Coleridge, Hume, and the principles of political knowledge.
Michael, Timothy
Reserving then the expression "Idea" [Idee] for the
objective or real Notion [Begriff] and distinguishing it from the Notion
itself and still more from mere pictorial thought, we must also reject
even more vigorously that estimate of the Idea according to which it is
not anything actual, and true thoughts are said to be only ideas.
--G. W. Hegel, Science of Logic (1)
Being impelled or inspired by an image is not the same as knowing a
world. We do not need to postulate a world beyond time which is the home
of such images in order to account for their occurrence, or for their
effects on conduct.
--Richard Rorty, Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (2)
THE CONDITIONS OF KNOWLEDGE WERE, FOR S. T. COLERIDGE, THE
CONDItions on which the practical affairs of this world were required to
stand. What sorts of things counted as knowledge, and how the human mind
comes to know certain things, determined both the legitimacy of social
structures and the nature of political obligation, In much of his prose,
Coleridge denies the autonomy of epistemological discourse, emphasizing
instead the necessary connection between how the mind functions, on the
one hand, and the validity of particular political arrangements, on the
other. This belief in the social reality of what constitutes knowledge
led Coleridge to pursue a relatively sustained, at least by Coleridgean
standards, analysis of what he calls the "principles of political
knowledge," It is under this heading that the political essays of
the 1818 The Friend, Coleridge's first real attempt to formulate
his own political philosophy systematically, are gathered. Political
knowledge, like any other form of knowledge, must satisfy certain
conditions if it is to be trusted as any sort of guide in practical
affairs, especially those in which the welfare of large numbers of
people is concerned, Coleridge's specific interest is in the source
of this knowledge, and he thus engages with the faculty psychology of
the period (in both its British form and as modified and extended by
transcendental thought). The relationships among the various mental
faculties form the basis of his theory of political knowledge, just as
they form the basis of his literary criticism, his metaphysics, and much
of his best poetry.
In this essay, I argue for the centrality of the understanding in
Coleridge's mature political thought. A faculty often overlooked in
Romantic studies, which tends to focus on the dialectic between reason
and the imagination, the understanding is for Coleridge the operative
faculty in judging and applying the principles of political knowledge.
(3) I first examine Coleridge's relationship to Hume, arguing that
Coleridge's rejection of Humean epistemology reveals what is
perhaps the most essential aspect of Coleridge's own theory of
knowledge, the status of the "idea." The political
consequences of Humean epistemology provide more problems for Coleridge,
whose ideas of the social contract and political obligation differ
sharply from Hume's. I then provide a reading of The Friend
(1809-10, 1818), with attention also paid to The Statesman's Manual
(1816) and the Lectures on the History of Philosophy (1818-19), pursuing
the implications of Coleridge's revaluation of the understanding as
the faculty of "suiting measures to circumstances" and the
foundation of all political knowledge. (4) The significance accorded to
the understanding is shown to have the following related purposes: 1) to
address the possibility of metaphysics in the face of Hume's
critique of causality; 2) to demonstrate the necessity of the unequal
distribution of property; 3) to secure the autonomy of the moral will in
the context of political obligation; 4) to establish that a philosophy
reliant upon the senses is no longer suited to the material conditions
of the nation; and, finally, 5) to define knowledge in such a way as to
make room for faith.
The terms of this argument require perhaps some clarification, as
"epistemology" is our word, entering the language near the
middle of the nineteenth century, and not Coleridge's. The most
direct justification for its use is the fact that Coleridge is
explicitly concerned with the "principles of political
knowledge" in the sense of the grounds or conditions of this
knowledge. I argue that the necessary condition of political knowledge
is, for Coleridge, a particular configuration, or hierarchy, of the
mental faculties under the chairmanship of the understanding. In
presenting us with a theory of how the mind functions, Coleridge
presents us with a theory of knowledge. The two projects, up until the
late nineteenth century, were necessarily connected, if not
co-extensive: forming an idea of what constitutes knowledge typically
demanded forming an accurate picture of the mind. It is not until
Frege's, and then Husserl's, rejection of
"psychologism" from philosophy that the two projects formally
diverge.
What, then, is given to us in an analysis of "the principles
of political knowledge?" Beginning in the fourteenth century,
"principle" in English signified much the same as its root (L.
principium), i.e. "origin" or "source."
"Principle" develops a secondary sense of "general law or
rule" in the sixteenth century (a general law or rule "of
nature" in the nineteenth) and another sense of "elementary
constituent" in the seventeenth century. (5) Coleridge invokes
these related meanings of "principle" in The Friend when he
speaks of his desire "to refer men to PRINCIPLES in all
things" (F 2: 13), to "refer men's opinions to their
absolute principles" (F 16); when he speaks of principles as
"fundamental truths" (F 19) and "fundamental
doctrines" (F 21), of "ABSOLUTE PRINCIPLES or necessary
LAWS" (F 157) and "scientific principles (or laws)" (F
462). Coleridge also uses "principle" in The Friend to signify
"ground" or "condition:" "a man's
principles, on which he grounds his Hope and his Faith, are the life of
his life" (F 97); in the important epigraph from Spinoza to be
discussed later, "to demonstrate from plain and undoubted
principles, or to deduce from the very condition and necessities of
human nature, those plans and maxims which best square with
practice" (F 166); "the full exposition of a principle which
is the condition of all intellectual progress" (F 446); "the
grounds and essential principles of their philosophic systems" (F
487); "the condition or principles of method" (F 513), etc.
These kinds of principles, then, are quite clearly distinguished from
"maxims" or general rules of conduct: "[God] gave us
PRINCIPLES, distinguished from the maxims and generalizations of outward
experience by their absolute and essential universality and
necessity" (F 112). These are, in effect, pure principles, the
formal a priori grounds or conditions of knowledge generally. (6)
The other, practical definition of "principle," here a
kind of knowledge and not simply one of its conditions, relevant to The
Friend is Kantian: "Practical principles (Prinzipen, or
Grundsatze)," according to Kant, "are propositions that
contain a general determination of the will, having under it several
practical rules.'' (7) They are subjective maxims "when
the condition is regarded by the subject as holding only for his will;
they are objective laws "when the condition is cognized as
objective, that is, as holding for the will of every rational
being" (CPrR 158). Coleridge adopts Kant's definition of
practical principles (a kind of knowledge that may, in fact, take the
form of a subjective maxim or an objective "general law or
rule"), arguing in The Friend that political knowledge, to be
discussed in greater detail below, is a form of propositional
knowledge--specifically, inferential (demonstrative) knowledge--that is
not derived from either experience or reason alone, but from the
mediating faculty of the understanding.
Romantic studies has, for the past three decades or so, been keen
on subverting the "Kantian/Coleridgean" version of
Romanticism, suggesting that we may be able to learn more about British
literary culture following the French Revolution by focusing on its
internal tensions and affiliations rather than its dubious importation
of a foreign philosophic tradition (that Coleridge never quite
"got" Kant is still, lamentably, a lingering suspicion in
Coleridge studies). (8) At its best, critical resistance to the
traditional Kantian/Coleridgean line provides a salutary corrective to
monolithic interpretations of Romanticism which invariably return to, as
Stanley Cavell puts it, "something called uniting subject and
object." (9) The foundational works in Romantic studies, though,
and specifically in the Coleridge criticism that relates metonymically
to the larger field, are extraordinarily sensitive to the debt of the
Romantics to native intellectual traditions. This essay does not propose
to espouse a particular "version" of Romanticism, either
Kantian/Coleridgean or, say, one focusing on Byron or Waker Scott, nor
does it presume to negotiate between supposedly competing versions. Its
aim is to follow a particular line of Kantian thought in Coleridge in
order to understand more fully his most fundamental epistemological and
political assumptions.
In his excellent contribution to Scotland and the Borders of
Romanticism, "Coleridge, Hume, and the Chains of the Romantic
Imagination," Cairns Craig argues that Coleridge, in the
Biographia, neglects to engage fully with Hume's theory of
association, focusing instead on Hartley, because Humearl association
makes room for the imagination in a way that Hartley's materialism
does not. The Kantian imagination offered a way out of Hartley's
materialism for Coleridge; but, according to Craig, "Humean
associationism presents a more anguished conception of the imagination
since, for Hume, the imagination is both the foundation of all our
experience and, at the same time, its inevitable dissolution." (10)
In his review of Craig's essay, Seamus Perry reminds us that, at
least in terms of the personal philosophical development depicted in the
Biographia, Hume simply does not play much of a role--that, in
Craig's terms, the "historical and philosophical suppression
involved in this substitution of Hartley for Hume" may have less to
do with Coleridge's anxiety regarding Hume (attracted to his theory
of association and, at once, repulsed by his alleged atheism) and more
to do with the fact that Coleridge simply did not devote as much thought
to Hume as to Hartley or, Perry notes, to Joseph Priestley. (11) Even if
one were to grant the relative inattention to Hume in the Biographia,
the vitriol with which Coleridge speaks of Hume throughout his prose
suggests that there is much at stake here--namely, I argue, a picture of
the mind with political consequences. Where Craig sees a historical and
philosophical suppression of Hume for the sake of the transcendental
imagination, at least in the Biographia, I argue for a more direct
engagement with Hume on ideational and ideological grounds--in other
words, one centered on the status of the idea and the social
consequences of that status.
