to the city, or to our broadly speaking political concerns?
In order to answer this, we shall have to revisit the opening
quotation and the link between travel and transcendence.
If the past is another country, we would expect to find an analogy
between history and travel. History and travel are linked in that they
are both a means of 'transcending', in the sense of going
beyond or leaving behind the everyday. This does not mean, of course,
that it is impossible for a history book or a journey to be dull or
disappointing. On the contrary, it is precisely because travel,
especially, is often proffered as a kind of exemplary provider of
transcendence (experience something new!) that it is so possible to have
the Wordsworth-in-the-Alps experience of having blinked and missed the
sublimity of surroundings by which we were supposed to have been taken
outside of ourselves.
If history and travel are pre-eminent opportunities for
'transcendence of the everyday', we have to recognise the
extent to which the everyday is itself the product of a kind of
originary transcendence that subsists at the very heart of the human
condition. I would even go so far as to say that what we call
'experience' is an endless and endlessly colourful play of
transcendence and imminence. (21)
But the capacity for our thoughts to transcend (step outside of,
partly leave behind) all kinds of 'environments' and then to
transcend the subsequent environment that emerges through ensuing
constellations of perception-imagination-memory (22) means that every
society must constantly try to find a place for--or a way of making
sense of--experience as it is marked and constituted by transcendence.
Thus, all societies have ways of representing and making sense of
experiences of desire, and of dreams, of ecstasy and relief, of
symbolising birth, death, rapture, pain, loss, initiation. Similarly,
all societies have prohibitions and laws, taboos, markers: ways of
ordering and making sense of the ecstatic character of experience.
The need to limit, mark, consecrate and even repudiate certain
'transcendences' can be seen when we look at the existence of
rituals that have always surrounded travelling. All societies have ways
of marking journeys, crossing thresholds; ritual forms of commemoration
or consecrations to do with arrival and departure; and, in particular,
of blessing--of transferring some form of social soul-stuff on to a
person perceived to be undertaking a literal or figurative journey.
Because of the oft-remarked tendency for human beings to represent time
in terms of space--we can include among 'odysseys' crossings
of thresholds in time. I mean by this things like marriages, funerals
and all kinds of initiation rights, from circumcisions to graduations.
These can all be seen as ways of marking, commemorating, and
consecrating arrival and departure. It's just that here the
terminals of our destination are 'stages on life's way';
the airport departure lounges of our lives. (23)
Many conventional farewells in European languages (a-dieu,
good-bye, a-dios) speak of going to even more than with God. The idea
expressed in these terms is thus both an acknowledgement and an attempt
to deal with the fact that journeys (in transcending the quotidian)
entail existential threats: if my secular journey to the market, or to
the Hellespont, is 'interrupted' in the dramatic form of my
untimely death, I will--according to the hope express in the
'goodbye'--at least have reached my ultimate destination
safely.
Pre-eminent amongst the phenomena of 'globalisation' is
the fact that 'travel' (at least for the middle and upper
classes) (24) is often represented as one of the more prominent panaceas
for the ills for modern (globalised) life. More respectable than heroin,
more revocable than suicide, more chic than any religion lacking the
leather jacket of fundamentalism, 'travel' (25) is at once
supposed to be compatible with freedom while involving a willing
submission to the experience of other places and other cultures. It is
this openness that is supposed to offer us a transcendence of the
everyday, which can be received like a bolt of pure vitality, restoring
our sense of life's wonder and so on.
What is interesting here is the way this attitude plays down a
certain kind of existential threat, in order to make the embrace of this
threat the point of the exercise of travelling. This is curious, because
if we did not know better we could expect the opposite to occur and the
sense of existential threat to grow proportionally with the power to
travel. Power, after all, allows for control; control brings (or tries
to bring about) security; and the inevitable result of security is
anxiety about the security one has just (often expensively) purchased.
