Tracing fraternity in the social sciences and Catholic social teaching.
Mardones, Rodrigo ; Marinovic, Alejandra
DURING THE FRENCH REVOLUTION fraternity became a political
principle together with liberty and equality. (1) These principles
altered the course of political history asymmetrically. Liberty and
equality were incorporated into constitutions and inspired political
parties and movements; meanwhile, fraternity, the "strangest in the
trinity," remained relatively forgotten. (2) Fraternity is both a
normative concept and an empirical phenomenon that requires study and
deserves an explanation. Democracies need deep moral roots of a secular
or religious nature in order to function. These roots, which cannot
generate themselves, assure social cooperation and thereby protect and
perpetuate democracy. (3) Fraternity can provide such a moral
foundation. Despite its potential, the principle of fraternity has
languished in the social sciences and broad public sphere.
To philosopher Roberto Mancini, one reason for fraternity's
obscurity has to do with its pretension of universality, which appears
to contradict the reality of social exclusion. Ultimately, fraternity
appears utopian and unattainable and thus not apt for policy. (4)
Therefore, in the social sciences--even within the humanities--the
notion of fraternity is not widely used. Fraternity would contradict the
conflictual nature of power, creating an ontological pessimism in
politics. (5) However, the empirical phenomenon to which it refers, that
is, an attitude of reciprocal care among citizens, has been recognized
and studied largely through the concepts of social cohesion, trust,
social capital, pro-sociality, reciprocity, altruism, democratic
coexistence, civic friendship, community, and solidarity. We approach
fraternity by taking these concepts as a semantic field or semantic
domain as they are not synonymous but refer to approximately the same
phenomenon.
In this article we also show that, as a semantic field, fraternity
is an idea widely used in Catholic Social Teaching (hereafter CST), and
that the principle of fraternity has only recently gained a more
specific and precise meaning. Indeed, the latest encyclicals argue that
the principle of fraternity presupposes the existence of a common
Creator or Father, and by extension, that men should live in reciprocal
love and respect. From that point of view, CST makes an insistent call
for fraternity as a moral virtue at the core of society.
The objective of this article is to advance our understanding of
the affinities and differences between academic conceptualizations of
fraternity and those of CST. As a first step in this task, this article
examines and surveys three social science concepts that seem to have a
"family resemblance" to the notion of fraternity: social
cohesion, trust, and social capital. We then continue our survey with
the concepts of community and solidarity, which have received mixed
attention from law and philosophy. Finally, we enter into the realm of
civic friendship and fraternity, which, while mostly absent from the
social sciences, are often discussed in political theory. (6) We do not
pretend to engage in a linguistic or post-structuralist approach of the
idea of fraternity, but rather in a pragmatic attempt to build a bridge
between some of social sciences' concepts and a philosophical idea
widely relevant to CST. Finally, we present some challenges that the
study of the idea of fraternity poses and how CST may assist in
overcoming them.
Fraternity's Semantic Domain in the Social Sciences
The concept of social cohesion has been associated with a great
variety of issues such as: values and shared meanings, socioeconomic
equality, multiculturality, cooperation, social protection, social
bonds, inclusion, and citizenship. (7) Since 2001, the European Union
has measured social cohesion by social gaps through the so-called Laeken
indicators that encompass four areas: income, employment, education, and
health. In 2007 the United Nations Economic Commission for Latin America
(ECLAC) adjusted the Laeken indicators to better measure the more
pervasive gaps in Latin America and added indicators regarding the role
of democratic institutions and the sense of community belonging. (8) The
development community's literature on social cohesion assumes that
through active social policy socioeconomic gaps may be narrowed, and
this in turn generates a sense of belonging; both produce social
cohesion.
Nobel laureate in economics Gary Becker defines social capital as a
natural part of the human capital of a person found not in
relationships, but in individuals. (9) In contrast, most of the
literature uses the concept of social capital to refer to the value of
relationships and social networks. (10) According to sociologist James
Coleman, social capital refers to the social organizations that
facilitate the attainment of objectives that would not be reached in
their absence, or only at greater cost. (11) One of those objectives is
social cohesion; therefore, one can consider social capital an
ingredient or component of social cohesion.
