Dreams and superstition: a reinterpretation of satire in Apuleius, Metamorphoses 11.
Watson, Nathan
The question of whether Book 11 of Apuleius' Metamorphoses is
a sincere religious evocation or a satirical parody continues to animate
discussion among scholars. (1) Indeed, many scholars believe that the
text deliberately allows for both conclusions, following Winkler's
idea of an 'unauthorized', indeterminate ending. (2) One such
scholar, David Carlisle, emphasises the centrality of Lucius'
dreams to any interpretation of Book 11. (3) It appears that if one
accepts the dreams as true and meaningful, then the conclusion is
edifying, just as Lucius presents it; but if the dreams are considered
to be meaningless fantasies misinterpreted by Lucius, then the
conclusion presents a gullible convert deceived by his priests, who
themselves claim to experience instructional, god-sent dreams. I will
argue, however, that this is a false dichotomy, for it is not the only
way to approach the dreams as a key to interpreting Book 11. If the
depiction of god-sent dreams could be seen to parody religious
experience, then the existing view of satire in Book 11 might be
modified significantly.
Since Winkler first proposed that the novel presents a satire of
religious gullibility in Book 11, those who have argued likewise view it
as analogous to the satire on priestly corruption in Books 8 and 9.
During this episode, ass-Lucius witnesses his owners, Philebus and his
troop of itinerant priests, rob a temple and deceive unsuspecting
petitioners with all-purpose oracles. Likewise, in Book 11, the cult of
Isis and Osiris is believed to manipulate a gullible Lucius into
receiving ever more expensive initiations. Thus, the priests of Isis are
'rapacious vultures' and 'religious charlatans',
whilst Lucius is a 'sucker', who is 'duped by his own
gullibility' and 'allows himself to be plucked by the greedy
priests of Isis and Osiris'. (4) He pays money 'for obvious
religious fraud', which itself 'recalls the uncanny
description of the vagabond priests of the Syrian Goddess in Books 8 and
9', thus forming a 'familiar satirical pattern'. (5)
Ultimately, Lucius himself becomes a charlatan priest just like those
whom he had earlier criticised. (6)
As noted above, this argument relies upon the notion that Lucius
misplaces his trust in dreams. (7) Three main ideas inform this
position: (1) the dreams are products of Lucius' desire, revealing
his overeagerness for religious experiences; (2) the priests manipulate
this desire, influencing or interpreting Lucius' dreams to their
advantage; and, (3) Lucius is presented as gullible because he trusts
his 'charlatan' priests and believes his
'self-generated' dreams, finding divine significance in
unimportant details. (8) This emphasis upon deception occurs in the
satire of superstitious religious behaviour by Lucian and Juvenal. (9)
But this picture is not painted clearly in Book 11, for those who argue
for such a satire also include the gods as playing an active role in the
deception of Lucius, which implies that they are sending some of the
dreams. (10) This, however, begs the question of which dreams are
god-sent and which are self-generated, and how the reader is supposed to
tell the difference between them. Significantly, recent studies on the
dreams in the Metamorphoses have argued convincingly that, throughout
the novel, dreams consistently convey meaningful content to the
dreamer.11 Those who see Lucius' dreams as meaningless, however,
have neglected to consider that the dreams of Books 1-10 inform how the
reader understands such divination in the world of the novel prior to
Book 11. (12) Indeed, the dreams of Books 1-10 follow the convention of
those in narrative fiction (i.e. true dreams that function as
storytelling devices). (13)
Likewise, the dreams in Book 11 can be shown to be god-sent by
examining the first double-dream sequence of Lucius and the high priest,
which prefigures Lucius' retransformation. (14) After Lucius prays
to the moon on the beach at Cenchreae, he falls asleep and immediately
beholds a vision of Isis, whose subsequent instruction can be
substantiated. (15) She declares that on the next day her followers will
celebrate the festival which opens the sailing season (11,5,5). It is
indeed the navigium Isidis that the Isiac faithful celebrate after
Lucius is transformed (11,16,6-10). Isis also explains that her high
priest will lead the procession carrying Lucius' long sought cure
(11,6,1-2). The priest indeed carries a wreath of roses (11,13,1-2).
This passage also confirms that, since the priest appears startled by
the realisation that his own dream has come true (nocturni commonefactus
oraculi miratusque congruentiam mandati muneris), Isis did appear in his
dream also. In Lucius' dream, the goddess states that she is
instructing her priest (11,6,3). Isis also assures Lucius that people
will not accuse him of sorcery (11,6,4). Indeed, they pay homage to the
goddess by stretching their hands out to heaven and calling out with one
voice (11,13,6). (16) Lucius' dream of Isis, therefore, cannot be
explained away rationally because its content is borne out by the
subsequent events. (17)
This position is only strengthened by the detailed information Isis
has given the high priest about Lucius. For instance, the priest
addresses the newly-reformed Lucius by name (Luci), alludes to his high
birth (natales, dignitas), education (doctrina), and that he became an
ass as a result of his curiosity (curiositatis ... sinistrum praemium;
11,15,1). Moreover, he specifies robbers, wild animals, and slavery as
the torments of Lucius' adventures (quid latrones, quid ferae, quid
servitium; 11,15,3). (18) Lucius, as a speechless animal, could not have
related this information to anyone, so the double-dream of the Isiac
high priest and Lucius has to be god-sent. We can hardly accuse Lucius,
on this basis, of gullibility for believing in his dreams.
Yet the repeated use of dreams in Book 11 to motivate Lucius does
warrant consideration. The seemingly superfluous dreams include the
Candidus dream (11,20), Isis' message sending Lucius to Rome
(11,26,1), and the instructions for his initiations into the mysteries
of Osiris (11,27-29). Ostensibly, the first two connect the loose
threads regarding what became of Lucius' property and why the
prologue concerns Rome. (19) Even so, these matters could have been
handled without the use of dreams (for instance, through the advice of
priests). Therefore, they have to serve some narrative purpose. The
effect of the Candidus dream is twofold: first, by prefiguring the
return of Lucius' property in a dream, its actual return appears to
be Isis' gift; second, the wonder caused by its unexpected bounty
increases Lucius' devotion to Isis and the attention he pays to his
dreams (11,21,1). The dream that sends Lucius to Rome builds upon this,
illustrating that he will make life-changing and expensive decisions at
the behest of his dreams.
The second and third initiations continue to demonstrate
Lucius' deference to dreams. He is pushed by divine will (numinis
premebar instantia; 11,28,2) to sell his clothes to pay for an
initiation that is unexpected and likely unnecessary. (20) Likewise, a
'friendly phantom' (clemens imago) justifies the third
initiation to Lucius, telling him it is because his ceremonial cloak is
stored in Cenchreae (11,29,3-4). (21) Significantly, these dreams serve
to justify the expense and necessity of the initiations rather than
provide spiritual guidance. Moreover, since the justification does not
come from priests, it highlights the role of the gods as instigators of
this prolonged religious induction. (22)
These unforeseen initiations and their bizarre explanations only
serve to diminish the wonder caused by the initial dreams. The first
dream of Book 11 features Isis in her true form, the sublime detail of
its ecphrasis promoting awe. Likewise, the last dream of Book 11
features Osiris' true form, but his majesty is not related in a
magnificent manner: he gets no ecphrasis. Indeed, Lucius' attempt
to express the supremacy of Osiris comes across as comically histrionic
wordplay (deus ... regnator; 11,30,3). (23) Moreover, the dream's
content bestows a sense of banality to the conclusion: the detail that
Lucius' legal career has divine endorsement seems superfluous and
uninteresting given the extraordinary nature of Lucius' adventure
so far. (24) So, whilst the dreams from 11,26,4 onward show a continued
link between Lucius and the divine, the link has become more mundane
than mystical, with the result that the wonder imparted by Lucius'
first dream, his transformation, and his first initiation is diminished
by the more prosaic dreams and initiations in Rome. (25) This does not
indicate that the dreams are self-generated and Lucius is gullible for
believing them, but their anti-climactic nature, in conjunction with the
simpler narrative style in the last four chapters, could be a ploy by
Apuleius to suggest that Lucius' religious awakening should not be
taken at face value and may even hint that Lucius' relationship
with the gods is tainted by superstition, so reliant upon his dreams he
has become. (26)
This approach to dreams is similar to the paradoxical employment of
dreams by Petronius. In the Satyrica, the protagonists promote an
Epicurean stance regarding dreams by pointing out their meaninglessness.
(27) Simultaneously, however, Petronius employs god-sent dreams for plot
development and characterisation. Dreams about the protagonists are sent
to their adversaries by the gods; (28) the presence of god-sent dreams,
however, does not elevate these characters or laud such dreams. Instead,
god-sent dreams are mocked because they do not provide a lasting benefit
to their recipients. (29) In addition, Petronius exposes their very
absurdity by having unlikely gods send dreams to unworthy people in
unseemly settings about base and trivial matters. (30) Moreover, by
maintaining an Epicurean perspective, the recipients' willingness
to believe in these dreams characterises them as superstitious despite
the god-sent nature of the dreams within the story. (31) Petronius,
therefore, has it both ways by using a common literary device for
narrative ends while at the same time characterising superstitious
behaviour.
Admittedly, Lucius' dreams are not unseemly and Apuleius is
not expounding an Epicurean perspective, but the use of god-sent dreams
to highlight superstition is instructive when applied to Book 11.