(26) But if this is in any way the case, I nonetheless think that this
anxiety is a tacitly forbidden expression in modern rituals marking the
arrival and the departure of travellers. If we hug the person going to
Acapulco or New Zealand, we might wish them luck or a safe journey but
we are unlikely, I suspect, to make the avuncular suggestion that they
should mind that they do not lose their souls in the untrammelled wilds
of the world. One reason for this might be simply that it is, for the
most part, simply safer (and thus less scary) to travel these days than
it once might have been; there are no 'here be dragons' on the
Lonely Planet maps of the world. But I think there is another reason why
people in talking to departing friends and family do not mention
existential threats, at least of the non-literal sort that do not
involve us being threatened by guns or disease, but the kind of thing
that would have made an Edwardian aunt tell her nephew: 'Now,
remember that you are an Englishman,' as he set off for the Sudan.
This, I think, can be attributed to a concern about Orientalism that
does not require the speaker to be familiar with the term.
I use 'Orientalism' conventionally to mark the
simultaneous expression of fear and fascination that has marked
attitudes of the West to the East--the Coloniser to the Colonised. (27)
The Western traveller's fascinated pursuit of the exotic can look,
even to herself, so paradigmatically Orientalist that she is unlikely to
admit to the terror that is the other half of the Orientalist equation.
The fear I am talking about is the properly existential fear that is
suggested by the idea of a 'Heart of Darkness'. Nothing could
be more contrary to the ethos of capital
'T'--'Travelling'--than this fear, insofar as it
suggests that 'another country' might not only be the source
of injury or death, but of figuratively losing ourselves; losing our
Western, everyday identities. This 'Victorian' vision of
things is rejected by 'Travellers' because the point of
'Travel' is to risk that loss; to soak ourselves in everything
that is different, new, exotic about another country. The antithesis of
this 'traveller' attitude can be found in the attitudes
expressed by Evelyn Waugh in his travels and which are frequently
attributed by Australians to American tourists: complaining about
service or the weather, irritated by the fact that
'foreigners' speak another language, and generally demanding
that the place we are visiting blithely and instantaneously conforms to
our own desires, rather than giving ourselves up to the new place--the
other country. (28)
The question that this raises is: in the realm of history, is there
a comparable attitude to this Orientalism-avoiding,
transcendence-seeking attitude towards the 'other countries'
of the past? Does anyone tell schoolchildren that the point of their
learning is first--as people will argue with regards to Travelling, to
dive in--to get soaked in the past, its customs and ideas, until the
language, the ways, the quirks of the place start to suffuse one's
soul? Who thinks about the past the way a self-proclaimed
'traveller' thinks of 'another country'? Does anyone
argue that there could be nothing more mortifying than to bring
one's ignorant pre-conceptions about the past to the past as a
vehicle for judging preceding understanding?
The answers to these questions are, I think, 'No' and
'Not enough'. And this is revealing of the extent to which we
are in danger of neglecting what I am calling the paradox of civic
education in democracies. The paradox is this. Every society needs to
make some concessions to education 'for' the city. In liberal,
and especially in neo-liberal conceptions of our 'real
existing' democracies, it is often suggested that 'civic
education' per se, i.e. education 'for' the city, should
be kept to a minimum (at most a small 'civics' class teaching
the history of the nation, the functions of parliament and the rudiments
of getting a job and filling out tax returns). The bulk of our
'civic education' is then supposed to be provided by our
education 'by the city'--our character and decisions fleshed
out by our 'freely chosen' encounters with other people, with
ideas, and with information and entertainment that we somehow stumble
across in the lifelong process of pursuing our idiosyncratic interests
and goals.
But what role, in this conception, is left for
'education' generally, and for an education in the humanities
in particular? The question is particularly important, given that an
education in the humanities can and should give the student both a
series of standpoints from which and the rhetorical tools with which to
call into question the reigning orthodoxies of not only government,
business or bureaucracy, but also and at the same time the products of
the complex movements of money, information and ideas that constitute
the present culture and society. Alternatively, the humanities can be
seen as simply the matter of an idiosyncratic and rather peculiar career
choice or leisure pursuit that is dependent on (while hopefully)
contributing to a lucrative education industry. In this vision the
humanities do not constitute a dangerous threat to society (as they
might aspire to be) but at their worst are a mere pernicious distraction
from the real world. For the most part they are perceived, in this
vision, as just another marginal pursuit like motor-racing or
phylactery. But the ideal of a free society is surely close to being
abandoned altogether when it does not give humanistic education
(literature, philosophy, history) pride of place as the only possible
contender for providing the true (and not simply the minimal) civic
education of a democratic society. This is because and not despite the
fact that literature, philosophy and history expose the present society
to ideas that may be different from those which are currently idolised
by either noisy majorities or self-important minorities. In providing
society with more than just a mirror of itself, the citizens of our
democracies are given the tools to resist indoctrination and sophistry through a multiplicity of ways, symbols, ideas and visions of life and
the world, by which they might judge and choose everything from the
education system to the ideals which oriented or animated their classes.