2
Evidence of Coleridge's antipathy towards Hume is not
difficult to find. The tenor of the antagonism is perhaps best expressed
in Coleridge's remark that, in his planned History of Metaphysics,
Hume was to be given considerable attention and that he would be
"besprinkled copiously from the fountains of bitterness and
contempt.'' (12) Criticisms typically fall into three related
categories: theological, philosophical, and cultural. Coleridge, like
many others, objected to Hume's agnosticism in the strongest
possible terms. The Biographia Literaria (1817) refers to "the
impious and pernicious tenets defended by Hume, Priestley, and the
French fatalists or necessitarians; some of whom had perverted
metaphysical reasonings to the denial of mysteries and indeed of all the
peculiar doctrines of christianity." (13) The Statesman's
Manual unsympathetically refers to "the same Scotch philosopher,
who devoted his life to the undermining of the Christian religion; and
expended his last breath in a blasphemous regret that he had not
survived it." (14) The charge of blasphemy is repeated in the
1818-1819 Lectures on the History of Philosophy, in which Coleridge
dismisses, as he would throughout his Marginalia, the "spider"
argument from Hume's Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion (1779).
(15)
These theological objections stem, of course, from more fundamental
objections to Hume's philosophy, particularly his epistemology.
Coleridge offers his most concise and direct statement of the link in
the Biographia. "The process, by which Hume degraded the notion of
cause and effect into a blind product of delusion and habit, into the
mere sensation of proceeding life (nisus vitalis) associated with the
images of the memory; this same process must be repeated to the equal
degradation of every fundamental idea in ethics or theology" (BL 1:
121). The degrading ethical and theological effects of Hume's
critique of causality are countered in The Statesman's Manual,
where Coleridge contends that the necessity of causal relations
"depends on, or rather inheres in, the idea of the Omnipresent and
Absolute: for this it is, in which the Possible is one and the same with
the Real and the Necessary" (SM 32). For Hume, we remember,
"necessity is something, that exists in the mind, not in
objects.'' (16) While the necessity of causal relations in the
idea of the "Absolute" is slightly obscure in its details--it
is difficult to imagine such a process without resorting to something
approaching Malebranche's occasionalism or Berkeley's
idealism--Coleridge clearly and consistently posits God, the infinite I
AM, as the ground or foundation of all reality. Coleridge is thus
acutely aware not only of the standard skeptical arguments forwarded in
Hume's Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion and Natural History of
Religion (1757), but he is also sensitive to how the reduction of causal
knowledge to habitual belief in Hume's Treatise (1739-40) threatens
every "fundamental" ethical and theological idea.
There are also more purely philosophical objections to Hume's
epistemology, although these, too, almost always contain the trace of
theological suspicion. Perhaps the most technical objection is found in
the Notebooks (1804):
How opposed to nature & the fact to talk of the one moment of Hume;
of our whole being [as] an aggregate of successive single
sensations. Who ever felt a single sensation? Is not every one at
the same moment conscious that there co-exist a thousand others in
a darker shade, or less light; even as when I fix my attention on a
white House on a gray bare Hill or rather long ridge that runs out
of sight each way (How often I want the German [']unubersehbar[']?)
the pretended single sensation is it in anything more than the
Light-point in every picture either of nature or of a good painter;
& again subordinately in every component part of the picture? And
what is a moment? Succession with interspace? Absurdity! It is
evidently only the Licht-pun[k]t, the Sparkle in the indivisible
undivided Duration. (17)
This notebook entry from Christmas Day 1804 registers
Coleridge's main philosophic complaint against Hume. The "copy
principle" of Hume's Treatise--the notion, derived from Locke,
that complex ideas are composed of simple ideas, which are fainter
copies of the simple impressions from which they ultimately derive, to
which they correspond and exactly resemble--was formulated so that
irreducible complex ideas, such as the soul, God, or substance could be
shown to lack cognitive content. Its premise is that one can reduce a
complex idea into its constituent simple ideas and that these simple
ideas, in turn, could be reduced to the simple impressions from which
they derive. Coleridge repudiates the whole notion of a single
impression, suggesting the indivisibility of what Kant would call the
manifold of intuition, thus allowing the irreducibly complex idea of God
to have some other epistemological basis.
Hume's critique of causality, Coleridge worries, threatens the
possibility of metaphysics itself. In the Biographia, he writes that
"after I had successively studied in the schools of Locke,
Berkeley, Leibnitz, and Hartley" (a trajectory familiar to readers
of Coleridge) and "could find in neither of them an abiding place
for my reason," he began to ask whether "a system of
philosophy, as different from mere history and historic classification,
[is] possible?" (BL 1: 141). As Coleridge sees it, the possibility
of metaphysics is threatened by the empirical claim, originating in
Aristotle and finding its fullest expression in Book I of Locke's
Essay, that "there is nothing in the mind that was not before in
the senses." It is also threatened by Hume's analysis of cause
and effect, which, Coleridge argues, "will apply with equal and
crushing force to all the other eleven categorical forms, and the
logical functions corresponding to them" (BL 1: 142). As James
Engell observes, Coleridge "is saying that once a strictly
empirical premise is conceded, none of Kant's categories may be
trusted as objective operations of the mind" (BL 1: 141n).
Coleridge will, of course, concede neither the foundational empirical
premise nor Hume's claims regarding causality. He will concede
neither because, as he puts it, "Truth is correlative of
Being," or "intelligence and being are reciprocally each
other's Substrate" (BL 1: 142-43). Coleridge quickly makes it
clear that "being" here refers specifically to a Supreme
Being, the (possibility of the) idea of which dictated the philosophical
development, described with proper names, he has just outlined. "An
abiding place for my reason," offered by none of the philosophers
mentioned, is first and foremost a system in which the idea of God is
able to rest. (18)
The status of the idea, so obviously crucial in Hume's
philosophy, is precisely what is at stake in Coleridge's
negotiations with Hume. It is, as Coleridge would say in the final
sentence to The Statesman's Manual, "the highest problem of
philosophy, and not part of its nomenclature" (SM 114). Hume in the
Treatise defines the "idea" as "faint images of
[impressions] in thinking and reasoning." He explains in a note
that he is restoring the word "idea" to its "original
sense, from which Mr. Locke had perverted it, in making it stand for all
our perceptions" (THN 7). (19) Coleridge shares with Hume his
rejection of Locke's overly broad definition, and offers his own,
poorly worded definition in the Statesman's Manual, quoted here in
full because of its importance and untranslatability:
A Notion may be realized, and becomes Cognition; but that which is
neither a Sensation or a Perception, that which is neither individual
(i.e. a sensible Intuition) nor general (i.e. a conception) which
neither refers to outward Facts nor yet is abstracted from the FORMS of
perception contained in the Understanding; but which is an educt of the
Imagination actuated by the pure Reason, to which there neither is or
can be an adequate correspondent in the world of the senses--this is and
this alone is = AN IDEA. Whether Ideas are regulative only, according to
Aristotle and Kant; or likewise CONSTITUTIVE, and one with the power and
Life of Nature, according to Plato, and Plotinus is the highest problem
of Philosophy, and not part of its nomenclature. (SM 114)
Coleridge claimed that the appendix from which this passage comes
is "by far the most miscellaneous and desultory of all my
writings"; but, he adds, "it had a right to be such." It
had a right to be such because, as R. J. White observes, this passage is
perhaps "the best statement of Coleridge's philosophical
position" (SM 114n). However much we may object to it on literary
grounds, it condenses into a relatively short space the complexity of
the Coleridgean idea. An idea, according to Coleridge, is a notion
necessarily engaging with all three major faculties: it is abstracted
from the understanding, an "educt" (i.e. an inference or
development) (20) of the imagination actuated by the reason. Coleridge
is intent on having the idea interact with as many aspects of the mind
as possible because his desire is to widen the range of things that may
possibly be considered "ideas." If the ideas of God or
substance cannot exist in an empirical system of sense impressions, then
surely they can exist in the slippery space known as the "play of
the mental faculties." (21) Their status as regulative or
constitutive is left undetermined, but, given Coleridge's theory of
the symbol and his other writings on the idea in the Biographia and
elsewhere in the Statesman's Manual, one may assume the latter.
(22)
The Biographia offers a less definitive, but more suggestive
discussion of the idea. Its chapter on the history of associationism
complicates and extends the claims made in the Notebooks regarding the
indivisibility of sensation. Intending to demonstrate that Hobbes
contributed nothing original or substantial whatsoever to this history,
Coleridge describes Hobbes' theory of association in Humean terms:
"Whenever we feel several objects at the same time, the impressions
that are left (or in the language of Mr. Hume, the ideas) are linked
together. Whenever therefore any one of the movements, which constitute
a complex impression, are renewed through the senses, the others succeed
mechanically" (BL 1: 96). Hobbes (and, Coleridge contends, the
materialists such as Hartley who followed him) thus reduces all the
forms of association to "the one law of time." This is an
untenable philosophical position for Coleridge, for whom contemporaneity
is only part of the law of association: "For the objects of any two
ideas need not have co-existed in the same sensation in order to become
mutually associable" (BL 1: 96-97). Memory, that is, works with
sensation in providing the materials of association. More interesting,
however, than the rejection of claims regarding Hobbes' lasting
contributions to the history of associationism---a judgment not at all
surprising for someone who had long since rejected materialism in all
its forms--is what Coleridge says in a lengthy footnote amended to the
sentence just quoted. In it, Coleridge grudgingly justifies his, and
Hume's, use of the word "idea":
I here use the word "idea" in Mr. Hume's sense on
account of its general currency among the English metaphysicians; though
against my own judgment, for I believe that the vague use of this word
has been the cause of much error and more confusion. The word idea, in
its original sense as used by Pindar, Aristophanes, and in the gospel of
Matthew, represented the visual abstraction of a distant object, when we
see the whole without distinguishing its parts. Plato adopted it as a
technical term, and as the antithesis to eidola, or sensuous images; the
transient and perishable emblems, or mental words, of ideas. The ideas
themselves he considered as mysterious powers, living, seminal,
formative, and exempt from time. (BL 1: 97)
This Platonic use of the term is essentially the one Coleridge
adopts in his most sustained and thorough writing on the subject, The
Statesman's Manual: "But every principle is actualized by an
idea; and every idea is living, productive, partaketh of infinity, and,
(as Bacon has sublimely observed) containeth an endless power of
semination" (SM 23-24). (23) What is conspicuously absent here is
the concept, the division of which into a priori and a posteriori
classes by Kant left little room for the kind of idea Coleridge viewed
as "exempt from time." "[A]n Idea is equi-distant in its
signification from Sensation, Image, Fact, and Notion: [it] is the
antithesis not the synonyme of eidolon" (SM 101). The operative
relationship here is the actualizing one between the idea and the
principle, to be discussed shortly.