Sociologist Michael Woolcock classifies social capital by the type
of relationships it involves: first, relationships with close
interpersonal bonds (bonding social capital); and second, capital that
builds bridges between groups (bridging). These two types refer to a
horizontal dimension (between equals). A third type tackles the vertical
dimension and discusses the relationship between individuals and
structures of power, particularly the capacity of these to obtain
resources, information, and benefits from formal institutions, such as
the government (linking). (12) This last type of capital refers to
relationships both up and down the social scale. (13) Thus the effects
of social capital depend on the combinations of the three types of
social capital, some being negative combinations for society. For
example, highly cohesive groups--like gangs--with little capacity to
relate to each other in a country with very weak formal institutions can
result in situations of conflict or exclusion. Political scientist
Francis Fukuyama claims, alternatively, that not just any type of norm
or relationship generates social capital: these must be inspired by
virtues, such as honesty, reciprocity, cooperation, and trust. (14)
If social capital has been conceived of as a component of social
cohesion, trust in turn has been traditionally conceived of as a basic
component of social capital. Regarding the concept of trust, political
scientist Peter Nannestad distinguishes between particularized and
generalized trust and between rational and normative trust.
Particularized trust appears when an individual trusts another with
respect to a specific matter or domain of affairs. (15) Rational trust,
as defined by Margaret Levi and Laura Stoker, is when an
individual's act of trust exposes him to vulnerability: another
individual, a group, or an organization is now able to harm or betray
him. (16) To political scientist Russell Hardin, the individual's
previous experiences determine his predisposition to trust or distrust,
while trustworthinesss would be ensured through institutional
mechanisms, such as contracts that define incentives and punishments.
Hardin points out the economic relevance of trust by quoting two Nobel
Prize laureates Kenneth Arrow and Douglass North. Arrow sees trust as
the social system's lubricant which improves efficiency, and North
perceives that trust reduces transaction costs and thus favors
international competitiveness. (17) In contrast, normative--or
moralist--trust is, according to political scientist Eric Uslaner, a
personal predisposition that transcends individual experience, which is
neither strategic nor based on expected utility or risk but a
commandment to treat people as if they were trustworthy, or some sort of
belief in the goodwill of the other. (18)
Within a more specific political context, policy experts William
Leach and Paul Sabatier discuss trust by considering psychological
dynamics in political settings that are characterized by interpersonal
relationships, such as long-term policy dialogue tables. They found
evidence that participants of these tables tend to honor their promises,
to honestly negotiate, to show respect toward other points of view, and
to express concern for the well-being of others. (19) This is the
interpersonal relational dimension of trust also underlined in the work
of economist Vittorio Pelligra. (20)
While Leach and Sabatier, as well as Pelligra, have concentrated
their studies on interpersonal face-to-face trust, generalized trust in
contrast refers to the idea that an individual can trust people that he
or she does not know; it is more properly a favorable general attitude
toward all human beings. (21) Generalized trust does not limit itself to
people that belong to the same local or national group, as the notion of
community does. Neither does it refer to a specific domain of
well-specified issues in which someone trusts another. (22) Science
writer Marek Kohn calls the latter type of trust thin. While thick trust
arises through frequent interpersonal experience over time, thin trust
is that which is based on reputation, norms, or signs like appearance or
behavior. This second type is particularly important, as it allows the
expansion of the radius of interpersonal relationships beyond firsthand
experience, and does not require a long time lapse. (23)
In their reading of nineteenth-century social theorist Ferdinand
Tonnies and twentieth-century sociologist Robert Nisbet, theologians
Severino Dianich and Carmelo Torcivia contend that the notion of
community seemed focused on a shared feeling of belonging, in which
territory, interpersonal relationships, and participation are key
dimensions, beyond mere functionalism. As community psychology
underlines, not every human group (which is narrowly defined by a vague
sense of belonging) is a community; a precise and shared vision of
common good or purpose is required for the latter. (24)
According to economist Luigino Bruni, social theory contends that
community is the most important social unit of the ancient and
pre-modern worlds--and a lost paradise of warm human relationships that
anonymous contractual societies tend to destroy. In fact, the ancient
world did not experience community in its etymological sense of cum
munus, that is, reciprocal gift, which expresses the equilibrium of
interpersonal relationships. Indeed, in the ancient world society was
less concerned with individuals but instead with hierarchical collective
bodies. Within ancient communities--continues Bruni's
argument--there were hierarchical relationships: wives, children, and
slaves were expropriated of their rights as individuals, as in the
ancient Roman model of the pater familiae. Therefore, it was only in
modernity--with the reaffirmation of individuality and equality--that
community as the place to engage in reciprocal and free interpersonal
relationships could take place. (25)
Mutual concern between citizens has been identified as solidarity
in law, sociology, and psychology. Solidarity is mostly conceived of as
relational or interpersonal, or, in Emile Durkheim's tradition,
mechanical solidarity. Some relate solidarity to social cohesion,
whereas others think that it is the result of a shared project, which
generates unity. In any case, solidarity entails concrete obligations
toward fellow citizens by virtue of common membership to a community.