It is a hallmark of a truly liberal and genuinely democratic
society that it should be willing to come close to losing its life in
order to save it. The right to freedom of speech is often conceived
along the lines of an assumption that a democracy is strengthened by
diversity of opinion, even when that opinion deviates from simply the
monotonous praise of the present culture and its idols. This is because
a democracy is supposed to be a society in the process of becoming--a
society whose laws and forms can be subject to revision, to questioning,
to revolutions and restorations. And if democracy requires a vigorous
and free public sphere in order to be truly autonomous, that public
sphere is itself best preserved by citizens who possess a deep and rich
grasp of more ideas than the ones to which they subscribe. This last
feature has nothing to do with promoting flakiness or lack of
conviction. Instead, it is often the condition of real eloquence as well
as a bulwark against rhetorical tricks and propaganda.
To elaborate, everyone knows that education is the arena in which
the battle for the future will be decided. All visions of society
converge, meet and fight over education. But it is over the teaching of
history more than anywhere else that standard ideological warfare has
most resembled war. In the ten-year reign of the Howard government, the
former Prime Minister and his journalistic apparatchiks argued again and
again for the 'reform' of history programs, effectively
demanding that edifying national myths blot out unedifying national
crimes. (29) This demand was intriguingly accompanied by denunciations
of 'post-modern history' and a call for 'narrative'
history, as if there were natural affinities between a given style of
historical reportage and a given ideological line. (30)
One of the hallmarks of the debates of the Howard years was the
number of times different partisans saw themselves as debating which
moral lessons or 'values' should be the ones to hold sway over
the next generation and thus the future. And, presumably, we cannot
avoid teaching children something like 'values'. But while we
will find various values to promote--from the 'national pride'
beloved of right-wing think-tanks to engendering 'openness'
and other such modish simulacra of the ability to think--the best sign,
I would argue, that what is being taught is history and not simply the
fashionable ideology of this or that side is the extent to which a given
history program has a chance of having its stated goals confounded by
aspects of that same program. (31)
Therefore, I would argue, the better the history course, the harder
it will be to derive any particular moral lesson from it; or, more
accurately, the less its content will be subordinated by or equivalent
to that moral lesson. The better the program, the more it will have that
which history records most frequently of all: unintended consequences.
What I am arguing, in essence, is that the teaching of history should be
regarded less along the lines of the inculcation of correct opinions and
more along the lines of the handing out of passports. Further, that a
free society should be one which believes it has an obligation to allow
itself to be judged by standards that it had not pre-arranged in
advance.
Most people who have talked about history curricula since the 1960s
would agree that the emphasis of history courses should be on ideas and,
through ideas, the fostering of capacities for 'critical
thinking'. I agree with this, but I think it is important to add
the caveat that teaching the ideas requires an extraordinary level of
sensitivity, caution and skill. This is because while rote-learning a
date may have dubious value, rote-learning an idea is always an
abomination. And it is precisely the rote-learning of ideas that will
occur (whatever those ideas are) if we treat history teaching in a way
that does not at least partially replicate something like
'Traveller' attitudes, i.e. if we do not treat the past as
another country. (32) After all, the only evidence that 'critical
thinking' is going on is the manner in which we treat the ideas
with which we come into contact; it is not an inherent property of which
ideas we prefer above others. It should be (but seemingly isn't)
obvious that no doctrines or views are inherently 'critical';
there are only the critical or uncritical attitudes of those who
subscribe to them.