The crucial issue, as far as Coleridge's relationship to Hume
is concerned, is the possibility of an idea not derived from sense
experience. The instances of the ideas of God and substance have already
been mentioned, but the idea as it relates to political knowledge is
Coleridge's other concern, and our primary one here. Coleridge
warns against the abuse of the idea, speaking nostalgically of the
"genial reverence" with which Algernon Sydney "commune[d]
with Harrington and Milton on the Idea of a perfect state; and in what
sense it is true, that the men (i.e. the aggregate of the inhabitants of
a country at any one time) are made for the state, not the state for the
men" (SM 102). The influence of materialism and Lockean psychology,
however, has produced a new breed of philosophers, "and these too
have their Ideas!" They include those who have "an Idea, that
Hume, Hartley, and Condillac have exploded all Ideas, but those of
sensation" (SM 102). The suggestion is that the complex idea of a
perfect state, here defined in fairly reactionary terms, cannot rest on
ideas derived from sensation, but must have some other source.
These assertions from The Statesman's Manual, in which an
English literary and political tradition is threatened by Scottish and
French influences (and from within by materialists such as Hartley and
Priestley), reflect Coleridge's anxiety about the status of English
literary culture, broadly defined, at the end of the eighteenth and
beginning of the nineteenth century. (24) These "cultural"
objections constitute the third major category of Coleridge's
criticisms of Hume, existing alongside and frequently engaging with more
purely theological and philosophical objections. Coleridge laments in
his Notebooks that "[T]he flashy modems seem to rob the ancients of
the honors due to them/& Bacon & Harrington are not read because
Hume and Condillac are. This is an evil" (CN 2: 2193), a claim he
would repeat in the Biographia thirteen years later. In an entry from
1805, "Let England be Sir P. Sidney, Shakespeare, Spenser, Milton,
Bacon, Harrington, Swift, Wordsworth, and never let the names of Darwin,
Johnson, Hume, furr it over!" (CN 2: 2598). In his marginalia to
Pepys's Memoirs, Coleridge observes: "But alike as Historian
and as Philosopher, Hume has, meo saltem judicio, been extravagantly
overrated.--Mercy on the Age, & the People, for whom Lock is
profound, and Hume subtle." (25) Criticism is often directed
towards Scotland and Scottish writers at large, reflecting an
anti-Scottish sentiment even Wordsworth would share at times. In his
marginalia to Anderson's British Poets: "Damn this Scotch
Scoundrel of a Biographer" (CM 74) and "Is it possible that a
man should have written this? O Lord! Yes! any thing is possible from a
Scotchman" (CM 75). In an 1816 letter to Thomas Boosey: "The
Scotch appear to me dull Frenchmen, and superficial Germans.--They have
no Inside" (CL 4: 667). (26) Alexander Dyce, the Scottish editor
and literary historian, suspected in Coleridge a "mortal antipathy
to Scotchmen." The source of this anti-Scottish sentiment is
unclear, but there is, at best, an uneasiness, more than a century after
the Act of Union, about the role Scotland is to play in British cultural
life. At worst, there is mere prejudice along national or ethnic lines.
These objections by Coleridge to Hume on theological, philosophical
and cultural grounds are significant, and they form the basis of
Coleridge's fundamental attitude towards Hume. Of equal importance
and interest, however, are the rare moments when Coleridge defends Hume.
In his Lectures on the History of Philosophy, Coleridge argues that Hume
has been attacked unjustly, singling out the opponents of Hume whom Kant
dismisses in his Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics (1783): Joseph
Priestley, James Oswald, and James Beattie. "No one will suspect me
of being an advocate of Mr. Hume's opinions," Coleridge
writes, "but I most assuredly do think that he was attacked in a
very illogical, not to say unhandsome manner, both by Priestley and
Oswald, and, I grieve to say for the beauty of the book in other
respects, by Beattie.'' (27) Their attacks were
"illogical" and "unhandsome" because they were too
easily alarmed by the consequences of Hume's critique of causality:
"'Here is a man denying all cause and effect. What will become
of all our religion?' If it stopped there there would be some sense
in it, but they went on. 'What was to become of all society? If
such opinions were to prevail, men would not use their spoons to put
their soup into their mouths!'" (LHP 260). Coleridge warns
against this vulgarizing, overly literal interpretation of Hume. He is
shrewd enough not to reduce Hume to the caricature of the
skeptic--someone unable to avoid running into posts, etc., as was said
of Pyrrho. For Coleridge, a philosophy such as Hume's becomes
"pernicious" when it serves as an epistemic foundation not
only for theological claims (from what impression do we derive our idea
of God?), but also for political claims (from what impression do we
derive our idea of contract or fight?). The relations between these
branches of thought were clear enough for Hume. As Knud Haakonssen
observes, "The task he set out for his political theory was to
explain why [superstition and enthusiasm] were philosophically
misconceived, empirically untenable, and, in their extreme forms,
politically dangerous." (28)
Hume's political philosophy proceeds logically from the same
basic assumptions and premises he employs in the rest of his philosophy.
Just as the Treatise confidently proposes a science of human nature, so
do Hume's political essays contend "that politics may be
reduced to a science"; "So great is the force of laws and of
particular forms of government, and so little dependence have they on
the humors and tempers of men, that consequences almost as general and
certain may sometimes be deduced from them as any which the mathematical
sciences afford us.'' (29) The "universal axioms,"
"maxims," and "eternal political truths" of
Hume's politics are uttered on this basis. In its negative
component, Hume's politics deny the contract theory associated with
Hobbes and Locke and its attendant claim that consent is the source of
political obligation. "But would these reasoners look abroad,"
Hume writes in "Of the Original Contract," "they would
meet with nothing that, in the least, corresponds to their ideas, or can
warrant so refined and philosophical a system" (PE 46). Again, from
what impression or impressions do we derive our idea of an original
contract? "On the contrary, we find everywhere princes who claim
their subjects as their property and assert their independent right of
sovereignty from conquest or succession" (PE 46). Political
obligation does not have its source in an original contract, real or
imagined, but in historically situated power relations. "Is there
anything discoverable in all these [historical] events but force and
violence? Mere is the mutual agreement or voluntary association so much
talked of?" (PE 48). The claim that the historicity of the contract
is irrelevant--that it gains its force through a process of analogy (we
have certain social obligations as if such a contract had existed)--is,
for Hume, "false philosophy": we are thrown, as it were, into
societies that are already subject to authority and find ourselves
obliged to obey its laws, without the choice that is necessary in any
contractual relationship. In more positive terms, Hume's politics
extend the empirical methods of experience and observation to make
claims about property, law, and justice:
In general we may observe that all questions of property are
subordinate to the authority of civil laws, which extend, restrain,
modify, and alter the rules of natural justice, according to the
particular convenience of each community. The laws have, or ought
to have, a constant reference to the constitution of government,
the manners, the climate, the religion, the commerce, the situation
of each society. (30)
Having demonstrated the insufficiency of the contract theory in his
political essays, where he concludes that "some other foundation of
government must also be admitted" (PE 50), Hume continues in the
second Enquiry to argue for a foundation of interest:
Property is allowed to be dependent on civil laws; civil laws are
allowed to have no other object, but the interest of society: This
therefore must be allowed to be the sole foundation of property and
justice. Not to mention, that our obligation itself to obey the
magistrate and laws is founded on nothing but the interests of society.
(EPM 197n)
The ease with which Hume reaches this foundational claim comes from
the empiricist's faith in his own experience and observation (the
unacknowledged origins of our impressions) as the bases of his ideas; no
rationalist claim about the volonte generale is attempted with such
sangfroid. The briefest reflection on our own experience, for Hume,
indicates that our allegiance to governmental authority comes from a
collective interest in the protection (specifically, of property and
contracts) given to us by the administration of justice. (31)
Hume's inspiration here is nonetheless French, as it is
Montesquieu's L'Esprit des Loix (1748) that has
"prosecuted this subject [the fitness of the law to the historical
circumstances of a society] at large, and has established, from these
principles, a system of political knowledge, which abounds in ingenious
and brilliant thoughts, and is not wanting in solidity" (EPM
196-97, Hume's emphasis).
This language returns us to Coleridge and the "principles of
political knowledge" examined in The Friend. Hume's
epistemology of impressions and ideas, and the strict correspondence
between them, yielded a political philosophy that subordinates questions
of property to questions of law, places the source of political
obligation in interest, and maintains that basic social and political
institutions are fundamentally artificial: "those impressions,
which give rise to this sense of justice, are not natural to the mind of
man, but arise from artifice and human conventions." (32) These are
unacceptable premises for Coleridge, for whom the structure of the mind
itself determines both political organization and what constitutes
political knowledge. This is not to say that the ideas of justice,
property, right, obligation, and the perfect state--in short, the most
important and basic kinds of "political knowledge"--are, for
Coleridge, innate to the mind; but rather that the structure of the
mind, and not its impressions, determines their status as knowledge.