(26) The pioneering work of sociologist and jurist Georges Gurvitch on
social law made an important contribution to overcoming juridical
individualism of contracts and allowing the emergence of the idea of
social rights, (27) which is arguably the foundation of modern
solidarity, or organic solidarity, following Durkheim's distiction.
Philosopher Kurt Bayertz distinguishes four forms of solidarity:
first, human solidarity as the force that bridges all humankind; second,
social solidarity, a relative of social cohesion in the communitarian
tradition of Emile Durkheim; third, civic solidarity, which alludes to
the functions of the welfare state through social policies addressed to
the needs of citizens; and fourth, political solidarity, which defines
the relationships among members of a community. (28) This last concept
means that the well-being of others enters one's practical
reasoning in a non-instrumental way and cooperation is the expression of
one's duties toward others. (29) To jurist Erhard Denninger,
solidarity refers to more than duties, to a permanent predisposition to
show decency toward other people and respect for the common spirit,
going beyond sentiments and emotions, which to him would constitute the
fallacy of the concept of fraternity. Denninger extends solidarity to a
planetary scale, as it not only refers to a comrade or member of
one's own community, but even to a stranger. (30)
"Concern" is also the key sentiment or emotion in the
idea of civic friendship. Philospher of education David Blacker defines
civic friendship as a certain "reciprocal concern" that is
manifested in the public relationship between citizens. For Blacker,
civic friendship is an imperative that permits the achievement of two
goals. First, it assures certain levels of spiritual, moral, and
aesthetic depth to citizens' political obligations. Second, it
allows citizens to cultivate the capacity to hear and tolerate the views
put forth by other citizens. (31) To political theorist Sybil
Schwarzenbach, civic friendship does not require that citizens be alike
and possess everything in common. (32) Instead, it requires unanimity on
the basics of the constitution as well as a mutual "concern"
for the well-being of fellow citizens expressed through concrete
actions. (33)
Reciprocal concern as a choice to act for the well-being of others
is also a key trait of fraternity. (34) In fact, using the terms
"civic friendship" and "fraternity" synonymously is
common in political philosophy; still, some prefer to make a
distinction. Political theorist Oscar Godoy, for example, argues that
the concept of fraternity in its ambition of universality and
abstraction is less comprehensible than that of friendship, which is
related to people's everyday experience. Further, Godoy prefers to
use the term friendship in its original Greek sense philia, as it is the
oldest sense on record. (35) Schwarzenbach for her part indicates that
she prefers to use the concept of civic friendship, instead of
fraternity, because the latter has a masculine connotation (fraternity),
which excludes women (sorority). (36) Also Nelson rejects as
"poingnantly ironic" that fraternity would try to promote
among men attitudes and emotions usually associated with women. (37)
While this distinction is present in the English language, it has little
significance in Spanish, Italian, French, and Portuguese, where there is
no single word to translate the term "sorority." French uses
the expression "confrerie feminine," while Spanish uses
"hermandad de mujeres." The subtleties of the languages are
better expressed in German, in which fraternity refers to three distinct
things. First, the community of the brothers (Bruderschaft); second, the
bond that unites (Bruderlichkeit); and third, the virtue of fraternal
love (Bruderliebe). (38)
Other authors, though, openly use the term fraternity in English.