Therefore, a History of Australia (for example) is not inherently
'critical' just because it irritates the government's
official version of national mythology, even if that official version is
widely believed. Conversely, a government's self-serving attempt at
an 'official history' hardly deserves the status of an
embattled Socratic gadfly just because it goes against the consensus of
historians. Being 'critical' does not attach to given
arguments; still less to their 'majority' or
'minority' status. Otherwise, the flat-earther who compares
herself (in her heterodoxy) to Galileo would have a point.
'Critical' can only refer to to the way that people behave in
reaching the positions they uphold as true and, moreover, how they
continue to behave once they have reached these positions. (How open are
they to contrary evidence? How interested are they in other
perspectives, etcetera?). Suffice it to say, there is a lot of loose
talk which suggests that precisely the opposite is the case; as if
'critical' status came with being a partisan of one side (one
methodology) and not another, the way chips come with pub meals.
History involves risks. And these are no less than those of going
to another country. It is because of this that our attitudes to history
should better reflect our ideas of Travel. I have argued that the true
civic education of a democratic community is one which will expose it to
things that are not simply what the current moods of that society find
respectable. This is not a new idea, but it is an endangered one. (33)
Travellers pride themselves on not trying to 'manage' the
experience they are about to have; on not determining in advance what
they are going to experience. To treat the past as another country is to
remember that it, too, is as unruly, unmanageable and wild as the
Antarctic or the Sahara. Indeed, wildness and unpredictability are the
reasons why we seek history out. This is not to say that we do not need
to reflect on pedagogical techniques, or that history programs can be
without any kind of structure--this would be insane--or that we do not
need constant reflection on the moral and political consequences a way
of teaching. I only worry that, in trying to win the battle for the
future, different ideologues in educational debates will unintentionally
end up posing the idea that any travels to the past must be pre-arranged
to ensure the safety of some set of ideas/principles or another. But
such risk-management stifles a journey to the extent that we may as well
never have left the place from which we set out.
'Liberal' education in a democracy involves a paradox. It
is the idea that we can at once live in one 'city', or one
country, dedicated to a finite (if not homogenous or monochrome) set of
ideals (cosmopolitanism, liberty, the expansion of social justice) while
yet allowing our bodies and souls to wander the Earth. It is, therefore,
an attempt to uphold the ideal that the least constrained and least
'pre-determined' education could, precisely as such, be the
one most suitable to a free society and its citizens. The dream here,
coeval with the idea of democracy, suggests that the civic education of
a bounded, finite city could nonetheless converge with something that
aimed at being, at the same time, the education of human beings in the
panoply of human concerns and not only what is thought to preserve the
community or fulfil its functions. This would be education at its most
wide-ranging but also at its deepest. A truly liberal, truly democratic
society would not suffer from, but thrive from having plumbed such
depths. It would not be stifled but sustained by the breadth of these
wanderings.
ENDNOTES
(1) This is the first line of L P Hartley's The Go-Between,
Penguin Books, Harmondsworth, 1971. In quotation the word
'foreign' is often substituted for the more euphonious (or at
least more memorable) 'another' which I have used throughout.
(2) The peculiar beauty of these sentences seems to owe much to the
way that the seemingly redundant second sentence is (through the
parataxis that links it to the first) somehow redolent with the mystery
and 'pathos of distance' to which the first sentence
testifies.
(3) For an excellent discussion of how we can concede the
impossibility of leaving behind the 'prejudices' of our own
time, and why this nonetheless does not prevent the possibility of an
encounter between our prejudices and the past, see Hans-Georg Gadamer,
Truth and Method, Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G Marshall, Continuum,
London, 2004, 268-282.
(4) For a less attenuated discussion of the issue of myth and
reality that has nonetheless informed these brief remarks, see, for
instance, Mircea Eliade, Myth and Reality, George Allen & Unwin Ltd,
London, 1964; J G Gunnell, Political Philosophy and Time: Plato and the
Origins of Political Vision, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1987,
17-53. On the role of stories in constituting a world see Hannah Arendt,
The Human Condition, New York, Double Day Anchor Books, 1959, 164.