Indeed, the excessive use of god-sent dreams in Book 11 helps to show
that Lucius is the kind of person who superstitiously sublimates his
rational mind to dreams. Furthermore, the overabundance of dreams,
concluding with an epiphany of Osiris that is much less compelling for
the reader than that of Isis, combined with the knowledge of
Lucius' undiscerning nature during the first ten books, raises
suspicion about whether he has really changed. But this is not the only
suspicion created in Book 11, for Lucius casts doubt upon his priests
before his third initiation (11,29,3). Those who argue for a satire on
priestly deceit believe that this mistrust is justified and signals how
the reader is supposed to view them; (32) but given that the dreams are
god-sent and since it is the gods who justify the later initiations, a
reassessment of the priests is required.
The idea that the presentation and content of the later dreams
undercut those preceding them is aided by the contrasting portrayal of
Mithras and Asinius Marcellus. The notion of priestly decline in Book 11
has been proposed by Margaret Edsall. (33) She argues that Mithras is an
'idealised Egyptian priest' who is sincere in his motive for
initiating Lucius, whereas the profit-seeking Asinius Marcellus dupes
Lucius with his 'degraded mysteries'. (34) Nevertheless, when
Mithras and Asinius receive god-sent dreams it regards their religious
duties, whereas Lucius' final dream from Osiris deals only with his
fame in the law court, which contrasts the materialistic concerns of
this pastophorus with the pure asceticism of Mithras. (35) I shall use
Edsall's model as a base for my own discussion of the priests,
adding to it where I can and modifying it so as to shift the focus of
the satire towards Lucius' relationship with the gods.
The criticism levelled against Mithras that supposedly points to
satire concerns his inspired speech and the apparent cost of his
initiation rites. (36) Mithras has been likened to the Syrian priests
due to his breathlessness after his divinely inspired speech to Lucius
(11,16,1), which recalls the frenzied breathing of a Syrian priest
before he makes his false confession (8,27,6). (37) Even if the
intratext is deliberate, several factors indicate disparity between the
two priests rather than parity. (38) That the priest of the Dea Syria is
feigning ecstatic possession is beyond doubt, but the difference for
Mithras is that he has already been shown to have Isis' favour
since she instructs him in his dream (11,6,3; 11,13,1). Furthermore,
Mithras' very words prove this divine favour in that his speech is
entirely accurate--Lucius has been a victim of his curiosity. Therefore,
this is not an attempt by Mithras to dupe Lucius or the crowd by
feigning divine possession.
Mithras has also been said to betray an anti-intellectual sentiment
in this speech. (39) When contrasted with Apuleius' own learning,
this is meant to signal that the priest is a figure of ridicule. Such a
conclusion, however, stretches Mithras' words.
'Nec tibi natales ac ne dignitas quidem, vel ipsa qua flores
usquam doctrina profuit, sed lubrico virentis aetatulae ad serviles
delapsus voluptates, curiositatis inprosperae sinistrum praemium
reportasti.' (11,15,1)
'Neither your lineage, nor even your social position, nor even
the learning in which you flourish has benefited you in any way; but
having sunk to slavish pleasures on the hazardous path of inexperienced
youth, you have won the perverse reward of your ruinous curiosity.'
What the high priest is actually saying is that Lucius had all the
advantages of birth, position, and education (i.e. things that usually
benefit people), but his curiosity was so strong that it overrode even
these positive attributes and led to him becoming an ass. Mithras no
more condemns education than he does noble birth or social position. Far
more suspicious is Mithras' call for Lucius to 'submit to the
voluntary yoke of service' (ministerii iugum subi voluntarium;
11,15,5), the wording of which cannot but recall Lucius' negative
experience as a beast of burden. This expression indeed foreshadows
Lucius' relationship to the gods in the latter half of Book 11 (cf.
iugum subeo; 11,30,1). But in making this recommendation, Mithras acts
in accordance with Isis' command that Lucius worship her until his
last breath (11,6,5). This does not expose Mithras as a fraudulent
priest like those of the Dea Syria.
The cost of Lucius' initiation is said to connect Mithras to
the Syrian priests, but several points undermine this suggestion. First,
Lucius pays for his initiation not in full but only as much as he is
able to give (11,24,6). Second, Lucius states that he was not able to
reward Mithras as much as he deserved (11,25,7). (40) Nevertheless,
Lucius is not impoverished by the initiation because he can afford to
relocate to Rome afterwards. (41) Moreover, since the details of the
amount Lucius was able to give are lacking, these passages, though
admitting expense, do not depict a cult mercilessly exploiting Lucius
for everything he has. (42) Indeed, Mithras is not annoyed by
Lucius' humble offering; on the contrary, the two embrace and
Lucius now views the high priest as a father (meum iam parentem). Thus,
the last image of Mithras displays a degree of affection not to be found
with Asinius in Rome.
This positive presentation of Mithras' character is aided by
an absence of satirical physical description. Whereas other priests in
the Metamorphoses receive arguably unflattering, stereotypical
descriptions, Mithras is given no physical description other than that
he wears linen and carries a sistrum. (43) Indeed, Mithras is only
broadly associated with a satirical theme in that he takes payment for
his services; yet he is content to receive less reward than was agreed,
which contrasts with the large fee required for the services of Zatchlas
(2,28,1). Furthermore, whilst the expenses of initiation are included,
they are laid down by Isis (11,22,3), not demanded by Mithras.
Therefore, it is difficult to maintain that Mithras is to be understood
as an insincere, greedy, or inept priest of a type whom the reader is to
understand as being satirised.
By contrast, the characterisation of Asinius is dubious at best.
This is most evident in his name, status, and deformity. The name
'Asinius' is significant to Lucius because he believes that it
is a favourable omen relating to his retransformation (11,27,7). This
conclusion, however, recalls Lucius' trait of misapprehension since
the name could just as easily refer to his original transformation from
man into ass (symbolising his foolishness), thus becoming a name of ill
omen. (44) Indeed, that the name recalls the animal which is so hateful
to Isis (11,6,2) creates uncertainty about his suitability.
This uncertainty is reinforced by Asinius' rank. As
apastophorus, Asinius is significantly lower in status than Mithras the
summus sacerdos. (45) Fittingly, Asinius is shown only to hang garlands
around the statue of Osiris (in his dream at 11,27,9), whereas Mithras
actually conducts a public ceremony (11,16,6). Egelhaaf-Gaiser notes
that the elevation of a pastophorus to the role of a priest (i.e.
functioning as a mystagogue) is strange, but attributes this to literary
licence, suggesting that Asinius anticipates 'the final image of
the bald-headed Lucius on the board of the college ofpastophori .'
(46) Of course, if one views Asinius as an inadequate figure, then this
identification becomes uncomplimentary for Lucius. (47) Indeed, a clue
to Asinius' character could lie in the role of the pastophorus as a
collector of alms--that is, the taking of material wealth as a measure
of religious devotion. (48)
The most striking detail of Asinius' characterisation,
however, is his deformity. The left ankle of Asinius is 'slightly
twisted' (paululum reflexo) causing him to walk with a limp
(11,27,5). It is therefore surprising that he holds a priestly position
at all, since priests were required to be pure of body and mind. (49) In
the Metamorphoses, the adjectivepurus is used (without irony) only in
association with the cult of Isis (11,10,1; 11,16,6; 11,21,9). (50)
Associating purity with the cult of Isis only to have a deformed figure
initiate Lucius is as conspicuous as it is disconcerting. In classical
literature, deformity and mobility impairment often indicate a negative
character. (51) Significantly, Plutarch describes Typhon (Seth) as the
part of the body that is 'destructible, diseased and
disorderly' ([TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]; De Is. et Os.
49,371b). (52) When one considers this along with Asinius' name, a
cognate to the animal that symbolises Typhon, then it seems that Osiris
has made an unfit choice for Asinius to succeed Mithras. Thus when
combined, Asinius' ominous name, lower status, and conspicuous
deformity diminish the standard of Lucius' religious experience.
Importantly, a detail near the conclusion of Psyche's
adventure relates to both Asinius' name as well as his deformity.
Having been sent on a quest to the Underworld by Venus, Psyche is
informed that she will encounter 'a lame, wood-carrying ass with a
similarly disabled driver' (claudum asinum lignorum gerulum cum
agasone simili; 6,18,4). (53) She is instructed to ignore the driver
when he asks for her help to pick up sticks. This seemingly harmless
(yet somehow perilous), lame duo, consisting of a man and an ass, may
anticipate the unthreatening and lamepastophorus whose name recalls
Lucius' asinine form. The connection is strengthened when one
considers that Osiris was the Egyptian god of the dead, and Lucius does
meet Asinius on his path to this chthonic god just as Psyche will meet
the lame ass and man on her journey to the Underworld. This could serve
as warning to a cautious reader that the path Lucius takes by listening
to Asinius (and the demanding gods behind him) should be avoided.
In addition to the contrasting presentation of Mithras and Asinius,
the initiations of the two priests differ with respect to the dream
material preceding them. In the dream featuring Mithras at 11,20, the
high priest generously offers gifts to Lucius that represent his
returned possessions. But in the dream preceding his third initiation
(11,29,4-5), Lucius is told that he must be initiated again to receive a
new cloak because his old one is still in Cenchreae (evidently, this
possession cannot be returned). (54) For the second initiation, the
dream of Asinius placing sacred objects near Lucius' household
altar is said to prefigure a banquet Lucius is to provide for the
faithful, showing another expense (11,27,1). (55) Moreover, Asinius is
told in his dream that he ought to initiate Lucius because, in doing so,
he shall receive a 'great reward' (grande compendium;
11,27,9). That money is used to entice him strongly suggests that he
does not practice asceticism. (56) Furthermore, while Isis' dream
instruction to Mithras contains detailed and accurate information about
Lucius, Osiris' instruction to Asinius is vague and, taken
directly, contains incorrect information; Lucius is a Greek from Corinth
not a Madauran from North Africa. Nevertheless, since the dream is
god-sent, the relevance of this remarkable detail requires closer
investigation.