3
The earliest reference to what would become The Friend occurs in an
1804 notebook entry, where Coleridge writes, "I should like to dare
to look forward to the Time, when Wordsworth & I with some
contributions from Lamb & Southey--& from a few others ...
should publish a Spectator" (CN 2: 2074). In a letter to Thomas
Poole of the same year, he describes the work in noticeably different
terms: "Consolations and Comforts from the exercise and right
application of the Reason, the Imagination, and the Moral Feelings,
addressed especially to those in Sickness, Adversity, or Distress of
mind, from Speculative Gloom, etc." (CL 2: 1036). This description,
which would be repeated five years later in the Prospectus to The
Friend, declares the renovating and fructifying purpose of the work. It
is no accident that this project would be undertaken in the midst of
Coleridge's so-called "dark years," when the effects of
his failed marriage, his strained relationship with Wordsworth, his
persistent depression, his financial troubles, and his opium addiction
demanded the assistance of some "friend" to rescue him from
his dejection, Given that no friend--not Wordsworth, Southey, Gillman,
or even the steadfast Poole--was capable of the task, Coleridge in a
truly impressive act of an often paralyzed will, assumed the role of
aid-giver so that he might heal himself. The agent of this healing is
not the idea or the concept, but the principle: "It is my object to
refer men to PRINCIPLES in all things; in Literature, in the Fine Arts,
in Morals, in Legislation, in Religion. Whatever therefore of a
political nature may be reduced to general principles ... this I do not
exclude from my scheme" (F 2: 13). The Friend is an effort to
return to firm principles so that the detritus of false metaphysics may
be discarded.
Twenty-eight numbers were produced between June 1809 and March
1810. An "1812 edition" reprinted the numbers in a single
volume. The 1818 rifacimento altered and rearranged the essays so as to
form a more coherent whole, divided into three volumes. All three
volumes contain much that is interesting, covering a wide range of
subjects with Coleridge's characteristic bursts of imaginative
insight. Throughout there is an emphasis on the return to pure
principles, an effort to establish a foundation for judgment more firm
than the one provided by discursive reasoning. It is, however, the first
proper section, beginning towards the end of the first volume and
continuing all the way through the second, that is our primary concern.
This section, "On the Principles of political Knowledge,"
contains Coleridge's most sustained and explicit analysis of the
relationship between political theory and the conditions of knowledge.
The first essay on the principles of political philosophy begins
with an epigraph from Spinoza's Tractatus Politicus. In it, Spinoza
criticizes both the "mere practical Statesman" and the
"mere Theorists" for neglecting to do the actual work of
"conceiv[ing] a practicable scheme of civil policy." Spinoza
proposes, in contrast, "simply to demonstrate from plain and
undoubted principles, or to deduce from the very condition and
necessities of human nature, those plans and maxims which square best
with practice." (33) This, as we shall see, is essentially the
political model of expediency espoused by Coleridge later on in the
work. It is important, however, to note here the significance of
beginning his most sustained discussion of political history with a
lengthy epigraph from Spinoza. By the time Coleridge had begun writing
The Friend, he had rejected the fundamental claims of Spinoza's
Ethics and had already immersed himself in the Kantian-Schellingian
phase that would dominate his mature philosophic thought. By beginning
with Spinoza, Coleridge signals two central themes of The Friend: 1) a
philosophically radical metaphysics such as Spinoza's may be
consistent with a fairly conservative political philosophy (politically,
Spinoza largely follows Hobbes, with some important qualifications
regarding the theory of sovereignty); and 2) in some important ways, the
Coleridge of 1818 is much the same as the Coleridge of 1795. This is
nowhere more evident than in his decision to reprint some of his 1795
Bristol lectures in The Friend. As Barbara Rooke points out, "In
republishing in 1818 a large section of his political lectures
originally delivered in Bristol in 1795 during his period of
pro-revolutionary enthusiasm, Coleridge was doing more ... than trying
to prove that, contrary to satirists and caricaturists, he had been no
seditionist at that time and was no reactionary now" (F xcix), He
is asserting his own fidelity to pure principles. Just as Burke had
opposed the French Revolution while supporting American conciliation, so
had Coleridge maintained a consistent principle throughout his seemingly
incongruous philosophic allegiances. The principle is ultimately a
pragmatic one: a political proposition is justified so long as it proves
useful in a specific set of circumstances, what Coleridge would call the
"theory of expediency." This is not, one may justifiably
object, true of Coleridge across the entire range of his thought, It
does, however, apply particularly well to what he calls "political
knowledge."
The political essays of The Friend are predicated on a division of
"all the different philosophical systems of political justice, all
the Theories on the rightful Origin of Government" into three
classes. What is absolutely crucial, for our purposes, is that each
class is attended by an assumption about how the mind functions or what
it can know. The first class is the system of Hobbes, which ascribes the
origin and continuance of government to fear, "or the power of the
stronger, aided by the force of custom" (F 106). This theory
corresponds to the view that "the human mind consists of nothing,
but manifold modifications of passive sensation" (F 106). Coleridge
follows both Harrington and Cudworth here in objecting to Hobbes'
debasement of men into brutes, possessing some degree of understanding
but utterly devoid of the moral will. (34) The reality and legitimacy of
the moral will is the first principle of Coleridge's ethics, just
as the principle of irreducible unity is the first and guiding principle
of his metaphysics. Any theory of government which denies it is
therefore untenable. This objection aside, the whole theory is,
Coleridge contends, "baseless" on more empirical grounds:
We are told by History, we learn from experience, we know from our
own hearts, that fear, of itself, is utterly incapable of producing any
regular, continuous and calculable effect, even on an individual; and
that the fear, which does act systematically upon the mind, always
presupposes a sense of duty, as its cause. (F 167)
Fear may provide us with an inclination to behave in certain ways,
but it is always preceded, and ideally subjugated, by a dominant sense
of duty. This sanguine view of things, influenced by his reading of
Kant, fails to inquire into the causes of the sense of duty. Knowledge
of the sense of duty is not derived from any particular impressions,
but, it seems, from more universal principles under which historical and
personal particulars are subsumed. It is in this state that the
conscience, which Coleridge defines earlier in The Friend as a
"spiritual sense or testifying state of the coincidence or
discordance of the free will with the reason" (F 159) may be said
to operate.
The "sense of duty" translates easily and predictably
into the "Spirit of Law," the "true necessity, which
compels man into the social state" (F 167). This is as close as
Coleridge comes to asserting an original contract, which for him is an
absurd theory insofar as it neglects to assign a "moral force"
to the contract. In Coleridge's sense, the word
"contract" simply is the "sense of duty acting in a
specific direction, i.e. determining our moral relations, as members of
a body politic":
If I have referred to a supposed origin of Government, it has been
in courtesy to a common notion: for I myself regard the supposition as
no more than a means of simplifying to our apprehension the
ever-continuing causes of social union, even as the conservation of the
world may be represented as an act of continued Creation. (F 174)
The analogy Coleridge presents between the preservation of social
union and the divine preservation of the world itself recalls not only
the conclusion of Berkeley's argument of esse est percipi, but also
the Biographia's definition of the primary imagination as a
"repetition in the finite mind of the eternal act of creation in
the infinite I AM" (BL 1: 304). The "origin" of
government is not an isolated historical event, but is continually
created by the "moral force" of our "sense of duty."
This subjective sense of duty, and the objective "Spirit of the
Law" to which it corresponds, is the guiding principle of the
second theory of government, what Coleridge acknowledges as his own
theory of expediency: "according to this theory, every institution
of national origin needs no other justification than a proof, that under
particular circumstances it is expedient" (F 176). The assumption
of this theory is that the human being is an "animal gifted with
the understanding," defined here by Coleridge as "the faculty
of suiting measures to circumstances" (F 176).
The faculty of suiting measures to circumstances is the most
prominent definition of the understanding in The Friend's analysis
of the principles of political knowledge, although there are others. The
political essays of The Friend are preceded by a section on the
distinction between the reason and the understanding, a distinction on
which Coleridge claims to base his entire metaphysics. (35) Coleridge
here presents authentically Kantian definitions of the two faculties.
The understanding is "the faculty by which we generalize and
arrange the phenomena of perception; that faculty, the functions of
which contain the rules and constitute the possibility of outward
experience." In a note to the political section itself, Coleridge
writes that "by the UNDERSTANDING, I mean the faculty of thinking
and forming judgments on the notices furnished by the sense, according
to certain rules existing in itself, which rules constitute its distinct
nature" (F 177n). For Kant, the understanding (Verstand),
"whose province alone it is to make an objective judgment on
appearances," compares perceptions and connects them in
consciousness. (36) It is none other than the faculty of thinking, for
thinking "is the same as judging, or referring representations to
judgments in general" (Prolegomena 304). In the first part of the
Transcendental Logic in The Critique of Pure Reason (1781), he defines
the understanding as the faculty of rules.