(5) With a cantankerous wit which alternately belies or confirms
his reputation, Hegel is reputed to have said that the only thing that
we learn from history is that no one ever learns anything from history.
(6) It is interesting to note that the term 'civic
education' is rarely used in Australian public debate, whereas
there are classes in 'civics' (often involving history) at
both American high schools and French lycees. This could arguably be
said to be reflective of the fairly minimal role that republican (as
opposed to liberal, social-democratic, socialist and
Burkean-conservative and neo-liberal) political theory has played in the
history of the nation. For an extraordinary treatment of everything to
do with 'civic humanism' and 'classical
republicanism', see J G A Pocock, The Machiavellian Moment:
Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Political Tradition,
Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1975. The relatively
insignificant role played by this set of political ideas in the
political history of Australia (and Britain after the ages of Milton and
Harrington respectively) can perhaps be explained that, in the 19th
century, republican ideas seemed to be integrated into the
self-conception of the aristocracy (noble houses as the servants of the
commonweal) and thus would have been anathema to the democratic
agitators of, say, the Labour Movement, with its roots in liberal,
social democratic, socialist and Jacobin traditions.
(7) For an account of the paradox of the minimal 'civic
duties' with enormous demands of the 'social', see Arendt
35-45.
(8) Pierre Hadot speaks of synousia in terms very similar to how I
describe 'education by the city'. See Pierre Hadot, What is
Ancient Philosophy?, Michael Chase (trans.), Harvard University Press,
Cambridge, Mass., 2002, 7.
(9) Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in America, Harvey Mansfield
and Delba Winthrop (trans.), University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 2000.
(10) On my use of the concept of 'social imaginary', see
Cornelius Castoriadis, The Imaginary Institution of Society, Kathleen
Blamey (trans.), Polity Press, Cambridge, 1997, 135-156.
(11) The vision of Sparta as a totally integrated polity has
numerous sources going back to Thucydides and Plato, but is a constant
reference point of Rousseau starting with his First Discourse.
(12) An objection may be raised to this claim that would invoke the
sociology of science. Obviously, many sociologists and philosophers have
been interested in the role played by everything from moral to
metaphysical ideas in the development of the natural sciences.
Furthermore, there is considerable interest expressed in many
disciplines in questions about how science could be made morally and
politically responsible to the community. But while this is the case,
few of the people who analyse this intersection tend to speak of
determining the content of science programs in relation to given social
aims. (The spectre of Lysenko, not to mention Creation Science hovers
over all such attempts.) Thus, we are more likely to find claims either
that science performs its civic duties better by becoming more
scientific (i.e. by not having its results skewed by this or that
present-day prejudice) or that scientists study 'ethics' as a
kind of supplementary practice that nonetheless is not supposed to
displace scientific method.
(13) The heyday of the idea of Bildung is probably the late 18th
and early 19th century, so perhaps particularly under the influence of
Rousseau's ideas of education.
(14) On the rejection of teleology and the problem it causes for
ideas of virtue (and thus the whole Bildung concept), see Alasdair
MacIntyre, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory, Ducksworth, London,
1985.
(15) See, for example, Marcus Aurelius, Meditations, Martin Hammond
(trans.), Penguin, London, 2006.
(16) See MacIntyre op. cit.
(17) For a discussion on this parallel between these thinkers, see
Michael P Morrissey, Consciousness and Transcendence: The Theology of
Eric Voegelin, University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, 57-80.
(18) For Rousseau, see Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Emile, Or On
Education, Allan Bloom (trans.), Basic Books, New York, 1979, alongside
Jean-Jacques Rousseau, The Social Contract in Rousseau's Political
Writings, Julia Conaway Bondanella (trans.), Allan Ritter (ed.), W W
& Norton Company, New York, 1998. For Marx, see the small but
telling section in Marx and Engels, The Communist Manifesto, in Lewis S
Feuer (ed.), Marx & Engels: Basic Writings on Politics and
Philosophy, Double Day Anchor Books, New York, 25.
(19) I use this expression in the sense of Theodor Adorno, where it
is not just a pretentious (and inexplicable) substitute for
'different', but suggests that this difference exhibits a
resilience, a resistance to being subsumed under an identity.