According to philosopher James Griffin, fraternity at times refers to
observing mutual respect, a type of concerned relationship that is at
the same time free, easy, and natural, and makes life better. (39)
Education expert Gerald Johnston also conceives of fraternity as a
sentiment of mutual responsibility or a moral obligation that falls upon
citizens, in line with the construction of community. (40) For
Griffin's part, fraternity corresponds to a prudent value: that is,
"a valuable type of personal relationship." (41) From John
Rawls's conception in his Theory of Justice, in relation to the
principles of liberty and equality, comes the idea that fraternity does
not define democratic rights but instead alludes to certain mental
attitudes and to behaviors such as social esteem and the absence of
servility and the feelings of friendship and social solidarity. These
mental states do not imply an obligation and instead incorporate
emotions and attitudes that can be applied only within the context of
face-to-face interactions and not on a macro societal scale, as
philosopher of education Kenneth Benne implies. (42) Even then, Rawls
points out, the principle of difference offers an interpretation of the
principle of fraternity, in the sense that it postulates the idea of not
wanting more personal gain except for in the case that others in worse
conditions benefit. (43)
Rawls's interpretation thus makes equivalence between the
concepts of civic friendship and fraternity impossible. While civic
friendship defines obligations, fraternity does not. Also, it suggests
that though civic friendship could be applied as a political category,
fraternity would fall short. Fraternity has tended to be interpreted as
solidarity, as proposed by Maria Nieves Tapia within the context of
Latin American educational experience on service learning. (44) But for
philosopher Antonio Baggio, solidarity, referring more to social rights,
has been practiced as such that it maintains the social vertical
relationship of weak to strong. (45) In fraternity, though, the
relationship is totally horizontal, among brothers. (46) Therefore,
fraternity should not be considered a synonym for solidarity.
The previous discussion, in our opinion, indicates that while these
concepts are approached from diverse perspectives and disciplines, they
nevertheless have important elements in common and offer a rich basis
for deepening the study of fraternity from the social sciences point of
view. While social cohesion, trust, and social capital are social
science concepts, they are simplifications of empirical phenomena that
have been built with the final purpose of measurement and comparison;
the notions of community, solidarity, civic friendship, and fraternity,
more common in the humanities, are richer and more comprehensive, while
more abstract in their reach. All of these notions--from the social
sciences and the humanities--make reference to some sort of virtuous
social bond, and this social bond is what defines their belonging to our
proposed semantic domain.
Fraternity's Semantic Domain in Catholic Social Teaching
CST did not refer to social cohesion explicitly until recently,
though the phenomenon to which this idea refers is discussed--that is,
that which keeps community united. Caritas in Veritate (hereafter CV)
incorporates the phenomena, as well as the nomenclature of trust, social
capital, and social cohesion, into CST as requirements for the proper
functioning of democracy and civil coexistence. (47) In any case, CV
does not touch upon the subtleties and grey-zones proper to these
concepts that are found in social science literature: for example, the
distinction between instrumental or strategic trust and normative trust,
or the idea that there exist forms of bonding social capital that are
noxious, in the degree to which they do not generate relationships
between groups in the same manner as does bridging social capital.
Mutual trust is discussed a few times in Pacem in Terris, but
linked to the relationship between states and as a mechanism to assure
peace. (48) Gaudium et Spes advances this idea, arguing that peace must
emerge from mutual trust between nations and not be imposed by fear or
weapon deterrence. (49) CV (35) claims that without trust the market
cannot fulfill the very economic function it is supposed to serve. It is
necessary to point out, though, that the type of trust lost that CV
laments is actually normative or moral trust. In contrast, rational or
instrumental trust--which can also be expressed as reciprocal
trust--remains implicit in the document and is that which, along with
contracts, assures the market's functioning, though not as an
economic institution that allows encounters among people and thus social
cohesion.