Significantly, Asinius Marcellus was not the first to speak of a
poor Madauran man. As can be deduced from the Apologia, the prosecution
in the case against Apuleius portrayed him as having once been
impoverished and hailing from a backwater town (Apol. 17-24). (57) A
backwater hometown would provide few opportunities for advancement and
thus carries the connotation that a poor Apuleius left to find
advancement at the expense of others; and so, being clever and familiar
with the esoteric, he advanced by means of magia, which he used to
seduce Pudentilla in order to acquire her fortune (cf. carmina et
venena; Apol. 69,4). Before he addresses the charge of being a magus
proper, Apuleius confronts the accusations of former poverty and a
backwater origin sequentially. In true Cynic fashion, he explains that a
philosopher cannot be poor because poverty is measured by one's
desire for material things--thus a content but poor man is in fact
wealthier than a rich man who continually desires more (Apol. 20). (58)
For good measure, Apuleius throws the accusations of a backwater origin,
greed, and former poverty back against one of the men behind the
prosecution, Aemilianus (Apol. 23, 24). So it is significant that
Asinius, who literally dreams of receiving wealth for initiating Lucius,
applies to Lucius two of the things laid against Apuleius by the
prosecutor who, according to the Apologia, figuratively dreams of
receiving reward for prosecuting Apuleius.
Further thematic ties link Aemilianus of the Apologia to the
Metamorphoses. Apuleius claims that Aemilianus is nicknamed
'Charon' because he gained his wealth through the deaths of
several relatives (Apol. 23). In the tale of Cupid and Psyche, Charon is
said to do nothing unpaid (nec ... quicquam gratuito facit), hence greed
is living amongst the dead (ergo et inter mortuos avaritia vivit;
6,18,6). Moreover, Aemilianus is said to have ploughed his small plot
with one ass (solus uno asello ... exarabas; Apol. 23). This links him
to the lame driver (with the lame ass), whom Psyche is told to ignore in
the Underworld. This duo has already been connected by name and
disability with Asinius--the one who, like Aemilianus, mentions
Apuleius' homeland and Lucius' poverty. If Aemilianus and
Asinius are to be linked by these themes, on top of providing another
connection between the Apologia and Metamorphoses, this would further
degrade Asinius' character, distancing him from the ascetic
Mithras.
But while Asinius appears to have a defective character in addition
to his deformed body, this does not confirm that he is a charlatan
priest like Philebus. First, Asinius is unknown to Lucius when he dreams
about a second initiation. This shows that Asinius cannot have
influenced Lucius' dreams towards receiving initiation, nor who is
to perform the rites. Second, Lucius is poor when Asinius meets him and
so not a suitable target to con (cf. 11,28,1). The false prophet
Alexander, by contrast, dupes a wealthy and superstitious Roman senex,
Rutilianus (Lucian Alex. 30-35), and the Syrian priests travel the
country fleecing folk by the townful. It is not until after Lucius'
initiations that he wins fame and an income as a lawyer--gaining
financial security after being duped makes little sense if the object is
to show a victim of clerical deceit.
Moreover, the typical traits from the satire of avaricious, foreign
priests are difficult to assign to Asinius. First, Asinius has a Roman
name, thus is not foreign. Second, like Mithras, his shaven-head is not
highlighted. Third, while Asinius is promised by Osiris to be greatly
rewarded for initiating Lucius, the reader is not shown the value of
this 'great reward' or him even receiving it; the priests of
the Dea Syria, by contrast, are shown to greedily accept their
ill-gotten gains (avidis animis conradentes omnia, 8,28,6; 9,8,1;
9,8,6). Most importantly, it is Lucius' dreams--not the
priests--that instruct him about, and later justify, his initiations.
(59) Yet if the priests were the target of the satire, being avaricious
and manipulative, one would expect that they would be in focus during
each step along the path of Lucius' induction. On the contrary, the
priestly element is entirely missing from the third initiation--there is
no double-dream with the priest who will initiate him. It is only Lucius
and his god-sent dreams that are highlighted.
This divine element creates the biggest problem with the view that
Book 11 is a satire on priestly corruption and youthful gullibility. The
satire in Books 8-9 and in Lucian's Alexander act as an expose of
disreputable and impious behaviour; but if the gods are complicit in a
religious scam, this changes the very nature of such satire. For
example, if the Syrian goddess was shown to be instructing Philebus and
his troupe, then the priests would cease to be corrupt or false;
instead, they would be men carrying out the orders of a thieving
goddess. Likewise, the satire in Alexander would fall flat if the
prophet were actually receiving instruction from a god called Glycon.
The humour of such satire lies in the affectation of the priests: they
make a grand spectacle of their religious devotion, but they are really
thieving degenerates. (60) They cannot be both obedient to their gods
and impious thieves because the humour of affectation disappears, the
focus instead falling upon the corrupt divinities. Similarly,
Lucius--regardless of his previous gullibility--cannot be gullible for
obeying what are clearly commands from the gods. And since neither
Mithras nor Asinius is shown to benefit personally from initiating
Lucius, the focus of the satire must lie elsewhere. The only character
to be laid bare to such scrutiny is Lucius.
The intertext of Metamorphoses 11,27,9 with Apologia 17-24,
discussed above, draws a comparison between 'Apuleius' and
Lucius. (61) The result is not favourable to Lucius. In the Apologia,
Apuleius defends himself against the charge of magia by claiming that
his peculiar interests all relate to him being a philosopher. (62) By
contrast, Lucius seeks out magic in a less than intellectual manner
(nimis cupidus; 2,1,1; 2,6,6). (63) Additionally, while Apuleius was
falsely accused, Lucius, who did use magic, was protected from such
accusations by Isis (11,6,4; 11,13,6). (64) Another point of contrast is
Apuleius' ability to keep a secret. In the Apologia he makes a
point not to reveal the nature of the objects he received after
initiation or the name of the divine king he is said to worship (Apol.
55, 64). Lucius, however, lets too much information slip when relating
his first initiation (11,23,6). (65) Regarding appearances, Apuleius
counters the accusation of being handsome and using a mirror by
emphasising his unkempt appearance (Apol. 4), all while demonstrating
his polymathy during his speech. (66) Significantly, Apuleius attributes
Lucius with good looks (1,23,3; 2,2,9) and yet leaves him full of
character flaws (curiosity, gluttony, anger, and lust). (67) Indeed,
Keulen views Lucius as the type of immoral man from Apuleius' de
Platone, with his unquenchable thirst for pleasure, lack of
self-knowledge, and fixation on appearances (De dog. Plat. 2,16
[242-243]). (68) Similarly, Kenney argues that Lucius does not gain
wisdom in Book 11. (69) Thus, the identification of Apuleius and Lucius
at 11,27,9, rather than showing unity, fixes Lucius as Apuleius'
fictional alter-ego who is but a debased parody of the original. (70)
In addition to the contrast of 'Apuleius' and Lucius, the
Apologia and Metamorphoses differ in their treatment of the relationship
between philosophy and religion. Van Nuffelen indicates that in the
Apologia, religion and philosophy are intrinsically linked, whereas in
the Metamorphoses, religion is devoid of philosophy. (71) Indeed, he
goes on to state that, like Plutarch in de Iside, Apuleius'
Apologia advocates the use of philosophy to check religion, which helps
to avoid superstition. (72) Unfortunately for Lucius, superstition (not
to mention its requisite, unbalanced emotion) is crucial to his
characterisation in Book 11.
Lucius' emotions are a driving force behind his initiations
and his whole religious experience. (73) Finkelpearl accepts the
opposition to Lucius' philosophical progress when compared to the
Platonic approach to Isiac religion in Plutarch. (74) Instead, she
argues that, in Book 11, Apuleius presents the mystical nature of Isiac
religion using an emotional approach. (75) A positive interpretation of
Lucius' emotionally driven religious awakening, however, is
problematic because Lucius' emotional volatility is crucial to his
initiation into magic as well as his initiations into the cult of Isis.
(76) Preceding Lucius' botched initiation into magic, he encounters
the animated wineskins (2,32). This leads to the humiliating ordeal of
the Risus festival, during and after which he is an emotional wreck.
(77) A similar emotional rollercoaster can be seen to start when Lucius
flees from the amphitheatre in Corinth and ends with him as a joyful
pastophorus in Rome. (78)
This illustrates a connection between Lucius' strong and
constantly shifting emotions and his various initiations. In addition,
it reinforces the idea of Lucius' intense emotional--one might say
irrational--link to Isis. This is exactly the same connection that
Lucius had to Photis. Indeed, Lucius uses the same phrase,
inremunerabili beneficio ('an unrepayable favour'), with
regards to Photis using magic on him (3,22,5) as he does when thanking
Isis for saving him from his asinine state (11,24,5). Thus, Lucius
demonstrates no development but merely fastens on a divine recipient for
his emotional attachment. (79) Such overbearing emotion was discouraged
by philosophers, including Apuleius (De dog. Plat. 2,4 [225]). One might
object that Lucius displays genuine joy at 11,30, which contrasts with
his former misery. Seneca, however, indicates that misplaced joy
disrupts a rational mind by contrasting the frivolous joy of the masses
with the profound joy of philosophy. (80)
Overpowering emotion was not just viewed negatively for
subordinating rational thought, but also because, with respect to the
gods, it led to superstition. (81) Indeed, Van Nuffelen states that, to
Plutarch, 'superstition is essentially a misinterpretation of
religion by the uneducated.' (82) This would suggest that, despite
his schooling, Lucius approaches religion in an uneducated manner--just
as he approached magic. For instance, when Lucius rents an apartment in
the temple precinct, he does so in order to be 'an ever-present
worshipper of the great deity' (numinis magni cultor inseparabilis;
11,19,1). Plutarch states that whilst shrines and altars are sanctuaries
even to social outcasts, they are places of fear and hope to the
superstitious man, who cannot be parted from them (De sup. 4,166e-f).