(20) For an excellent introduction to phenomenology, see Dermot
Moran, Introduction to Phenomenology, Routledge, New York, 2000.
(21) We can see this aspect of our experience most clearly when we
look to the invoked phenomena of the imagination. Thus, on the one hand,
we know that we can 'transcend' our environment, not insofar
as we can defy gravity or leave behind the sub-lunary world, but insofar
as we do not encounter simply an environment--in which we orient
ourselves according to biological programs--but a world made up of
meanings, symbols, imaginings through and within which the different
aspects of our environment emerge as objects of experience. Thus, the
world presents itself to me not only as a place where I want food, but
where I want a sandwich, where I do not only see a green-gold blur to
which I'm mysteriously compelled; I do not even see
'trees': I see, instead, the poplars in the distance of which
that poet spoke so beautifully before the consumption took him. I can
try to ignore my hunger because of a diet or a vow, because I am
mourning over a lost love, or busy developing my perfect abdomen for the
greater glory of whatever. But the existence of something like the
imagination (as a kernel of the psyche) is not only the condition of
possibility for participating in a universe of forms, symbols, signs and
ideas, but also the condition of possibility for these
'symbolic' universes to be themselves interrupted, disturbed
or called to account by an experience of hunger or desire, by a sudden
conflagration of memory or an overwhelming perception (of, say, another
person who I find beautiful or mysterious, a landscape that I find
sublime). We transcend our 'environment' in order to see a
world, but this world is not static, enclosed or homogenous, but
something perpetually interrupted by events that summon us back from an
enclosure in our own minds and which direct our capacities for
apprehension outwards, even as our outward experience can direct us
inwards (to meditation, speculation, reflection). We are thus beholden to the exigencies of a reality that subsists outside of us, i.e.
transcends our own minds. By an act of thought, I transcend my thoughts
on the history of Languedoc to stare at the waterfall in front of me,
and vice versa. The waterfall is at once transcendent to my thought
process (I am not and can never be it) and the cause of my mind's
self-transcendence its going outwards to apprehend something in the
world. It is through a weight of experience under which we can find the
symbols through which we make sense of the universe changing, in flux,
in motion; and with this our apprehension and perception of that
universe. In reverie we can, for instance, transcend surroundings both
ignoring the tiger in front of us for a daydream, and dreaming of tigers
when our immediate surroundings consist of a prison in which we have
nothing real to stare at but stone. Experience, then, is--as a venerable
philosophical tradition holds--ecstatic, meaning that in experiencing we
constantly (if never absolutely) step outside of ourselves. (My account
here owes much to Castoriadis but the account is also inflected by works
by Emmanuel Levinas and Eric Voegelin.) See Morrissey, 81-82.
(22) The triad is from Aristotle's De Anima, but see also note
20 above.
(23) I would have said 'waystations', but the expression
is so conventional that its metaphoric origin is lost--such expressions
are the places, as George Orwell often said, where thoughts go to die.
See George Orwell, 'Politics and the English language',
Essays, Penguin, London, 1994, 350.
(24) 'Travel' conceived of as a somehow
'authentic' encounter with 'another country' (its
people and culture) seems to be a pretension of a section of the middle
class--namely, whatever section disdains the idea of a mere
'overseas holiday' as crass or exploitative. This attitude
usually requires that the kind of tawdry leisure activities indulged in
by people on 'holidays' are sufficiently accessible at all
times to not constitute an interruption (or transcendence) of one's
everyday working life.
(25) See note 23 above.
(26) On a deeper exploration of some of the paradoxes that arise
from the perceived link between anxiety, security and power, see Jason
Freddi, 'London, July 2005: A failure of security?', Melbourne
Journal of Politics, vol. 32, 2007, 45-66; Zygmunt Bauman's
discussion of 'Unsicherheit' as
uncertainty/insecurity/unsafety [sic] in Zygmunt Bauman, In Search of
Politics, Polity Press, Oxford, 1999, 17.
(27) See Edward Said, Orientalism, Penguin, London, 1995.