CST's invitation goes further. A society with good contracts
and institutions and even a culture of encounter would fall short of CST
aspirations unless these are founded on the recognition of God as the
source: "The God who is himself reliable gives us a city which is
reliable." Removing faith in God from cities (understood as
political communities) would weaken mutual trust and the bond that joins
humanity, as we would remain united only by interest or fear. (50)
The concept of community is not well defined in CST but is used
widely. CST acknowledges the sociological distinction between society
and community arguing that in the community affective bonds prevail,
while in society bonds are pragmatic. Community holds the highest
importance in CST, both as an organizational model of coexistence and as
an everyday way of living. In CST's dictionary, human existence
requires the emergence of communities and associations not only to
address material needs but also to exercise fraternity. (51)
Consequently, CST does not put society in opposition to community; in
effect, it calls on every society to become a community.
The pontifical documents usually refer to different spheres in
which community occurs. Gaudium et Spes, for example, refers to the
universal community (GS 4), the human community (GS 9 and 40), the
"civic community" (GS 53), or the "political
community" (GS 65). More narrowly, GS refers to the Church founded
by Christ as "a new brotherly community" (GS 32),
"spiritual community" (GS 40), "the community of the
faithful" (GS 58), or the "Christian community" (GS 62).
Ut Unum Sint speaks of the "Catholic community," and also of
"other Christian communities." (52) In turn, countries form a
community on their own (PT 46), or a political community that exercises
authority and government (PT 73). Chapter 4 of Gaudium et Spes is
dedicated to "the life of the political community," which
exists "for the sake of the common good" (GS 74)--an objective
that is also proclaimed in Caritas in Veritate (CV 6).
Given the universal nature of the Christian message, building an
international community represents an important objective, which
technological development and greater exchange are making increasingly
possible (Diz. 136-37). In Pacem in Terris, society forms a
"community of men" (PT 36). Gaudium et Spes mentions the idea
of forming the "community of mankind" (GS 23-32). Populorum
Progressio defines universal charity as "the effort to build a more
humane world community." (53) This "worldwide community of
nations" (PT 7 and 33) is also called the "international
community" (PP 6), or "the community of peoples and
nations" (CV 7).
To deepen the notion of worldwide community, Pacem in Terris refers
in chapter 4 to the relation between political communities and the world
community. As the political community at the national level must be
concerned with the national common good, so must the worldwide community
exercise government and authority on the grounds that the common good of
humankind makes it imperative (PT 7). If unity is the very essence of
the Christian community (UUS 9), mutatis mutandis the international
community should direct itself toward this end; however, this could
never be achieved without God (CV 34).
Solidarity has a place of preeminence in the magisterium. It is
named one of the four cardinal principles in CST, the other three being
the centrality of the human person, subsidiarity, and the common good.
(54) Solidarity is key in CST because it addresses the intrinsic social
nature of man and as a result it reflects the authentic nature of human
relations (Diz. 725). In Populorum Progressio, Blessed Paul VI argues
that each man belongs to humanity, and therefore has obligations to
everyone, even to those who are to come in the future (PP 17). In
CentesimusAnnus, Pope Saint John Paul II indicates that the principle of
solidarity was referred to by Leo XIII as "friendship," by
Pius XII as "social charity," and by Paul VI as
"civilization of love." (55) Solicitudo Rei Socialis
recognizes solidarity as a Christian virtue with many points of contact
to the notion of charity, which underlines total gratuity, forgiveness,
and reconciliation. (56)
For CST solidarity is the participation of men with their peers as
much in the production as in the enjoyment of common goods. In solidum
means to participate together or co-participate. Solidarity is the tie
that unites men and drives them to reciprocate concrete acts of
assistance. Moreover, in Pacem in Terris the result of solidarity
--lived at different levels, from the local community to the state to
the international order--is universal fraternity (Diz. 722-23). That is,
solidarity--as in the case of community--is a prerequisite for
fraternity to exist. In CST, solidarity is composed of two complementary
aspects: a social principle, that must order institutions, laws, and
market rules; and a moral virtue, in the sense that it is not a pure
emotion or sentiment, but instead a firm and persevering disposition--or
concern--to act for the good of others (Comp. 193).