Indeed, the idea of slavery to Isis in order to escape Blind Fortuna is
fundamental to Lucius' religious experience. Likewise, the themes
of emotion, enslavement, and escape from distress, all feature heavily
in the superstitious man (De sup. 5,167B). Furthermore, Lucius' two
most prevalent emotions in Book 11, awe and anxiety, are united in the
superstitious man (De sup. 3,165d).
Indeed, fear is the reason why Lucius never disregards a dream
command, hence his obedience when selling his clothes to pay for his
second initiation (11,28,5) and his madness (insania) whilst fretting
about his third initiation (11,29,3). (83) Lucius often discusses his
dreams with others (11,27,1, 11,27,6; 11,30,1), which is stereotypical
behaviour of the superstitious man (Thphr. Char. 16,11). When he has
doubts, it is his dreams that provide the answers. For instance, when he
is afraid that he will be unable to remain chaste and guard against
life's misfortunes, he does not come to an answer using sound
reasoning; instead, Isis sends him a dream (11,20) that fires his desire
to be initiated (11,21,2). (84) Later, when Lucius doubts his own
priests, he does not overcome these suspicions with rational thinking;
instead, he is instructed by the 'friendly phantom' not to
fear and is offered a bizarre explanation (11,29,4-5). (85) Similarly,
Lucius does not decide to go to Rome after self-deliberation; instead,
the goddess commands him and he hastily obliges (11,26,1). Thus,
Lucius' dependence on his dreams and fear to disappoint the gods
becomes clear. Likewise, the superstitious man is governed by unfounded
fear both waking and sleeping (De sup. 3,165E-F; 3,166C). (86)
Lucius' mode of worship also reflects that of the
unreflective, superstitious man. When Lucius tells his story to his
relatives (11,19,1), he does so not because he has reflected upon it,
but 'out of courtesy' (ex officio), performing this
'quickly' (pro<pere>) (87) so that he may return to his
'greatest pleasure' (gratissimum). That is, 'gazing
upon' (conspectum) Isis. Moreover, having wept melodramatically
with his own face pressed to the statue of Isis' feet (11,24,7), he
promises to keep the vision of the goddess's face close to his
heart (11,25,6). Plutarch, however, considers the focus upon mere
representations of gods as the product of superstition (De sup.
6,167d-e).
Another trait found in the superstitious man is the need for
purification with seawater (Theoph. Char. 16,13). (88) Indeed, Plutarch
makes a special mention of those who act irrationally because of their
dreams, including dipping themselves in the ocean (De sup. 3,165f-166a).
Significantly, after waking from sleep and being awed by sight of the
moon, Lucius' first act is to purify himself in the sea, making
sure to dip himself seven times because of the number's
significance to Pythagoras (11,1,4). (89)
Therefore, it is clear that many traits of the superstitious man
can be found in Lucius. Yet one of the central aspects, as presented by
Plutarch, appears to be absent from Lucius' characterisation. This
is the unhappiness that arises from the superstitious man's secret
hatred and fear of the gods, to whom he attributes every evil he suffers
(Plut. De sup. 11,170e). The explanation for this lies in the
identification of two Fortunae, one Blind and the other Seeing
(11,15,3). Naturally, Lucius reserves his hatred for the former as the
cause of his ills, whereas the latter he views as his saviour. (90) Yet
by blaming Fortuna, Lucius still conforms to the trait of the
superstitious man in taking no responsibility for the actions that led
to his misfortunes. (91) Moreover, whilst Lucius no longer fears Blind
Fortuna, he is still god-fearing when it comes to Isis and Osiris,
obeying their every command because he fears losing their support.
The account of Lucius, then, portrays the superstitious man from
his own perspective. Consequently, Isis and Osiris are presented as the
gods of the superstitious man come to life. So, whilst Lucius'
dreams are truly god-sent, they help to depict an irrational man whose
continued emotionality reveals a lack of philosophical depth. Equally,
Lucius is as much a slave to the gods as is the superstitious man,
except that by being saved from his (literal) slavery as an ass, he
actually enjoys his new (figurative) slavery as an Isiac. Thus the gods
have ensnared him more comprehensively than Photis ever could and, like
Pamphile's apprentice, they have transformed him into something he
did not anticipate becoming: a superstitious pastophorus. The cure for
Lucius' asshood was roses; it seems that, as far as Plutarch is
concerned, the cure for his superstitious enslavement would be a bouquet
of philosophical insights. For despite his schooling (and ancestry),
Lucius approaches religion in an uneducated manner--just as he had
approached magic.
Thus, Lucius and Apuleius are related, but they are not the same.
This is the humour behind the Madaurensem passage: it evokes the
'real' Apuleius, but this only highlights the inadequacy of
the fictional version. According to the Apologia, Apuleius is interested
in substance, whereas Lucius is interested in mere appearances. This is
evident when Lucius goes out of his way to purchase the books containing
Egyptian hieroglyphics with the help of friends (meos socios coemenda
procuro; 11,23,1). He is driven by his curiosity for religious items and
will pay money he does not have for them, betraying the value he places
on the trappings of the cult rather than the deeper meaning. (92) This
is important when considering Lucius' dubious second and third
initiations, for which he shaves his head, and the last image of him as
a bald pastophorus happily going about his duties (11,30,5). In this
way, Lucius merely imitates the image of a wise and ascetic Isiac priest
(cf. Plut. De Is. et Os. 3,352c). One might object that Lucius joyfully
sporting a shaven head would have caused great embarrassment to the shy
Lucius who blushes in front of his aunt (2,2,7), indicating that he has
changed. Indeed, Lucius has changed, but only in that he now values
baldness as a member of the Isiac priesthood. And yet his pride in
publicly asserting this fact is a clear demonstration that, contrary to
the idea that Lucius distinguishes appearance from what is important,
his appearance is all important to him. (93) Thus Lucius' decision
to display his shaven pate is not a conscious rejection of former lust
for Photis or her hair, because at no point has he reflected upon this.
(94) To Lucius, his stereotypically bald head gives him status in the
eyes of the god and goddess he so adores. He has not reached
enlightenment; he just wants everyone to know that he is one of the
chosen of Isis and Osiris. (95) The final image of Lucius as a proudly
bald pastophorus symbolises his whole conversion; outwardly he has
changed--he is a priest and a successful lawyer who has divine
sponsors--but internally Lucius is still the same because he values the
trappings of the cult, such as the hieroglyphic holy books (11,23,1),
his robes of initiation (11,24,3), and now his new tonsure. The ultimate
irony is that his insight has remained unchanged as a bald pastophorus
just as it remained unchanged when he transformed into an ass (3,26,1).
Consequently, he is no wiser and appears to be something that he is not.
(96)
The divine experience of Lucius, therefore, is instrumental to the
satire of un-philosophical approaches to religion. (97) Fittingly, the
gods are also debased. For example, Plutarch says that the name
'Isis' is Greek, implying a link to the verb [TEXT NOT
REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] 'to know' (De Is. et Os. 2,351f). (98)
But in the Metamorphoses, Isis does not require Lucius to attain
knowledge; she only desires the same slavish worship and obedience which
he had earlier offered to Photis (11,6,5; 3,22,5). (99) This desire for
irrational devotion rather than wise followers is reflected in the
decision to favour an (internally) unchanged Lucius and to select an
unworthy Asinius to succeed the wise Mithras. For while Lucius is too
caught up in surface details to perceive the difference between these
priests, the gods, who should be able to tell the difference, do not
appear to care so long as Lucius remains a devout, un-philosophical
servant.
In summary, this paper has endeavoured to illustrate that
interpreting a satire of priestly deceit and religious gullibility in
Book 11 is flawed. First, the double-dreams of Lucius and his priests
have to be true to make sense of the many concurrences between dream and
reality. Second, this involvement of the gods removes the key ingredient
to satire involving deceitful priests, namely, religious affectation.
Third, viewing Lucius as naively believing self-generated dreams creates
inconsistency between Apuleius employing meaningless dreams in Book 11
and meaningful dreams in Books 1-10. Instead, if one understands a
Petronian use of literary dreams throughout, Apuleius is freed of this
charge. Moreover, the use of god-sent dreams is entirely in keeping with
a narrative of magical and miraculous transformations.
The dreams themselves are not necessary to illustrate Lucius'
eagerness for initiation, for he and Mithras explicitly note this
enthusiasm (11,21). Instead, the dreams form part of a larger strategy
to characterise Lucius as superstitious for his un-philosophical
approach to religion and the gods as deficient for not requiring
anything better. Thus, the doubt Lucius experiences when he is called
for a third initiation is not intended to flag the priests as
untrustworthy but to show that Lucius would sooner question his priests
than his dreams, which--unsurprisingly--replace rational thought in
providing the answer. Similarly, the financial theme, previously
understood to hint at Lucius' exploitation, is better explained as
demonstrating priestly decline through Lucius' (and Asinius')
non-ascetic concerns, reflected in the presentation of his secular
career alongside his religious one. Therefore, one should not be
surprised that Lucius misconstrues Mithras' speech about his
unbound curiosity exposing him to the vicissitudes of wicked Fortune
because he fails to condemn his past behaviour throughout the narrative
and still blames Photis (and Fortuna) for his transformation.