Kant distinguishes the understanding from the reason in the
Transcendental Dialectic: "here we will distinguish reason from
understanding by calling reason [Vernunft] the faculty of
principles" (CPR 387); again, "If the understanding may be a
faculty of unity of appearances by means of rules, then reason is the
faculty of the unity of the rules of understanding under
principles" (CPR 389). In The Friend, Coleridge defines reason as
the "organ of Super-sensuous," that which subordinates the
notions of rules of the understanding to "ABSOLUTE PRINCIPLES or
necessary LAWS" (F 156-57). In the note to the political section;
"By the pure REASON, I mean the power by -which we become possessed
of principle, (the eternal verities of Plato and Descartes) and of
ideas, (N.B. not images) as the ideas of a line, a circle, in
Mathematics; and of Justice, Holiness, Free-Will, &c. in
Morals" (F 177n). As he does in the Biographia, he is careful to
emphasize the Platonic idea in opposition to eidola, or "sensuous
images," that are further removed from cognition and knowledge.
Coleridge begins to make stronger claims on behalf of reason with
his introduction of Jacobi's definition of reason as the organ
concerned with "spiritual objects, the Universal, the Eternal, and
the Necessary." Reason, Coleridge insists, is in fact an organ
identical with its objects: "Thus, God, the Soul, eternal Truth,
&c. are the objects of Reason; but they are themselves reason"
(F 156). He appeals to Milton: "We name God the Supreme Reason; and
Milton says, 'Whence the Soul Reason receives, and Reason is her
Being" (PL 5: 486-87). Animals may possess understanding (what
Hooker, Bacon, and Hobbes called "discourse, or the discursive
acuity"), but they entirely lack reason: "an understanding
enlightened by reason Shakespear gives as the contra-distinguishing
character of man, under the name discourse of reason" (F 156;
Hamlet 1.ii.50). "The human understanding," he concludes,
"possesses two distinct organs, the outward sense, and 'the
mind's eye" which is reason" (F 156). Coleridge appeals,
then, to the authority of Milton and Shakespeare to argue for 1) the
identity of reason with its objects and 2) the subsumption of the reason
under the understanding. The section on "Reason and
Understanding" does not simply distinguish between the two
faculties along Kantian/Jacobian lines but, significantly, subordinates
reason (the only faculty capable of making Kant blush: "Since I am
now to give a definition of this supreme faculty of cognition, I find
myself in some embarrassment" [CPR 387]) to the understanding. (37)
What is to be gained by this subordination of reason to the higher
faculty of understanding? Coleridge provides a clue when he says
"If the reader therefore will take the trouble of beating in mind
these and the following explanations, he will have removed before hand
every possible difficulty from the Friend's political section"
(F 157). The answer, I think, is that in redeeming the understanding
from the penury of bureaucratic middle-management, elevating it to what
Deleuze would call the "chairmanship" of the mental faculties,
Coleridge provides a new necessary condition of political knowledge.
With this condition in place, the perceived mistake of his own
radicalism, and perhaps even the excesses of the Revolution, may have
been averted.
The Kantian definition of the understanding used by
Coleridge--" the faculty of thinking and forming
judgments"--does not by itself justify or explain the definition of
the understanding in the political section as "the faculty of
suiting measures to circumstances." These appear to be two vastly
different operations, one being a basic act of perception (or a
comparison of perceptions) and the other an active engagement with the
objective world or even a refined skill in the art of policy-making.
Kant suggests a link when he posits two species of judgment: theoretical
and practical. Theoretical judgment applies a concept to a determinate
given object; practical judgment determines how to produce an object (in
this sense a goal or purpose). The understanding, though, is for Kant
not responsible for practical judgment. Coleridge's placement of
both of them in the understanding, suggesting that they are the same
sort of thing, is perhaps justified by the impossibility of assigning
these operations to any other faculty. The reason, we have seen, has its
eye on the super-sensuous, operating outside the realm of
"circumstances" altogether, and the imagination's duties,
conspicuously absent in The Friend, are defined elsewhere in more vital
and esemplastic terms. So to the understanding are left the seemingly
mundane tasks of making connections between appearances and forming
judgments about them. Coleridge extends the sense of "forming
judgments," allowing the phrase to signify the recognition of
appropriateness or "suitability." It is necessary for
Coleridge that this ability is denied to reason. Reason alone is
insufficient in the art of governing and being governed. It can only
provide principles which the understanding must apply to particular
circumstances. The cautious moderation of this theory, precisely the
attitude Hume promotes towards the end of his Treatise, is predicated on
a critique of reason as the guiding faculty in political affairs. The
position, though, is ultimately Kantian: pure political ideas and ideals
are not things that have validity in their own right, but are relevant
insofar as they regulate an approach to politics that is grounded in
experience. The understanding, furnished by sense experience and
enlightened by reason, is the means of this regulation.
The third and final political system adumbrated by Coleridge in The
Friend is that which "denies all rightful origins to government,
except insofar as they are derivable from principles contained in the
REASON of Man, and judges all the relations of man in society by the
laws of moral necessity, according to IDEAS" (F 178). The
fundamental principle of the theory is that "Nothing is to be
deemed rightful in civil society, or to be tolerated as such, but what
is capable of being demonstrated out of the original laws of the pure
Reason" (F 178). The assumption of the theory is that
"Whatever is not every where necessary, is no where right" (F
178). It is the system of, most notably, Rousseau and the "French
economists," presumably physiocrats such as Quesnay, Turgot, and de
Nemours. It insists that the only rightful form of government "must
be framed on such principles that every individual follows his own
Reason while he obeys the laws of the constitution, and performs the
will of the state while he follows the dictates of his own Reason"
(F 194). Coleridge's objection to this theory of "pure
rationality" is based on a suspicion of the general will. He sees
no necessary reason why the general will must reflect either the reason
or the interests of the people from whom it supposedly originates. There
is a "mere probability" that it does; "and thus we
already find ourselves beyond the magic circle of the pure Reason, and
within the sphere of the understanding and prudence" (F 193). The
apotheosis of reason in France, Coleridge argues; ended disastrously
because pure reason, unaided by the understanding, is incapable of
making judgments based on perception. It can provide only the principles
which the understanding must apply to specific circumstances.
If all of this seems like the safe, common-sense politics of a
former radical coming to terms with his own apostasy, it is because it
is. There is, of course, limited political value in insisting that
things must be judged in the specificity of their circumstances (the
claim itself is so general and self-evident as to resist critical
inquiry); and a prudential politics based on the understanding hardly
makes for inspiring ideology, radical or reactionary. Throughout
Coleridge's analysis is the suggestion that he is no longer prone
to unmanly excess, but is a mature, practical political thinker capable
of suiting measures to circumstances. Behind this familiar, even
predictable, rhetoric of moderation, though, is a hierarchy of mental
faculties in political affairs that runs counter to both
eighteenth-century rationalism and critical assumptions about the
Romantic view of the mind. The reason and the imagination are here
subordinated to a faculty almost all thinkers of the period acknowledged
in animals and idiots. The privileging of the understanding in The
Friend is part of a project to secure a moderate cast of mind and an
increasingly conservative political agenda. As John Morrow observes,
Coleridge develops in The Friend a philosophical defense of
property-based politics. This defense involves a remarkable link between
the possession of property and the mental faculties. Coleridge writes:
[W]here individual landed property exists, there must be inequality
of property: the nature of the earth and the nature of the mind unite to
make the contrary impossible. ... Now it is impossible to deduce the
Right of Property from pure Reason. The utmost which Reason could give
would be a property in the forms of things, as far as the forms were
produced by individual power. In the matter it could give no property.
... Rousseau himself expressly admits, that Property cannot be deduced
from the Laws of Reason and Nature; and he ought therefore to have
admitted at the same time, that his whole theory was a thing of air. (F
200, my emphasis)
Coleridge's misreading of Rousseau aside (Barbara Rooke
helpfully points out that Rousseau nowhere makes such an admission in
his Social Contract), this passage makes explicit what is at stake in
the hierarchy of faculties. One simply cannot deduce, Coleridge argues,
the right of property from pure reason. The argument presumably is that
pure reason operates in an autonomous world of concepts and ideas,
dealing with the objective world only through the mediation of the
understanding and, in turn, sensation. The cynic may be tempted to view
this conclusion--the impossibility of deducing the right of property
from pure reason--as the first principle of Coleridge's entire
analysis, the assumption motivating the whole system. In this view,
Coleridge's mental hierarchy exists so that the right of
property--that is to say, the necessity of the inequality of
property--may have some other, more secure epistemological basis. The
cynic would, I think, be fight in taking this view, but it is limited
insofar as it suggests that Coleridge's primary concern is the
world of matter and not the world of spirit. At the same time, I do not
wish to suggest the opposite, if only because Coleridge's place in
the pantheist tradition implies that he did not always find such a
dualistic vocabulary useful, even if it was the dominant vocabulary of
the time or the one most readily available to him. I do wish to suggest
that Coleridge's philosophiCal defense of property-based politics
may have been as much in the service of philosophy as it was in the
service of property. An appeal to the material interests of his readers,
in a work persistently charged with "obscurity," is thus part
of a larger strategy which included the rejection of French rationalism
and the exposition of a uniquely Coleridgean brand of English
conservatism rooted in transcendentalism. Coleridge, we remember,
declared that he had snapped his "squeaking baby-trumpet of
Sedition" in 1798, the same year he began his life-long study of
Kant. (38)
If one accepts, as Coleridge does, that the nature of the mind is
such that it entails the inequality of property--or even more generally,
that there exists a direct relationship between how the mind functions
and how societies are structured--then one requires a sufficiently
generative psychology, i.e. one capable of producing changes in the
physical world by virtue of its very structure. The partitioning of the
mind in faculty psychology, essentially the construction of a set of
mental enclosures, provided such a structure. Faculty psychology is, if
one allows the term, the "natural" psychology of
property-based bourgeois culture. In Coleridge's version of it, the
unequal endowment of mental faculties, the rejection of Rousseau's
claim that "Reason is not susceptible of degree," makes the
necessity of inequality more plausible. It is perhaps here that
Coleridge's relationship to the Enlightenment, at least the
pre-Kantian Enlightenment, is most evident. It is only from the reason
that we can derive principles, and it is left to the understanding to
apply these principles. "This however gives no proof that Reason
alone ought to govern and direct human beings, either as Individuals or
as States. It ought not to do this, because it cannot" (F 199, my
emphasis). The laws of reason, Coleridge argues, are unable to satisfy
the "first conditions of Human Society" (F 199). The
"first conditions" of human society must rely on the
understanding, "enlightened by past experience and immediate
observation, and determining our choice by comparisons of
expediency" (F 196). This is the second, correct theory of
government, only briefly discussed by Coleridge before he attacks the
third theory of "pure rationality." The relative inattention
given to this theory of expediency suggests that Coleridge's
purposes are more proscriptive than prescriptive. The principles of
political knowledge should not, because they cannot, be deduced from
reason alone. Just as "Dejection: An Ode" exhibits something
resembling a real fear of the imagination in its seventh stanza, so do
The Friend's political essays exhibit something resembling a real
fear of the untethered reason.