To Paul VI universal solidarity is also a duty (PP 17). Caritas in
Veritate argues that solidarity is composed of a concrete concern and
sense of responsibility for others and that solidarity cannot be merely
delegated to the state, as without gratuitousness there can be no
justice (CV 38). Paul suggests that, more than material causes, the
problem of underdevelopment occurs because of a lack of understanding of
the responsibilities required for solidarity. Paul also mentions
nationalism and racism as obstacles to universal solidarity (PP 62). He
points out that the development of the individual cannot be separated
from the development of humanity, and that for this purpose, man and
nations should meet and work together in the mutual understanding of
friendship (PP 43). There is also a duty particularly relevant for
wealthier nations that arises from the human and supernatural
brotherhood of man that presents a three-fold obligation: mutual
solidarity, social justice, and universal charity (PP 44).
Uzochukwu Jude Njoku presents solidarity as a central concept in
John Paul's thought; however there appears to be no agreement on
the meaning of the concept in the latter's writings. Quoting
several of John Paul's encyclicals Njoku identifies its meaning as
alternatively interdependence, communion, charity, forgiveness, and
reconciliation, commitment to the good of the other, a preferential
option for the poor, participation, a spirit of cooperation, the absence
of oppression, defense of the poor and those in need, pursuit of the
common good, and advancement of true life-fulfillment to persons and
communities. (57) Also, in Laborem Exercens solidarity suggests the idea
of workers' social movement (LE 8). (58) While solidarity for John
Paul may be an ambivalent concept, there are nevertheless two traits
that are common to his thought: first, he undertakes theological
arguments centered on the idea of the interdependence of people, the
common fatherhood of God, and the brotherhood of all in Christ; and
second, in line with personalism, he develops the idea that solidarity
emphasizes individual responsibility and agency instead of arguing for
the determinism of social or collective structures. (59)
The doctrines regarding civic friendship and the unity of the human
family and dignity of all individuals as children of God can be found in
several encyclicals. For example, in Rerum Novarum, "if Christian
precepts prevail, the respective classes will not only be united in the
bonds of friendship, but also in those of brotherly love" (RN 25).
(60) Ut Unum Sint (42) underlines the need to recognize that brotherhood
is not the consequence of a large-hearted philanthropy or a vague family
spirit, but is rooted in the oneness of baptism, and that the unity of
all divided humanity is the will of God (UUS 6). In the Second Vatican
Council the Church offers its collaboration to humankind in fostering
fraternity as this corresponds to man's destiny (GS 3): to
constitute a single family and to treat each other in a spirit of
brotherhood (GS 24). More specifically with respect to human unity,
Lumen Fidei has recently placed love as key in keeping men and women
united (LF 51).
Although Pacem in Terris did not explicitly include the notion of
fraternity, it does often refer to it as "charity" (PT 34),
the "fellowship" (PT 121) of humankind and "brotherly
love" (PT 171), which is an individual attitude of care toward
others and primarily a matter of personal decision (PT 34) or "an
appeal to conscience" (PT 48). Some 50 years later, Caritas in
Veritate points out that "economic, social and political
development, if it is to be authentically human, needs to make room for
the principle of gratuitousness as an expression of fraternity" (CV
34).
To theologians Dianich and Torcivia, fraternity expresses an
ontological notion of bond that the concept of community is unable to
reach. (61) Baggio, inspired by Chiara Lubich's charismatic
experience, underlines this concept, referring to universal fraternity.