Thus, the satire has a philosophical point behind the ironic
presentation of Lucius' religious 'awakening'. For, as
well as offering entertainment, Apuleius advocates a philosophical
approach to Isiac religion similar to Plutarch in De Iside. Apuleius,
however, makes his point by portraying its opposite, namely, an
unenlightened approach based upon dream-visions and a lack of
introspection. And yet, in the end, Lucius finds success in the law
court and in his promotion to the rank ofpastophorus. It is thus a
nightmarish vision of a world in which financial input without
philosophical development can secure religious advancement even in the
eyes of the gods. Indeed, the choice to supplant the exemplary Mithras
with the lame and suspiciously mercenary Asinius, not to mention the
unexpected and poorly justified second and third initiations, suggests
that Isis and Osiris are no less flawed than the other characters of the
novel. Equally, the choice of showing special favour to Lucius
illustrates that they care not for piety so much as irrational and
obsessive worship--just as the superstitious man is obsessed by his
relationship with the divine, dictating his every action. These, then,
represent the gods of the superstitious man. Moreover, the revelation
that Lucius 'is' Apuleius is tainted because it is included in
the dream of the unworthy Asinius. The comparison to Apuleius in the
Apologia fixes Lucius as his debased alter-ego. Thus, the joy Lucius
finds is misplaced--he has not achieved an enlightened state. This is
what informs his baldness and reveals that he, like a charlatan, wishes
to affect the appearance of the Isiac priest due to its perceived
importance to him. In the end, Apuleius demonstrates to the reader that
the philosophising ass indeed makes for an asinine philosopher. (100)
Bibliography
Ahl, F. 1985. Metaformations, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Bartsch, S. 1989. Decoding the Ancient Novel: The Reader and the
Role of Description in Heliodorus and Achilles Tatius, Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
Branham, B. 1984. 'The Comic as Critic: Revenging Epicurus: A
Study of Lucian's Art of Comic Narrative', ClAnt 3, 143-163.
Carlisle, D. P. C. 2008. 'Vigilans somniabar: Some Narrative
Uses of Dreams in Apuleius' Metamorphoses ' in: W. Riess
(ed.), Paideia at Play: Learning and Wit in Apuleius, Groningen:
Barkhuis, 215-232.
Dowden, K. 1994. 'The Roman Audience of the Golden Ass',
in: J. Tatum (ed.), The Search for the Ancient Novel, Baltimore: John
Hopkins University Press, 419-434.
Edsall, M. 1996. The Role and Characterization of the Priest in the
Ancient Novel. Diss. Columbia University.
Egelhaaf-Gaiser, U. 2012. 'The Gleaming Pate of the
Pastophorus: Masquerade or Embodied Lifestyle?', in: W. Keulen and
U. Egelhaaf-Gaiser (eds.), Aspects of Apuleius' Golden Ass 3: The
Isis Book, Leiden: Brill, 42-72.
Finkelpearl, E. 1990. 'Psyche, Aeneas, and an Ass: Apuleius,
Metamorphoses 6.10-6.21', TAPhA 120, 333-348.
--2004. 'The Ends of the Metamorphoses Apuleius Metamorphoses
11.26-11.30', in: M. Zimmerman and R. van der Paardt (eds.),
Metamorphic Reflections: Essays presented to Ben Hijmans, Leuven:
Peeters, 319-342.
--2012. 'Egyptian Religion in Met. 11 and Plutarch's DIO:
Culture, Philosophy, and the Ineffable', in: W. Keulen and U.
Egelhaaf-Gaiser (eds.), Aspects of Apuleius' Golden Ass 3: The Isis
Book, Leiden: Brill, 86-106.
Frangoulidis, S. 2008. Witches, Isis, and Narrative: Approaches to
Magic in Apuleius' Metamorphoses, Berlin--New York: de Gruyter.
Gaisser, J. H. 2008. The Fortunes of Apuleius and The Golden Ass: A
Study in Transmission and Reception, Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton
University Press.
Gollnick, J. 1999. The Religious Dreamworld of Apuleius'
Metamorphoses: Recovering a Forgotten Hermeneutic, Waterloo, Ontario:
Wilfrid Laurier University Press.
Griffiths, J. G. 1975. Apuleius of Madauros: The Isis-Book
(Metamorphoses, BookXI), Leiden: Brill.
Hanson, J. S. 1980. 'Dreams and Visions in the Graeco-Roman
World and Early Christianity', in: W. Haase (ed.), ANRW 2,23,2,
Berlin - New York: de Gruyter, 1325-1427.
Harris, W. 2003. 'Roman Opinions about the Truthfulness of
Dreams', JRS 93, 18-34.
Harrison, S. J. 1996. 'Apuleius' Metamorphoses', in:
G. Schmeling (ed.), The Novel in the Ancient World. Leiden: Brill,
491-516.
--2000. Apuleius: A Latin Sophist, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
--, J. L. Hilton, and V. J. C. Hunink 2000. 'Apuleius:
Rhetorical Works, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
--2012. 'Narrative Subversion and Religious Satire in
Metamorphoses 11', in: W. Keulen and U. Egelhaaf-Gaiser (eds.),
Aspects of Apuleius' Golden Ass 3: The Isis Book, Leiden: Brill,
73-85.
Heiserman, A. 1977. The Novel before the Novel: Essays and
Discussions about the Beginnings of Prose Fiction in the West, Chicago:
Chicago University Press.
Hijmans, B. L. JR. et al. (eds.) 1985. ApuleiusMadaurensis:
Metamorphoses Book VIII: Text, Introduction and Commentary, Groningen:
Egbert Forsten. (= GCA 1985)
Hindermann, J. 2009. 'The Elegaic Ass: The Concept of
Servitivm Amoris in Apuleius' Metamorphoses', Ramus 38, 75-84.
Hunink, V. J. C. 2002. 'The Date of Apuleius'
Metamorphoses', in: P. Defosse (ed.), Hommages a Carl Deroux. II.
Prose et Linguistique, Medecine, Brussels: Latomus, 224-235. (Collection
Latomus, 267)
--2006. 'Dreams in Apuleius' Metamorphoses', in: A.
P. M. H. Lardinois, et al. (eds.), Land of Dreams: Greek and Roman
Studies in Honour of A. H. M. Kessels, Leiden--Danvers: Brill, 18-31.
Kenney, E. J. 1990. Apuleius, Cupid and Psyche. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
--2003. 'In the Mill with Slaves: Lucius Looks Back in
Gratitude', TAPhA 133, 159-192.
Kessels, A. H. M. 1973. Studies on the Dream in Greek Literature,
Hes Publishers: Utrecht.
Keulen, W. H. 2003. 'Comic Invention and Superstitious Frenzy
in Apuleius' Metamorphoses: The Figure of Socrates as an Icon of
Satirical Self-exposure', AJPh 124, 107-135.
--2006. 'Adamussim congruentia: Measuring the Intellectual in
Apuleius'. in: W. H. Keulen, et al. (eds.), Lectiones Scrupulosae:
Essays on the Text and Interpretation of A-puleius' Metamorphoses
in Honour of Maaike Zimmerman, Groningen: Barkhuis, 168-202.
--2007. Apuleius Madaurensis: Metamorphoses Book I: Text,
Introduction and Commentary. Groningen: Egbert Forsten. (= GCA 2007)
--and U. Egelhaaf-Gaiser (eds.) 2012. Aspects of Apuleius'
Golden Ass Vol. 3: The Isis Book, Leiden: Brill.
Kirichenko, A. 2008. 'Satire, Propaganda, and Pleasure of
Reading', HSPh 104, 339-371.
--2010. A Comedy of Storytelling: Theatricality and Narrative in
Apuleius' Golden Ass, Heidelberg: Winter.
Lateiner, D. 2000. 'Marriage and the Return of Spouses in
Apuleius' Metamorposes', CJ 95, 313-332.
Libby, B. B. 2011. 'Moons, Smoke, and Mirrors in
Apuleius' Portrayal of Isis', AJPh 132, 301-322.
Long, A. A. 1986. Hellenistic Philosophy: Stoics, Epicureans,
Sceptics. 2nd ed. Berkley: California University Press.
Massey, I. 1976. The Gaping Pig: Literature and Metamorphosis,
Berkley: California University Press.
May, R. 2006. Apuleius and Drama: The Ass on Stage, Oxford:
Clarendon.
Murgatroyd, P. 2004. 'The ending of Apuleius'
Metamorphoses', CQ 54, 319-321.
Nicolini, L. 2012. 'In Spite of Isis: Wordplay in
Metamorphoses XI an Answer to Wyste Keulen', in: W. Keulen and U.
Egelhaaf-Gaiser (eds.), Aspects of Apuleius' Golden Ass 3: The Isis
Book, Leiden: Brill, 28-41.
Panayotakis, S. 1997. 'Insidiae Veneris: Lameness, Old Age and
Deception in the Underworld Apul. Met. 6, 18-19', in: H. Hofmann
and M. Zimmerman (eds.), Groningen Colloquia on the Novel 8, 23-40.
Platt, V. 2011. 'Dream Visions and Cult Images in Second
Sophistic Literature', in: Facing the Gods: Epiphany and
Representation in Graeco-Roman Art, Literature and Religion,
Cambridge--New York: Cambridge University Press, 253-292.
Rives, J. B. 2003. 'Magic in Roman Law: The Reconstruction of
a Crime', ClAnt 22, 313-339.
Schlam, C. C. 1992. The Metamorphoses of Apuleius: On Making an Ass
of Oneself, Chapel Hill: North Carolina University Press--London:
Duckworth.