This apprehension about the potentially devastating effects of pure
rationalism is occasioned not only by the threat it poses to private
property, but also by the political consequences it had in France. The
reliance on principles derived from reason alone, such as the general
will, was for Coleridge, as it was for Burke, the precondition of the
Terror and Napoleon's rise to power.
With a wretched parrotry [the National Assembly] wrote and
harangued without ceasing of the Volonte generale--the inalienable
sovereignty of the people: and by these high-sounding phrases led on the
vain, ignorant, and intoxicated populace to wild excess and wilder
expectations, which entailing on them the bitterness of disappointment
cleared the way for military despotism, for the satanic Government of
Horror under the Jacobins, and of Terror under the Corsican. (F 194)
The targets here are the framers of the 1791 constitution, although
claims made on behalf of the volonte generale and the "natural,
inalienable, and sacred rights of man" were voiced in considerably
stronger terms in the 1789 Declaration of the Rights of Man and Citizen.
The 1791 constitution is, in fact, a much more sober document than
Coleridge suggests, with the debates leading up to it dominated, at
least in the beginning, by the moderate monarchiens. Intoxication,
"wild excess and wilder expectations" may have been the result
of the new political culture that emerged between 1789 and 1791, but one
would be hard pressed to find them in the constitution itself.
Similarly, Coleridge's claim that the framers of the 1791
constitution "deduce, that the people itself is its own sole
rightful legislator, and at most dare only recede so far from its right
as to delegate to chosen deputies the power of representing and
declaring the general will" (F 195) is misleading. The phrase
"general will" is never explicitly mentioned in the document,
the most objectionable article being perhaps the now modest republican
claim that "the nation, from which alone all powers emanate, may
exercise [sovereignty] only by delegation." (39) So Coleridge, in
his effort to establish a direct link between the ideas of philosophes
such as Rousseau and the terror of the Robespierre-led Jacobins and
Napoleon, constructs a reading of the constitution in which phrases such
as "clear the way" perform a fair amount of work. Coleridge,
following Burke, here remains committed to the social and political
efficacy of ideas, confident in their ability to determine material
conditions and not the other way around.
The displacement of reason by the understanding as the paramount
political faculty has ethical implications as well. Specifically,
Rousseau's theory of pure rationality, the idea that one can derive
fundamental political principles from the reason alone, seems to
jeopardize the moral judgment. "Apply his principles to any case,
in which the sacred and inviolable Laws of Morality are immediately
interested, all becomes just and pertinent" (F 194). This is so
because each man is compelled to act according to the dictates of his
own conscience, which, as we have seen, is no more than the
"testifying state of the coincidence or discordance of the free
will with the reason." Since neither free will nor reason is
susceptible of degree, the dictates of conscience are universally
irreproachable. Coleridge follows Kant in declaring the categorical
imperative to be the "one universal and sufficient principle and
guide of morality" (F 194). The justification of this claim,
Coleridge argues, is the fact that "the object of morality is not
the outward act, but the internal maxim of our actions" (F 194).
"And," Coleridge concedes, "so far it is infallible"
(F 194). Coleridge thus rejects consequentialist or utilitarian ethics
in favor of a virtue ethics in which the inner "purity of our
motives" is the basis for all moral judgment. Laurence Lockridge,
Coleridge's greatest ethical critic, correctly situates this purity
of motives--or, more broadly, the will--at the center of
Coleridge's thought. "Among the many foundational concepts in
Coleridge," Lockridge claims in his review of the Opus Maximum,
"the most fundamental is Will--the Absolute Will of God as the
source of all that is, and the finite personal Will of human beings, the
source of our individuality and, if conjoined with Reason, our goodness
and wisdom." (40) The conjunction of the finite personal will with
the principles derived from reason results in "virtuous
habits," which, for Coleridge, are formed "by the very means
in which knowledge is communicated" (F 171). Coleridge devotes the
majority of the first volume of The Friend to "detail and ground
the conditions under which the communication of truth is commanded or
forbidden to us as individuals" (F 166). The communication of truth
is, not surprisingly, commanded more frequently than forbidden, as the
conditions of communicating a "right though inadequate notion"
are few and rare. As he asserts in the essay entitled "Virtue and
Knowledge," "[T]he essence of virtue consists in the
principle" (F 167) and "with clearer conceptions in the
understanding, the principle of action would become purer in the
will" (F 168). Virtue and knowledge are so intimately linked that
to take care of the one is to ensure that the other will follow. There
is a contradiction here, as Lockridge notes in Coleridge the Moralist,
between the "formalism" of an individual virtue ethics
("probable consequences and personal inclination are of little to
no import in determining what is right and wrong") and the
prudential model of expediency Coleridge prescribes for the state:
"In The Friend, he often seems to say that the affairs of the state
should proceed on the basis of prudence alone; the only thing the state
must consider is the outward act. This muddles, of course, his position
as a moral critic of social and political affairs. How can he continue
to denounce the expediency he seems in these instances to be
recommending?" (41) One resolution of the contradiction is perhaps
to concede the incommensurability of public and private morality. The
"main office" of government is for Coleridge the regulation of
social organizations according to particular circumstances, a
responsibility that perhaps demands no greater morality than that of its
constituent members. "Public" morality, not far removed from
the alleged interests of the general will, may too easily slip into the
"wretched parrotry" Coleridge abhorred in the National
Assembly.
To concede the incommensurability of public and private
morality--or to deny the existence of a public morality above and beyond
a number of disparate private moralities--does not, however, solve the
problem of moral action in the public sphere. Coleridge, as noted,
admits the possibility that reason is capable of formulating a principle
of moral action, such as the categorical imperative. Yet, he argues, it
remains entirely incapable of deducing "the form and matter of a
rightful Government, the main office of which is to regulate the outward
actions of particular bodies of men, according to their particular
circumstances" (F 195-96). Rousseau, then, is mistaken in believing
that reason, which Coleridge acknowledges to be a sufficient guide in
individual morality, is equally capable of determining moral action in
the public sphere. Coleridge tacitly invokes the traditional
morality-prudence distinction, arguing that the former is the domain of
the individual conscience (and therefore the reason) and the latter the
domain of public decision-making (the understanding). (42) The two
converge most conspicuously in the case of political obligation, in
which the claims of the individual and those of the state must achieve
some sort of rapprochement. As Morrow notes, obligation for Coleridge
has a moral basis: it springs "from a sense of duty which reflected
an acknowledgment of the appropriateness of particular
arrangements" (79). In Coleridge's terms, "the whole Duty
of Obedience to Governors is derived from, and dependent on" the
idea, as opposed to the fact, of a social contract. Again, "[I]n my
sense, the word Contract is merely synonymous with the sense of duty
acting in a specific direction, i.e. determining our moral relations, as
members of a body politic" (F 173-74). That political obligation,
described here and elsewhere as a "sense" or
"feeling," should be derived from the "idea" of a
contract may seem surprising; but Hume, for one, readily granted the
ability of complex ideas (such as a social contract) to produce new
impressions. For Coleridge, though, the word "contract"
signifies merely this "sense of duty." There is an apparent
tautology here, with the "whole Duty of Obedience to
Governors" being derived from an idea of a contract, or "the
sense of duty acting in a specific direction." Coleridge is not
presenting the sequence in any systematic way, but one may conclude that
political obligation is predicated on a particular form of political
knowledge, namely the idea of a contract. The "idea" of a
contract and a "sense of duty" appear to arise
contemporaneously. There is no impression from which we derive our idea
of duty; but rather this "sense," or feeling, of duty simply
is the "idea" we have of a contract. As we have seen,
Coleridge rejects the entire notion that all our ideas are faint copies
of our impressions, arguing instead that, as far as political knowledge
is concerned, feelings, or impressions, and thoughts, or ideas, are not
so easily distinguishable.
The political essays of The Friend, then, situate the understanding
at the center of an epistemology appropriate to the application of the
principles of political knowledge. It is only through the understanding
that the theory of expediency, of prudential politics, may be said to
operate. Coleridge's argument ultimately takes a middle ground on
the status of the principle-i.e., Coleridge is, as Lockridge puts it,
"attracted to principles in principle," but is skeptical of
thinkers, such as Rousseau (or even, one may say, people like Godwin and
Thelwall), who rely exclusively on principles derived from pure
reason--and grants priority to the idea. The principle, we have seen,
merely actualizes the idea, and the idea itself "is living,
productive, partaketh of infinity, and, as Bacon has sublimely observed,
containeth an endless power of semination" (SM 23-24). By granting
such a mysteriously generative power to the idea, as far removed from
Hume's copies of impressions as possible, Coleridge makes room for
a highly adaptable political system, one capable of applying principles
to constantly changing circumstances.