Lubich conceives of universal fraternity not as a mere feeling exhausted
in an affective dimension, but instead as the ontological bond of
humanity. (62) As such, the Trinity becomes a model for society. (63)
This trinitarian view calls for a transformation of social relations in
the widest sense. (64) In order to understand the deepest meaning of
fraternity, says Baggio, one needs to refer to the bond that unites the
divine persons as expressed in Jesus's prayer: "May they all
be one, just as, Father, you are in me and I am in you, so that they
also may be in us, so that the world may believe it was you who sent
me." (65)
According to Dianich and Torcivia it is in the first book of
Maccabees that the term fraternity first appears in the Bible to remind
readers of the fraternal bond that unites Jews and Spartans, which is
neither founded over the Alliance nor refers to the meaning of
community. (66) Later, in the New Testament the term appears a few times
in the first letter of Peter referring to Christians being together;
(67) to reciprocal fraternal love, and to the virtue of fraternity, (68)
which altogether applies to the community of Christians, but also
implies hospitality toward foreigners, and a moral duty of concern
toward non-believers. (69) The fathers of the Church (Tertullian,
Cyprian, and Augustine of Hippo) refer to fraternity as synonymous with
Church; the community of Christians at two levels: the local Church and
the universal Church. For Augustine, a relationship of fraternity
emerges among Christians through baptism. (70)
To Joseph Ratzinger, fraternity goes beyond the Christian
community. He recalls the doctrine of the two brothers, by which the
Church helps in the realization of the Kingdom of God in an
eschatological sense of unity and universal fraternity. But the Church
is just one of two brothers, and is called on by God not to condemn the
other brother (the nonbeliever), but to save him. (71)
Following Baggio, it is in light of the principle of fraternity
that the fundamental concepts and moral categories of CST can be
properly interpreted and lived; thus, these concepts and categories
perform the role of mediating the principle of fraternity. (72) Baggio
argues that Vatican II represents a turning point in defining a new
humanism as a founding category; that is, it renders fraternity a fully
meaningful social and political principle. Particularly through Gaudium
et Spes, we witness the birth of a new humanism, one in which man is
defined first of all by this responsibility to his brothers and to human
history (GS 55). (73)
In Erangelii Gaudium, Francis argues that social peace cannot be
understood as pacification or the mere absence of violence (EG 218), as
peace cannot be reduced to the absence of war (EG 219). Becoming a
people--that is, a community--is an ongoing process that requires a
culture of encounter (EG 220). Such a community is also conceived of as
universal (EG 181 and 188). It is essential to actively reach out toward
others in order to build such fraternity (EG 179). This seems to be the
key for distinguishing civic friendship from fraternity. Civic
friendship as mere democratic and peaceful coexistence is different from
the more active and demanding fraternity, which presuposes the former,
but requires a thick culture of encounter among citizens as a result of
an active and universal reciprocal concern.
Challenges to the Study and the Idea of Fraternity
According to Barreneche, fraternity is not a forgotten principle,
but a challenged principle. (74) Indeed, as evident from tracing
fraternity in social sciences and CST, there are numerous objections
that hinder fraternity from becoming a feasible social and political
category. We will comment on three deemed of particular importance: the
tension between homo economicus and homo reciprocans; fraternity as duty
or virtue; and local versus universal fraternity.
The first challenge is the widespread idea of the homo economicus
as the only valid behavioral assumption of decisional agents in
mainstream economics. Regarding the nature of human relationships, the
social sciences have been influenced by the rational choice paradigm
with its assumption of an individual that maximizes his or her own
utility. From an epistemological point of view, the effect of this
problem has been to consider altruistic behavior as instrumentally
rational. Also, one of the dilemmas of the social sciences is that the
type of face-to-face relations that a person establishes with his
fellows cannot be considered equivalent to the relations that an
individual has with people that he or she is not capable of
encountering. Traditionally, the response by mainstream economists to
the prevailing criticism has been to incorporate altruism into the
individual's utilitarian function, which does not alter the
fundamental anthropological view of an economic agent.
The generalization of this assumption not only had an important
effect on the social sciences, but more importantly it has fed a cynical
stance among many scholars when approaching the study of human
relationships. However, arguments against this assumption are not new
and have increased over time, even within economics. This reductionism
through an instrumentalist individualist rationality has been questioned
from a macroeconomic (75) as well as from a micro economic perspective.