Schmeling, G. and S. Montiglio 2006. 'Riding the Waves of
Passion: an Exploration of an Image of Appetites in Apuleius'
Metamorphoses' in: W. H. Keulen, R. R. Nauta, and S. Panayotakis
(eds.), Lectiones Scrupulosae: Essays on the Text and Interpretation of
Apuleius' Metamorphoses in Honour of Maaike Zimmerman, Groningen:
Barkhuis, 28-41.
Shumate, N. J. 1996. Crisis and Conversion in
Apuleius'Metamorphoses, Ann Arbor: Michigan University Press.
--1999. 'Apuleius' Metamorphoses: the Inserted
Tales' in: H. Hofmann (ed.), Latin Fiction: the Latin Novel in
Context, London: Routledge, 96-106.
Smith, W. S. 1993. 'Style and Character in the Golden Ass:
"Suddenly an Apposite Appearance"', in: W. Haase (ed.),
ANRW 2,34,2, Berlin - New York: de Gruyter, 1575-1599.
--2009. 'Apuleius and the New Testament: Lucius'
Conversion Experience', AncNarr 7, 51-73.
Van der Stockt, L. 2012. 'Plutarch and Apuleius: Laborious
Routes to Isis', in: W. Keulen and U. Egelhaaf-Gaiser (eds.),
Aspects of Apuleius' Golden Ass 3: The Isis Book, Leiden: Brill,
168-182.
Van Nuffelen, P. 2011. 'Dio Chrysostom, Apuleius and the
Rhetoric of Ancient Wisdom', in: Rethinking the Gods: Philosophical
Readings of Religion in the Post-Hellenistic Period, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 84-100.
Van Mal-Maeder, D. 1997. 'Lector, indende: laetaberis: the
Enigma of the Last Book of Apuleius' Metamorphoses', in: H.
Hofmann and M. Zimmerman (eds.), Groningen Colloquia on the Novel 8,
Groningen: Egbert Forsten, 87-118.
Walsh, P. G. 1999. Apuleius: The Golden Ass. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Weiss, C. G. 1998. Literary Turns: the Representation of Conversion
in Aelius Aristides' Heiroi Logoi and Apuleius' Metamorphoses,
Diss. Yale.
Winkler, J. J. 1985. Auctor and Actor: A Narratological Reading of
Apuleius' Golden Ass, Berkeley - London: California University
Press.
Winter, T. N. 2006. 'Apology as Prosecution: The Trial of
Apuleius', Faculty Publications, Classics and Religious Studies
Department. Paper 4. http://digitalcommons.unl.edu/ classicsfacpub/4
(Electronic version of Winter, T. N. 1968. Apology as Prosecution: The
Trial of Apuleius. Diss. University of Nebraska).
Zimmerman, M., et al. (eds.) 2004. Apuleius Madaurensis:
Metamorphoses Books IV 28-35, V and VI1-24: the tale of Cupid and
Psyche, Groningen: Egbert Forsten. (= GCA 2004)
--2006. 'Echoes of Roman Satire in Apuleius'
Metamorphoses', in: R. R. Nauta (ed.), Desultoria Scientia: Genre
in Apuleius' Metamorphoses and Related Texts, Leuven: Peeters,
87-104.
NATHAN WATSON
University of Otago
(1) This question is posed in Keulen and Egelhaaf-Gaisser (eds.)
2012, vii.
(2) Winkler 1985, 179, 227; Shumate 1996, 310-328 and 1999, 96-105;
Hunink 2006, 26-31. Kirichenko 2010, 6-7 proposes multiple plots
(including religious and satiric plots).
(3) Carlisle 2008, 215-233 argues that Apuleius employs dreams as
the prime motivator in Lucius' religious experience to create
ambiguity, thus enabling an indeterminate ending whilst challenging the
reader to find meaning.
(4) Kirichenko 2010, 139; the second and third quotes are from
Shumate 1996, 325; Harrison 2000, 246; Zimmerman 2006, 103.
(5) The first and third quotes are from Kirichenko 2010, 138; Van
Nuffelen 2011, 95.
(6) Edsall 1996, 218-219; Weiss 1998, 95; Kirichenko 2010, 135-36.
(7) For the purpose of this paper, I shall use the terms
'true', 'meaningful', and 'god-sent'
interchangeably for dreams that are considered to have a supernatural
source; the terms 'meaningless' and 'self-generated'
will be used for dreams that are considered to have a natural source
(i.e. the mind of the dreamer).
(8) Harrison 2000, 246-248; Weiss 1998, 83-94; Kirichenko 2010,
137-138; Murgatroyd 2004, 320-321; cf. Hunink 2006, 28: 'Nocturnal
visions are almost piled up ..., which reveals perhaps more about Lucius
and his ardent desire to devote himself to Isis than about her divine
power.'
(9) Lucian depicts the falsification of god-sent dreams by a
charlatan (Alex. 49), whereas Juvenal presents the misinterpretation of
meaningless dreams as god-sent by self-deceiving followers (6,522-531).
(10) Van Mal-Maeder 1997, 102 states that Isis robs Lucius just as
Meroe robbed Socrates; similarly, Murgatroyd 2004, 320 believes that the
Judgement of Paris scene at the end of Book 10 provides the context of
'divine corruption' in Book (11) and that Lucius is ordered
about by 'master and mistress figures'. Kirichenko 2010,
138-139 also places the gods alongside the priests as making financial
demands of Lucius through more initiations. Harrison 2012, 78-79 appears
to accept that Mithras has received word about Lucius from Isis, which
indicates that the goddess does send some dreams.
(11) Cf. Gollnick 1999, 74; Hunink 2006, 24; Carlisle 2008, 232.
For a general discussion of dream divination in antiquity, see Hanson
1980, 1325-1427 and Harris 2003, 18-34. On dream-visions in Aristides,
Pausanias, and Artemidorus, see Platt 2011, 253-292.
(12) The characters who experience dreams in Books 1-10 include
Socrates (1,18,7), Charite (4,27,1-4; 8,8,6-9), and the miller's
daughter (9,31,1-2). The characters who are only suggested to have been
dreaming include Aristomenes (1,18,2), Thelyphron (2,25-26,2), and
Lucius (3,22,2). The dreams of Books 1-10 differ from those in Book 11
in that they do not involve divine instruction. Yet they do follow
dreams in the literary tradition (see the following footnote for
examples), including communication between the dead and the living and
visions pertaining to future and contemporaneous events. All of the
dreams, save the one at 4,27, occur in sub-narratives, which could be
fictitious; this, however, does not deny the possibility of supernatural
events (such as god-sent dreams) in the world of the novel. For example,
magic features in the sub-narratives of Aristomenes and Thelyprhon as
well as in the main narrative; thus, Lucius' tale is just as
wondrous as the sub-narratives. For discussions on the dreams of Books
1-10, see Gollnick 1999, 53-67, Hunink 2006, 1925, and Carlisle 2008,
218-227.
(13) The admonitory and predictive aspect of dreams is utilized in
the Greek romances; cf. Ach. Tat. 4,1,4; 4,1,6-7; 7,12,4; Hld. 3,11,5;
5,22,1-3; Longus 1,7. Bartsch 1989, 80-108 discusses the role of dreams
in the Greek romances; cf. Harris 2003, 33. God-sent dreams also appear
in Petronius, Sat. 17,7; 104,1-3. Dream instruction is used frequently
in epic poetry; cf. Hom. II. 2,5-41; 23,65-110; Od. 4,795-841; 6,20-49;
19,535-559 (message, but not instruction); Verg. Aen. 2,270-297;
3,147-171; 4,351-353; 5,722-745; 8,26-67. For a full discussion of
dreams in Homer, see Kessels 1973.
(14) The first and second initiations are also prefigured by
double-dream sequences (first, 11,22,3; 11,22,5-6; second, 11,27,4;
11,27,9).
(15) Cf. Hunink 2006, 26-27.
(16) By contrast, the crowd want Loukios burned to death or, at
least, to explain himself (Ps.-Lucian Asinus 54).
(17) Carlisle 2008, 232, note 57 concedes that one may use
'very contorted logic' to rationalise the dreams as
meaningless, which ultimately protects Lucius from the charge of
falsifying his account. But such 'contorted logic' leaves too
many coincidences unexplained, making such a conclusion impossible to
maintain. And yet this does not mean that Lucius' tale should be
dismissed as a lie because it is, after all, a wondrous story involving
magical transformations; so its unambiguous use of supernatural dreams
is entirely consistent with the nature of the tale.
(18) Cf. Kirichenko 2010, 80 and note 38.
(19) That is to say, Lucius the narrator (or whoever the prologue
speaker might be) claims to be Greek in descent but has decided to tell
the story in Latin, giving it a Roman point of reference. If the story
ended in Greece, however, this would beg the question of why the
narrator has decided upon Latin for the story.
(20) The second initiation, not to mention the third, is
superfluous to the plot of religious salvation (see note 83, below) and
possibly to his religious requirements; Griffiths 1975, 330:
'Apuleius is at pains to justify the additional initiations in
Rome. Isis, Osiris and Sarapis all had some distinctive rites at this
time. The temples were in the name of Isis or Sarapis, but an Osirian
element was present in all the ceremonies.'
(21) Griffiths speculates that the local temple in Cenchreae
forbids the cloaks from being removed, ibid. 340. This seems an
arbitrary excuse for another initiation; cf. Libby 2011, 316.
(22) Cf. Carlisle 2008, 230.
(23) Finkelpearl 2004, 329 refers to this description as
'over-the-top' and that 'there is clearly humor in this
excess'. Libby 2011, 316: 'The god Osiris is not described in
anything like the detail that we expect, and he receives only a lukewarm
attention from Lucius'.