4
It is precisely in light of this fact that we can begin to
understand more fully Coleridge's rejection of Hume, with which we
began and with which we will conclude. Just as Coleridge had to
repudiate Hardey in order to make room for the creative imagination, so
does he have to reject Hume in order to make room for the endlessly
disseminating idea. The status of the idea is strategically important in
the formation of an epistemology that is to have political consequences.
Because the structure of the mind is such that it demands a particular
form of social organization, Coleridge is careful to delineate a mind
capable of applying principles derived from pure reason and, at once,
not so utterly reliant on those principles as to impair its ability to
react to changing circumstances. The Coleridgean idea, actualized by
principles but not determined by them, is thus able to remain both
living and autonomous. This autonomy is realized in the flexibility of
the understanding, the faculty on which practical and political affairs
must depend. The attitude which corresponds to the proper functioning of
the understanding is one of cautious moderation, which, as we have
noted, is the one Hume ultimately prescribes in the conduct of practical
affairs. This, of course, would have resonated with the political
attitudes Coleridge inherited from Burke.
Yet despite what Hume says at the end of his Treatise, Coleridge is
unable to accept the political consequences of the theory of knowledge
expounded in Book I, "Of the Understanding." Specifically,
Hume radicalized Locke's empiricism (thus making it ridiculous)
and, in doing so, continued a tradition that was appropriate for a
particular phase in English history insofar as it served the interests
of "national pride." This phase, Coleridge suggests, is over.
In his Lectures on the History of Philosophy, Coleridge refers to the
beginning of Hume's essay on causality (THN 1.3.1415).
"Everywhere it is, you have no real truth but what is derived from
your senses, it is in vain to talk of your ideas of reflection for what
are they? They must have been originally in our senses or there is no
ground for them" (LHP 2: 572). This is a mostly fair assessment of
Hume's position, although Hume readily admits the reality of ideas
derived from "impressions of reflection" (THN 1.3.2). What
follows is of greater interest:
So many circumstances combined together as to make it a kind of
national pride in the first place, and secondly, the interest of almost
each of the parties to cry [up] Mr. Locke. ... I can therefore say this
finally with regard to Locke, that it was at the beginning of a time
when they felt one thing: that the great advantage was to convince
mankind that the whole process of reacting upon their own thoughts or
endeavoring to deduce any truth from them was mere presumption, and
henceforward men were to be entirely under the guidance of their senses.
This was most favorable to a country already busy with politics, busy
with commerce, and [in] which yet there was a pride in nature [so] that
a man would not like to remain ignorant of that which had been called
the queen of sciences, which was supposed above all things to [elevate]
the mind, which had produced a word which a man had overthrown, had ...
that of "philosopher." What a delight to find it all nonsense,
that there was nothing but what a man in three hours might know as well
as the Archbishop of Canterbury! This exactly suited the state of the
nation, and I believe it was a symptom of that state of providential
government of the world which observed the nearer union of the kingdoms
of Europe to each other. (LHP 2: 572-73)
Coleridge is especially prescient here, anticipating the
symptomatic reading of philosophy and ideology that has come in and out
of fashion since Marx. Coleridge sees the end of the seventeenth cent,
then, as the beginning of empiricism's dominance in British
philosophy and attributes that success to two conditions: I) the limited
leisure time available to an incipient British middle-class in an
increasingly commercial society and 2) a desire, the residue apparently
of a theologically-dominated superstructure, on behalf of that class to
attain particular kinds of knowledge. Empiricism "exactly suited
the state of the nation" because it required nothing other than the
evidence of one's senses while granting that evidence the sort of
solidity formerly granted to faith-based theological claims. It was a
"symptom" of a state of European society in which a
continent-wide division of philosophical labor sponsored the growth of
philosophies suited to the soil of individual nation-states,
specifically empiricism in Britain, rationalism in France, and
transcendentalism in Germany, Locke inaugurated the movement in England
and, Coleridge suggests, Hume carried it to its absurd and pernicious
conclusion. Coleridge seems unsympathetic to the claim that Hume, in an
important and direct sense, made German transcendentalism possible,
focusing instead on his association with Locke and the overreliance on
the senses.
Coleridge's narrative is perhaps too schematic for our tastes,
but it does reveal his conception of how philosophies are
"suited" to the needs of a nation, even if an explicitly
causal relation is never established or specified. My repetition of
Coleridge's "suited" here is deliberate, if only because
it recalls the language used in his definition of the understanding in
The Friend: the "faculty of suiting measures to
circumstances." It also recalls his contention, cited above, that
there is a correspondence between the structure of the mind and the
structure of the social or political world: the mind is somehow
structurally suited to the world (an idea that would find frequent
expression in Wordsworth's poetry of "fitting and
fitted"). The nature of this correspondence is perhaps necessarily
vague, although I have attempted to sketch some of its outlines above.
The correspondence, I have argued, hinges on the operation of the
understanding, which is the only faculty capable of mediating between
subject and object, the reason and the world of practical affairs. It is
also the only faculty capable of resolving the theological doubts posed
by Hume's skepticism, however mitigated it may finally be. These
are the doubts with which we began: the precarious status of the idea of
God in a system whereby all our ideas are derived from impressions,
"which are correspondent to them, and which they exactly
resemble" (THN 1.1.1). Hume and skeptics like him, Coleridge
argues, take refuge in the claim that the "principle of Faith was
utterly out of their scope" (LHP 1: 332). This is not an option for
Coleridge, and his response has at times been understood as an embrace
of the certainty promised by the transcendental imagination. As Cairns
Craig argues, "The Kantian/ Coleridgean conception of the
imagination is one which seeks--or, indeed, already assumes--the
possibility of certainty" (32). The alleged certainty of the
transcendental imagination, or the possibility of this certainty, does
not, however, apply to the kinds of knowledge Coleridge would refer to
as "sacred truths." In the face of Humean skepticism,
Coleridge asks, in his lectures on the history of philosophy, "What
shall we do?":
It is most certain that the subjects most interesting to our best
hopes, most entitled to our Faith, are not within the domains of
faculties the stuff of which is given by the Senses--and if this be
granted, how are we to distinguish between dreams and sacred
truths?--The mid way seems plain--. Congruity with Reason--that which
the Understanding convinces itself to be above the Understanding, or
beyond it--but not contradictory to it--Still it must be of universal
validity--for instance, the Categorical Imperative of the Moral Law--not
pretending to any nostrum the Rule being this--We affirm that truths
there are higher than those of the understanding deduced from experience
of the senses; but that those who faithfully exert their Understanding
without sophistication from passion and appetite will be the first to
see and admit this--Hill above Hill--First surmount the first--&
then/ (LHP 1: 332)
The halting, hesitant cadence of the passage--perhaps only par@
explained by the transcription from Frere's shorthand--suggests an
exhausted Coleridge, covering familiar, tiresome philosophic terrain so
that the prospect of the next hill may become visible. It is as if only
now, in 1818 and under financial duress, that Coleridge is able to
overcome the charge laid against him by Carlyle: that instead of
decidedly setting out, "he would accumulate formidable apparatus,
logical swim-bladders, transcendental life-preservers and other
precautionary and vehiculatory gear" (J. S. Mill, Complete Works
10: 56). Here he has finally set out; but it is not with the dialectical
zigzaggery of 1798, when Hazlitt anecdotally observed that "he
continually crossed me on the way by shifting from one side of the
footpath to the other." (43) Now, for Coleridge, "the mid way
seems plain." The "mid way" is precisely that of the
understanding, the faculty capable of recognizing what is above or
beyond it, but not contradictory to it. The dispassionate exertion of
the understanding is necessary in the acquisition of "sacred
truths" above and beyond it.
These pedestrian metaphors appear to have led us from political to
theological concerns, but Coleridge, in his philosophical lectures of
1818, broadens the centrality of the understanding from the kinds of
political knowledge discussed above to sacred truths that are "most
interesting to our best hopes." In short, Coleridge by 1818 had
developed a conception of the understanding in which it is the central
and dominant faculty in what one may call his political epistemology,
with profound effects on his conception of the conditions of knowledge
more generally. For the mind to know certain things--more precisely, for
the mind to have an idea of an-] real importance, such as substance,
God, property, obligation, contract, or the perfect state--it must rely
on the essentially mediating capacity of the understanding. In this
faculty, which is none other than the prudential faculty of
"suiting measures to circumstances," the oppositional tensions
which mark Coleridge's thought are suspended: subject and object,
reason and imagination, principle and policy, individual and state.
Coleridge's own self-representation as a transcendental thinker in
the dialectical tradition is, in this view, subsumed into a larger
picture of the practical application of particular kinds of knowledge.
The aim of this essay has not been to systematize Coleridge, but, by
attending to his conception of political knowledge, to study some of the
epistemic structures that support the wide range of his thought.
The University of Chicago
(1.) G. W. F. Hegel, Science of Logic, trans. A. V. Miller (London:
G. Allen and Unwin, 1976) 755.
(2.) Richard Rorty, Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (Cambridge:
Cambridge UP, 1989) 154.