(28) For an amusing account of Waugh's attitude to
'foreign travel', see Selina Hastings, Evelyn Waugh: A
Biography, Sinclair-Stevenson, London, 1994, 240-241.
(29) A good summary of the so-called 'History Wars'
during the reign of the Howard government can be found in Stuart
MacIntyre's 'The History Wars: the 2003 Russel Ward Lecture,
University of New England, Armidale, 1 May 2003', Journal of
Australian Colonial History, vol.4, no.2, 2002, 1-19.
(30) For an excellent account of why this is not the case, see the
recent article by John Hirst, 'Australia: The official
history', The Monthly, Feb 2008. Here Hirst comments on his
surprise at finding himself the author of the 'official history of
Australia, the one that the Howard government distributed to migrants to
pass the citizenship test'. But as he goes on to note:
'Howard's mistake was to think that narrative [history, of the
style advocated by both Hirst and Howard] would give him the history
that he wanted contra 'black armband' history of the
left'. Here, Howard showed himself under the spell of the false
idea that right-wing history is likely to be in Nietzsche's term
'monumental', while left-wing history is necessarily
'critical'. Against this, it is obvious that a work like E P
Thompson's The Making of the English Working Class is a work of
monumental history (dealing as it does with the splendour and misery of
a great movement in the context of a stirring narrative), whereas
Nazi-hack Alfred Rosenberg's The Myth of the Twentieth Century has
many of the hallmarks of 'critical history' in that it lays a
claim to see through 'official' history and recover instead
the story of an oppressed group (the 'Aryans' [!]) an
'excluded voice' in the ruthless world of official history.
(31) A wonderful example of this is Marxist literary critic Terry
Eagleton's description of what happened when 'English'
was first proposed as a program at Oxford. The old dons, he says, who
were mainly classicists, argued that the idea of teaching
'English' was a ridiculous piece of jingoism, a way of
replacing a knowledge of what was truly human with the inculcation of
nationalistic guff. This was, Eagleton says, entirely true. But because
the English program succeeded, despite its goals in giving its students
an actual encounter with English literature, the aims of the course
designers were never guaranteed success. On the contrary, the English
programs not only produced students who could glorify Britannia and its
right to rule the waves with a quote about 'this sceptred
isle' (Richard II); they also created students who were equally
capable of criticising the pretensions and the crimes of Empire on the
basis of the same play, not to mention the works of Milton, Blake,
Dickens etcetera. See Terry Eagleton, 'The crisis of contemporary
culture', New Left Review, no. 196, November-December 1996, 29-41.
(32) The source of my concern would be, for instance, a history
program that paid enormous attention to explaining a given author by
historical context (a laudable enterprise), but that consigned the
intellectual products of that author's epoch to mere epiphenomena
of current events. But while this might be worrying, it is still not yet
at the stage of the 'rote-learning' of ideas. For this, we
would need a case where students actually tried to achieve good results
by imitating their teacher's line or replicating her moral,
political or metaphysical judgements. Faced with such a thing in a
tutorial during the 1960s, the historian A J P Taylor is said to have
responded: 'I've heard of the dog returning to the vomit, but
never the vomit being returned to the dog.' See Adam Sisman, A.J P
Taylor: A Biography, Mandarin, London, 1995, 271.
(33) Among the things that endanger this idea, I would also have to
add the belief that civic responsibilities are best discharged by work.
While this may be regarded as a necessary 'liberal' concession
against 'republican' ideas of government (not everyone can
spend all their time in Tocquevillian town-hall meetings and not
everyone may want to), it is also a convenient way of allowing the
capitalist elements of our society to crush the ostensibly democratic
ones. For example, if I work for the minimum wage and spend my time
being harassed by managers, at what point do I get a chance to exercise
my 'citizen' rights? What is humanistic education to me, when
my level of participation in the functions of government is so minimal?
The disappearance of humanistic education as civic education is
suggestive of a world which is indifferent to people's flourishing
either as citizens or as human beings, a world where one is anonymous
employee number 579, anonymous consumer 4 billion and whatever.
Bryan Cooke
School of Philosophical, Anthropological and Social Inquiry