(24) Hunink 2006, 29; cf. Edsall 1996, 220, who notes that Book 11
ends with 'strange dreams'.
(25) Griffiths 1975, 54 and Massey 1976, 42 note that the
spirituality is tarnished by materialism.
(26) By way of contrast, the ending would have to be taken at face
value (i.e. as religiously edifying) if, after his first initiation,
Lucius summed up the last four chapters in one sentence: 'Having
returned to my home in Corinth, I was instructed by the goddess to
travel to Rome, where I embarked upon a successful rhetorical career and
joyfully advanced my way in the cults of Isis and Osiris.'
(27) Ascyltus (Petron. Sat. 10,1), Eumolpus (104,3), and possibly
Encolpius (frag. 43). For a comprehensive discussion on Epicurean dream
theory, see Long 1986, 24-25.
(28) Quartilla (Sat. 17,7-8; 18,3); Lichas and Tryphaena (104,1-2).
(29) Lichas is killed (Sat. 114,6), Tryphaena loses Giton (114,7),
and Encolpius, Ascyltus, and Giton somehow escape Quartilla (26,6).
(30) The gods who send the dreams are Priapus and the Neptune of
Baiae (a town of ill-repute; cf. Cic. Cael. 27, 35, 38, 47, 49; Sen. Ep.
51,1-4, 11-13; Prop. 1,11,27-30). The double-dream of Lichas and
Tryphaena warns them about their close proximity to Encolpius and Giton,
respectively (Sat. 104,1-2); Lichas seeks Encolpius, possibly as a
former lover (cf. 105,9-10; cf. 109,3), or possibly for seducing his
wife (113,3). Tryphaena seeks Giton, who is possibly her runaway slave
and/or lover (109,2). Similarly, Quartilla seeks the protagonists,
claiming that Priapus informed her that the cure for her malady, caused
by them spying upon her secret rites, is a nightlong orgy with them in
his honour (cf. 19,2); the possibility exists that she has fabricated
this dream to mask her own desires, which would fit her manipulative
display of tears. Lichas and Tryphaena, by contrast, are not aware that
Encolpius and Giton are aboard ship, so the report of their dreams
cannot hide an ulterior motive. And yet, if Lichas and Tryphaena can
experience god-sent dreams, it seems arbitrary to doubt Quartilla's
dream just because she is manipulative; thus, I believe that the burden
of proof lies with those who view the dream as fictitious. One might
observe that Quartilla's dream is not confirmed to be true in the
text; but this is due to the nature of the dream: it offers instruction
regarding a cure, not a premonition. That is, it does not predict
anything that can be borne out, such as the double-dream of Lichas and
Tryphaena. Kragelund 1989, 439-440, 445-446 believes that all of the
dreams are to be understood in Epicurean terms by the reader; that is,
they are self-generated erotic wish-fulfilments, not godsent. Harris
2003, 29 believes the dream-dream of Lichas and Tryphaena to be
god-sent.
(31) tam superstitione oratione Trypaena mutata... /
'Tryphaena was so moved by the superstition in [Lichas']
harangue.' (106,4).
(32) See Harrison 2000, 247; Kirichenko 2010, 138; and Libby 2011,
304.
(33) Edsall 1996, 202-219.
(34) The quotes are from ibid. 212 and 216, respectively.
(35) Edsall accepts the god-sent status of the dreams in Book 11,
ibid. 201, 203.
(36) The accusation that Mithras manipulates Lucius' dreams
(see Weiss 1998, 86) can be set aside due to the high priest's
belief in god-sent dreams, which is evident from his first double-dream
with Lucius.
(37) Libby 2011, 303.
(38) Edsall 1996, 207 argues for a contrast; cf. Griffiths 1975, 29
and GCA 1985, 252, 287.
(39) Weiss 1998, 92; Van Nuffelen 2011, 97.
(40) Edsall 1996, 213.
(41) Kirichenko 2010, 139 sees the first initiation as all but
bankrupting a fabulously wealthy Lucius. Yet it is the cost of
Lucius' travels and living expenses in Rome that has reduced his
'modest inheritance' (viriculas patrimonii; 11,28,1).
(42) The cost of the initiation--which would benefit a satirical
presentation--is not included. This contrasts with the precise amounts
of other financial transactions (1,24,4; 8,25,6). It thus seems that
when the focus is upon exorbitant price, the price is given.
(43) Diophanes is described as 'tall and slightly
swarthy' (procerus et suffusculus; 2,13,1), Zatchlas as
'shaven-headed' (deraso capite; 2,28,2), and Philebus as
'bald' and 'effeminate' (calvum, cinaedum; 8,24,2);
for a discussion of these priests, see Edsall 1996, 169183, 193-200.
Satirised Eastern priests are depicted as bald, such as the wig-wearing
Alexander (Lucian Alex. 59) and the Egyptian priest Pancrates, who is
'shaven-headed, dressed in linen, ever thoughtful, speaks accented
Greek, has a snub-nose, protruding lips, and quite skinny legs.'
('[TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].' Lucian Philops. 34). For
the stigma attached to baldness, see Winkler 1985, 225-227 and
Kirichenko 2010, 35-36.
(44) Ahl 1985, 151-152 believes that the name is a 'subversive
implication that Lucius could now be making an ass of himself in a
rather different way.' See Nicolini 2012, 29-30 for wordplay in the
use of the term reformationis.
(45) Griffiths 1975, 265-266. In addition to sacerdos, Mithras is
referred to as summus sacerdos (11,16,6; 11,20,1), sacerdos maximus
(11,17,1),primarium sacerdotem (11,21,2), and sacerdotem praecipuum
(11,22,3).
(46) Egelhaaf-Gaiser 2012, 53.
(47) For Lucius as a possible charlatan, see note 6, above.
(48) The entry for pastophori in the Lewis-Short Latin Lexicon
reads: 'a kind of priests who carried about the images of their
deities in a little shrine for the purpose of collecting alms.'
Egelhaaf-Gaiser 2012, 49-50, and note 29 has recently argued against the
etymology of pastophorus ('carrier of the [TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN
ASCII]') to mean 'carrier of the shrine' or 'carrier
of the fabric'. Regardless of its meaning, she concludes that the
evidence points to 'a lower-grade function on the border between
temple servants and the higher-ranking priests.'
(49) Griffiths 1975, 333; Winkler 1985, 218.
(50) GCA 1985, 289.
(51) Figures with deformed or injured feet and/or a limp include
Thersites (Hom. Il.2,217-219), Philoctetes (Soph. Phil. 1326-1328),
ill-omened Oedipus ('Swollen Foot'), and Claudius (Sen.
Apocol. 1). Gout sufferers are common in satire because the condition
was linked to unrestrained appetites in food and lust; cf. Pers. 3,64;
5,57; Petron. Sat. 64,3; 96,4; 140,6; Lucian Gall. 23; Philops. 6-7;
Sen. Ep. 24,16; Catull. 71. Altogether, these examples display the
negative moral connotations of the deformity and mobility impairment
that Asinius bears. For a discussion of physiognomy in the
Metamorphoses, see Keulen 2006, 168-202.
(52) Translation by F. C. Babbit 1936.
(53) The commentators of GCA 2004, 502 consider the identification
of the lame duo as Ocnus and his donkey to be uncertain. Finkelpearl
1990, 345-346 takes them to be an 'alter-ego' of Lucius the
ass. Panayotakis 1997, 29 identifies them as personified abstractions of
malignity.
(54) See note 21, above.
(55) Griffiths 1975, 270.
(56) Edsall 1996, 216; cf. Van Mal-Maeder 1997, 103. Compare the
grandipraemio and the compendium that are to be paid for the magical
services of Zatchlas and the witch (2,28,1; 9,29,4).
(57) The name of the hometown, Madauros, is missing from the
speech, but was widely known; see August. Ep. 102,32; De civ. D. 8,14,2;
Sid. Apoll. Epist. 9,13,8; Cassiod. Inst. 2,5,10. The temporal relation
between the Apologia and Metamorphoses is slightly contentious.
Apuleius' Apologia is dated soon after his trial in the winter
months of AD158/159; cf. Harrison 2000, 41 and Harrison, Hilton, and
Hunink 2001, 12. The Metamorphoses is usually thought to have been
published after the trial because the work is not mentioned in the
Apologia and thus appears not to have been used to demonstrate
Apuleius' involvement with magic; cf. Kenney 1990, 2, Schlam 1992,
12, Walsh 1999, xix-xx, Harrison 2000, 9-10, and, most decisively,
Hunink 2002, 233. Moreover, Lucius' trial at Met. 3.1-12 may allude
to Apuleius' own court case; see Harrison, Hilton, and Hunink 2001,
21, note 19. Dowden 1994, 419-34 has the Metamorphoses published prior
to the Apologia. Hunink, 2002, 234, suggests that the Metamorphoses
could have been written earlier in Apuleius' career but not
published until after the Apologia. My opinion, however, is that the
case behind the Apologia could have been what initially motivated
Apuleius to adapt the original Greek ass-tale, since its narrator--a
young man with intellectual pretensions--becomes involved in magic, just
as the prosecution claimed Apuleius had done.
(58) In the Metamorphoses, this Cynic sentiment can be found in the
words of the last dying brother to the murderous and greedy young
nobleman (9,38,2-4).
(59) Carlisle 2008, 231.
(60) On affectation as a key to Lucian's satiric strategy in
Alexander, see Branham 1984, 149.
(61) I am here referring to Apuleius as he presents himself in the
Apologia (see note 70, below).