(3.) This is not to say that the focus in Romanticism on the
dialectic between reason and imagination is not without its own
justification. One only needs to think of Wordsworth's claim in the
Mt. Snowdon episode that the imagination is "reason in her most
exalted mood" (The Prelude 14); or, of the many instances in
Coleridge's philosophical development, his fascination with Lessing
during his 1798 stay in Germany, when it was precisely the
"mingling and interpenetration of reason and imagination" that
attracted him to Lessing. The understanding may fit uneasily into a
conflict of mental faculties--where, in a Blakean context, the struggle
between Urizen and Orc contains the most drama--but this incongruity
reveals, I think, what is most interesting and distinctive about
Coleridge's political thought.
(4.) Samuel Taylor Coleridge, The Friend, ed. Barbara Rooke in The
Collected Works of Samuel Taylor Coleridge, Vol. 4 (Princeton: Princeton
UP, 1969) 176. Unless noted otherwise, all quotations from The Friend
come from the 1818 version (Vol. 1 of The Friend in the Collected
Works), hereafter cited as F in the text, as this was the last edition
Coleridge saw through the press.
(5.) Oxford Dictionary of English Etymology, ed. C. T. Onions
(Oxford: Clarendon, 1966).
(6.) See Kant's discussion of "principles" in the
Critique of Pure Reason (CPR), trans, and ed. Paul Guyer and Allen Wood
(Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1998) 387-88.
(7.) Immanuel Kant. Critique of Practical Reason (CPrR) in
Practical Philosophy, trans, and ed. Mary J. Gregor (Cambridge:
Cambridge UP, 1996) 153.
(8.) This "Kantian/Coleridgean" version of Romanticism is
hardly the result of a generation of philosophically-minded critics. It
extends to some of Coleridge's earliest critics, such as J. S.
Mill: "Now the Germano-Coleridgean doctrine is, in our view of the
matter, the result of such a reaction. It expresses the revolt of the
human mind against the philosophy of the eighteenth century. It is
ontological, because that was experimental; conservative, because that
was innovative; religious, because so much of that was infidel; concrete
and historical, because that was abstract and metaphysical; poetical,
because that was matter-of-fact and prosaic. In every respect it flies
off in a contrary direction to its predecessor...." Complete Works
of John Stuart Mill, Vol. 10, ed. J.M. Robson (Toronto: U of Toronto P,
1969) 125.
(9.) Stanley Cavell, In Quest of the Ordinary: Lines of Skepticism
and Romanticism (Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1988) 41.
(10.) Cairns Craig, "Coleridge, Hume, and the Chains of the
Romantic Imagination" in Scotland and the Borders of Romanticism,
ed. Leith Davis, Ian Duncan, and Janet Sorensen (Cambridge: Cambridge
UP, 2004) 32.
(11.) Seamus Perry, "Enlightened Romantics" in Times
Literary Supplement (5920, August 20, 2004): 7-8.
(12.) S. T. Coleridge, Collected Letters of Samuel Taylor Coleridge
(CL), ed. Earl Leslie Griggs (Oxford: Clarendon, 1956--) 2: 928.
(13.) S. T. Coleridge, Biographia Literaria (BL), Vol. 1, ed. James
Engell and W. Jackson Bate (Princeton: Princeton UP, 1983) 291.
(14.) S. T. Coleridge, The Statesman's Manual (SM) in Lay
Sermons, ed. R. J. White (Princeton: Princeton UP, 1972) 22.
(15.) David Hume, Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion (1779),
Part 7. Philo, the hardlined skeptic, relates to Cleanthes, the more
cautious skeptic, the Brahmin theory that the "world arose from an
infinite spider, who spun this whole complicated mass from his bowels,
and annihilates afterwards the whole or any part of it, by absorbing it
again and resolving it into his own essence." The argument that a
possible world exists wholly inhabited by these spiders prompts Philo to
assert "Why an orderly system may not be spun from the belly as
well as from the brain, it will be difficult for [Cleanthes] to give a
satisfactory reason" (DCNR 51). The argument did not convince
Cleanthes, nor did it convince Coleridge.
(16.) David Hume, Treatise on Human Nature (THN), ed. David Fate
Norton and Mary J. Norton (Oxford: Oxford UP, 2000) 112.
(17.) S. T. Coleridge, The Notebooks of Samuel Taylor Coleridge,
Vol. 2, 1804-1808, ed. Kathleen Coburn (London: Routledge & Kegan
Paul, 1961) 2370.
(18.) See the discussion of necessity in SM: "Suffer me to
inform or remind you, that there is a threefold Necessity. There is a
logical, and there is a mathematical, necessity; but the latter is
always hypothetical, and both subsist formally only, not in any real
object. Only by the intuition and immediate spiritual consciousness of
the idea of God, as the One and Absolute, at once the Ground and Cause,
who alone containeth in himself the ground of his own nature, and
therein of all natures, do we arrive at the third, which alone is a real
objective, necessity. Here the immediate consciousness decides: the idea
is its own evidence, and is insusceptible of all other" (SM 32,
final emphasis mine).
(19.) For Locke, ideas are those things furnished to the
understanding through either sensation or reflection (Essay Concerning
Human Understanding, ed. Peter H. Nidditch [Oxford: Oxford UP, 1975]
1.ii.3-4). Knowledge is "nothing but the perception of the
connexion and agreement, or disagreement and repugnancy of any of our
Ideas" (EHU 4.1.2).
(20.) The OED cites Coleridge as the first to use "educt"
in this way ("educt," The Oxford English Dictionary, 2nd ed.,
1989, OED Online: Oxford UP, 4 Apr. 2000).
(21.) I use this phrase, used by Kant in The Critique of Judgment
to signify the feeling of aesthetic pleasure, in the more general sense
of an "interaction" among the various faculties. It is
significant, though, that the language used by Kant to describe
aesthetic pleasure may apply equally well to the formation of the
Coleridgean idea. In both cases, there is a reaction against the
perceived rigidity of dogmatic rationalism or empiricism and a
willingness to recognize the reality of certain mental events that would
ordinarily be subordinated to propositional or discursive reasoning.
(22.) In the now classic definition from The Statesman's
Manual: the symbol "always partakes of the Reality which it renders
intelligible; and while it enunciates the whole, abides itself as a
living part in that Unity, of which it is representative" (SM 30).
(23.) As R. J. White notes in his edition of the Lay Sermons, this
idea is untraced in Bacon.
(24.) See John Guillory's widely influential analysis in
Cultural Capital: The Problem of Literary Canon Formation (Chicago: U of
Chicago P, 1993).
(25.) S. T. Coleridge, Marginalia IV (CM), ed. H. J. Jackson and
George Whalley (Princeton: Princeton UP, 1998) 75.
(26.) The phrasing here is reminiscent of Coleridge's claim,
derived from Schelling, in the Biographia that "Matter has no
Inward" (BL 1: 133). The language of surface and depth, appearance
and reality, to describe both the Scottish and matter is suggestive: it
was Hume, after all. who banished the ideas of substance, self, and
essence from philosophy altogether. Scots like Hume, then, appear to be
all surface and no depth, acutely aware of their own ideas but
resolutely determined not to inquire into their origin.
(27.) S. T. Coleridge, Lectures 1818-1819: On the History of
Philosophy (LHP), ed. J.R. de J. Jackson (Princeton: Princeton UP,
2000), Vol. 1: 259.
(28.) Knud Haakonssen, "The Structure of Hume's Political
Theory" in The Cambridge Companion to Hume, ed. David Fate Norton
(Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1993) 182.
(29.) David Hume, Political Essays (PE), ed. Charles W. Hendel
(Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1953) 13.
(30.) David Hume, Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals (EPM)
(Amherst: Prometheus, 2004) 196.
(31.) Hume would revise his position in ''Of the Origin
of Government" (1777), where he contends, much as he does in
"Of the Original Contract," that authority is established
first by force, then gradually by a mixture of force and consent, and
maintained by habits of submission.
(32.) David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge
(Oxford: Clarendon, 1978) 496.
(33.) Benedict de Spinoza, Tractatus Politicus in The Chief Works
of Benedict de Spinoza, trans. R. H. M. Elwes (London: George Bell and
Sons, 1889) 1.1.1-6.
(34.) See John Morrow, Coleridge's Political Thought:
Property, Morality, and the Limits of Traditional Discourse (New York:
St. Martin's, 1990).
(35.) S. T. Coleridge, Letter to Rev. Joseph Hughes, Nov. 24, 1819
in CL 6: Appendix B, 1049.
(36.) Immanuel Kant, Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, trans.
Paul Carus (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1977) 291.
(37.) It should be noted that Kant, in the Analytic of Principles,
suggests something similar to Coleridge's subordination of the
understanding to reason: the "Understanding-in-General"
(Verstandes uberhaupt) consists of the understanding (Verstand), the
power of judgment (Urteilskraft), and reason (Vernunft). Kant's
"Understanding-in-General" does not, however, perform the
intuitive acts of apprehension and identification Coleridge assigns to
the "discourse of reason," or the understanding enlightened by
reason.
(38.) S. T. Coleridge, Letter to George Coleridge, March 10, 1798
in CL 1: 397.
(39.) Constitution of 1791 in A Documentary Survey of the French
Revolution, ed. John Hall Stewart (New York: Macmillan, 1951) 234.
(40.) Laurence Lockridge, Review of Coleridge's Opus Maximum
in The Wordsworth Circle (Fall 2002): 133.
(41.) Laurence Lockridge, Coleridge the Moralist (Ithaca: Cornell
UP, 1977) 268.
(42.) In upholding this distinction, Coleridge most clearly
diverges from the kind of pragmatist ethics suggested by his repeated
endorsement of a prudential politics of expediency.
(43.) William Hazlitt, "My First Acquaintance with Poets"
(1823) in The Selected Writings of William Hazlitt (London: Picketing
and Chatto, 1998) 9: 100.