(62) Cf. Rives 2003, 325: 'Apuleius thus makes the case hinge
on the distinction between a philosopher and a magus.'
(63) Unlike Apuleius' philosophical curiosity, Lucius'
curiosity is indiscriminate (cf. 1,2,6). For the notion of positive and
negative curiosity in antiquity, see Kirichenko 2008, 340-345.
(64) By contrast, Loukios does have to defend himself as if in
court (Ps.-Lucian Asinus 54-55). Note that Apuleius' posthumous
reputation as a magus contradicts his own denial of magical practices in
his defence speech, a point which Augustine uses against those who claim
that Apuleius worked miracles (August. Ep. 137,13; 138,19). Nonetheless,
Augustine views Apuleius as a magician because he revered daemones,
which Augustine believes to be the source of pagan magic. For
Augustine's treatment of Apuleius as philosopher and magician, see
Gaisser 2008, 29-36. Winter 2006, 97-106 argues against the idea that
Apuleius' reputation and knowledge of magic (as displayed by the
Apologia) betrays occult leanings.
(65) Cf. Weiss 1998, 100; Schmeling and Montiglio 2006, 39; Van
Nuffelen 2011, 95; Harrison 2012, 82-83. Even Griffiths 1975, 308 admits
that Lucius has said too much. In addition, while Apuleius was initiated
into many cults (Apol. 55), Photis merely flatters Lucius that he is
(sacrispluribus initiatus; 3,15,4); cf. Winkler 1985, 319, note 77.
(66) Apuleius elsewhere says that appearance is of little
consequence; cf. De dog. Plat. 2,22 [251].
(67) Keulen 2006, 192 sees a connection between a handsome Lucius
and the beautiful yet ignoble stepmother in Book 10.
(68) Ibid. 193-194. This immoral man has an unquenchable thirst for
all sorts of pleasures and cannot see true beauty due to his fixation on
surface appearances; he also lacks self-knowledge. Cf. Apul. De deo Soc.
23 [172-175]. Kirichenko 2010, 140 links Lucius' fixation on the
strange letters of the sacred books (11,22,7-8) with his fixation on the
embroidered Olympiaca stola (11,24,3), betraying misplaced importance on
surface detail.
(69) Kenney 2003, 177.
(70) Cf. Heiserman 1977, 149-151. Kenney 2003, 187-189 suggests
Lucius' religious experience is a parodic reworking of
Apuleius' own, making Lucius an alter-ego. Apuleius'
presentation of himself in the Apologia is, like all sophistic
self-presentations, carefully designed for a specific purpose, here
being to win over the philosophical judge (and, to a lesser extent, the
audience). I believe that the Metamorphoses forms an extension of this
same sophistic self-presentation in that Apuleius, the author who has
displayed his learning and literary artistry throughout, contrasts
himself with Lucius, the comic scholasticus cum narrating pastophorus.
Apuleius thus puts himself forward as the ideal philosopher in the
Apologia (as the defendant, in contrast with the prosecutor) and in the
Metamorphoses (as the author, in contrast with the narrating
protagonist).
(71) Van Nuffelen 2011, 91-93; cf. Rives 2003, 326.
(72) Van Nuffelen 2011, 91 cites Apuleius' use of Plato to
reject cult statues made with anything other than wood (cf. Apul. Apol.
65; Pl. Leg. 955E).
(73) Cf. Weiss 1998, 94.
(74) Finkelpearl 2012, 194-196.
(75) Ibid. 196-199, 201.
(76) Contrast Frangoulidis 2008, 175-203, who argues that the lead
up to and initiation into the mysteries of Isis (Book 11) is a
successful and positive version of the failed initiation into magic in
Book 3.
(77) Lucius displays various emotions before and after the Risus
festival: daring (2,32,4-5); anguish and bewilderment (3,1);
wretchedness and boldness (3,4); sorrow and indignity (3,7); gloom and
dumbfoundedness (3,9); downheartedness, fear, and misery (3,10); fear
and embarrassment (3,12); curiosity and eagerness (3,14); lust
(3,20,3-4); amazement (3.22.1); anger and resentment (3,26). Cf. Weiss
1998, 94, note 20.
(78) Lucius exhibits familiar emotionality before and after his
initiations: shame and fear (10,34); awe and tears (11,1); misery
(11,3,1); fear and joy (11,7); joy and fear (11,12); amazement and great
joy (11,14); doubt (11,19,3); overeagerness (11,21,2); calmness
(11.22.1); thankfulness (11,24,5-6); confusion and eagerness (11,27);
anxiety (11,28,2); astonishment and doubt (11,29,); joy (11,30,5).
(79) For continuity between Lucius' relationships with Photis
and Isis, see Schmeling and Montiglio 2006, 36-39 and Hindermann 2009,
79-82.
(80) The foundation of a sound mind is not to rejoice in empty
things (Huius fundamentum [sc. bonae mentis] quod sit quaeris? Ne
gaudeas vanis; Sen. Ep. 23,1). As such, 'proper joy is a serious
matter' (verum gaudium res severa est; 23,4).
(81) Weiss 1998, 94; cf. Plut. De sup. 2,165b-c.
(82) Van Nuffelen 2011, 96.
(83) Cf. May 2006, 316: 'Isis has fulfilled her function as a
saviour already, and the second and third initiations of Lucius may
function as a hint for the reader to take the mystery narrative less
seriously, and may make him/her understand their function as a tool to
reinforce the reader's impression that Lucius is still as credulous
as before.' In my view, the second and third initiations show that
Lucius is willing to placate his demanding gods not due to gullibility
but out of fear, just like the superstitious man.
(84) Lateiner 2000, 329 views Lucius' celibacy under Isis as
the goddess's means of binding him to her.
(85) See note 21, above.
(86) On the programmatic (metaliterary) meaning of superstitious
fear as a typical feature of Apuleian storytellers (tormented by
'visions'), see GCA 2007, 46-48.
(87) I here follow the emendation by Kronenburg (1892. 'Ad
Apuleium Madaurensem', Erasmiani Gymn. Progr. Litt., Rotterdam,
1-32), adopted by the Bude edition of Robertson and Vallette (Paris,
1945) and the Loeb edition of Hanson (Cambridge, Massachusetts--London,
1989).
(88) Keulen 2003, 126.
(89) Harrison 2000, 240 and 2012, 77 sees humour in an ass
ritualistically bathing in the sea. In this context, the Pythagorean
detail comes across as more trite and superstitious than pious.
(90) Cf. 11,2,4: ac si quod offensum numen (a clear allusion to the
saevitia of Fortuna), and also 11,1,3: fato ... satiatio, which also
refers to his suffering at the hands of the goddess Fortuna.
(91) Rather than taking responsibility for convincing Photis to
show him magic, Lucius still blames her for his transformation
(11,20,6), despite Mithras telling him he was at fault (11,15,1); cf.
Smith 1993, 1593-1594. Socrates likewise blames Fortuna for his pitiable
state, revealing his own superstitious nature (1,7,1); cf. Keulen 2003,
120, 123.
(92) Note that Mithras produces the books from a secret part of the
temple (de opertis adyti) and that they contained 'unknown
letters' (litteris ignorabilibus; 11,22,8). Since Lucius is still
uninitiated, he is clearly one of those whose curiosity drives him to
learn about them (curiositate profanorum). Lucius focuses on the exotic
form of the writing, rather than its meaning; cf. Kirichenko 2010, 136.
(93) In Egypt, it was common for bald priests to wear wigs during
secular life, see Fletcher 2004, 100-101; cf. James and O'Brien
2006, 246, also note 17. If this were the case in Rome, this would
confirm that Apuleius is making a point of Lucius publicly displaying
his bald head. Egelhaaf-Gaiser 2012, 47-49 discusses the shaven-headed
busts of 'Scipio' as depicting Isiac priests. These portraits,
if they indeed represent Isiac priests, do not confirm that these men
did not wear wigs during secular activities, just that the busts
highlight the religious aspect of their character.
(94) Cf. van Mal-Maeder 1997, 107. For seeing Lucius as rejecting
serviles voluptates at 11,30, cf. Englert and Long 1973, 239; Smith
2009, 56-57; Frangoulidis 2008, 201-202.
(95) Lucius is told by the clemens imago that he should consider
himself blessed to be initiated three times while most are not even
initiated once (11,29,4). Cf. also 11,16, where Lucius relishes in his
minor celebrity status after his transformation.
(96) Lucius' comment at 9,13,5 that he has broader knowledge
(multiscium) due to his time as an ass, even if he is less wise (minus
prudentem) than Odysseus, is undercut by him proceeding to relate a tale
'better than the others' (prae ceteris; 9,14,1), which
concerns adultery and results in his master's death. Sharing such
stories illustrates that Lucius is still a busybody, which is a trait of
negative curiosity; cf. Kirichenko 2008, 357.
(97) Van Nuffelen 2011, 97 and note 54.
(98) Also noted by Frangoulidis 2008, 173 and Kirichenko 2010, 151.
(99) cf. Van Nuffelen 2011, 97. Van der Stockt 2012, 179-180
illustrates that Isis in the Metamorphoses is different in role and
significance to the Isis from Plutarch's De Iside.
(100) I would like to thank John Garthwaite for his invaluable aid
in the preparation of this article and to the anonymous readers whose
insightful comments and suggestions helped me to tighten it up in
several places.
Nathan Watson is currently a tutor of Classics at the University of
Otago in Dunedin, New Zealand, where he has recently completed his MA
thesis, From Philosophising Ass to Asinine Philosopher: Satire in Book
11 of Apuleius' Metamorphoses. He plans to continue his research on
the works of Apuleius.