(76) The interest in a more integral conception of the person is
observed in diverse instances, including recent initiatives at the
United Nations. (77)
CST suggests that the cause of today's difficulty in
understanding the concept of fraternity and accepting its implications
is the lack of a profound understanding of human nature, a nature that
shares a common Father and one made to love (Diz. 359-60)--a lack of
reciprocal charity. According to Lumen Fidei, one of the key
contributions of faith is to illuminate the true nature of social
relationships (54). CST underlines that the human being is made for gift
and reciprocity; as Lumen Fidei says, stressing the relational character
of human existence: "Persons always live in relationship. We come
from others, we belong to others, and our lives are enlarged by our
encounter with others" (LF 38).
This same nature is extrapolated to social and political spheres as
well as community, local, national, and global spheres. Charity,
conceived of as the basis of said community, illuminates in Christians
the most profound meaning of political life (Comp. 392). In Caritas in
Veritate, Benedict XVI indicates that charity is not just a principle
for micro-relations (friendship, family), but also for macro-relations
(social, economic, and political) (CV 2, EG 203 and 206), as man is made
only for gift (CV 34, EG 20 5). This encyclical is explicit in terms of
the need for an integral view of man and his development, inviting the
social sciences in this direction. (78)
PT equates what it proposes as harmonious relations between men to
those at the state level. In effect, given that men are equals in their
natural dignity, there is no difference from the point of view of
natural dignity between political communities (PT 89). States should be
governed by virtue of the truth and that presupposes the elimination of
racial discrimination and the recognition of the inviolable principle
that all states are by nature equal in dignity (PT 86).Thus, the
relationship between states must be harmonized with truth, justice,
liberty, and the disposition to cooperate (PT 80).
Just as the rational choice paradigm holds up the maximization of
one's utility as the motive of the individual and explains social
phenomena as an aggregation of self-interested individuals (homo
economicus), CST proposes that man by nature is made for gift and
reciprocity (homo reciprocans). (79) Thus the nature of society will be
the extrapolation from this reality that is not individual but
relational. Distinct from behavioral determinism--the paradox that does
not allow a choice that is not rational--the focus of CST, especially in
more recent documents, puts before men the choice of donating themselves
or denying themselves the true sense of their existence.
The second challenge regards the possibility of sublimating duties
associated with fraternity into an active concern (CST would say love),
that is, a moral virtue. The Universal Declaration of Human Rights
proclaimed by the General Assembly of the United Nations in December
1948 proposes that "all human beings ... should act towards one
another in a spirit of brotherhood." (80) This entails recognition
of liberty and equality and a consciousness of a moral duty toward
fraternity. This duty, though, has contested status in political theory.
(81)
From the perspective of republicanism, economist Jacques Attali
conceives of fraternity as duty. (82) However, in the liberal tradition
individuals are disengaged and morally free of duties toward their
compatriots, even though liberalism has refused to consider them
"moral strangers." (83) In this context, what could fraternity
mean more than a futile moralizing effort--as presented by political
scientist Wilson Carey McWilliams (84)--opposed to the real practice of
power and politics? Political theorist Christopher Wellmann considers it
acceptable to assume that we have special duties toward our friends--a
moral responsibility that is absent toward strangers. To Wellmann,
compatriots do not care about each other and do not feel identified or
connected with each other to the same degree as toward their friends.
(85)
According to political theorist and expert on global education,
Jason Scorza, within liberalism, citizenship is regarded as
instrumental. Therefore, citizens can demand respect and tolerance from
one another along with the provision of welfare according to human
dignity; however, they cannot demand to be loved or to be treated as
friends. However, Scorza identifies within certain lines of liberal
thought the possibility of civic friendship based on the concept of
democratic connectedness--which is a non-instrumental value that emerges
from the experience of belonging to the same community of equals, based
on openness and empathy, more than in purely contractual obligations.
(86) This line of argument is also proposed by Bruni for the functioning
of the market. (87) Whereas anonymity and impersonality characterizes
most marketplaces, fraternity in the form of reciprocity in
interpersonal relationships characterizes the functioning of the civil
economy. (88)
Considering CST in relation to political theory's dilemma
regarding whether fraternity alludes to duty or virtue, for Aquinas the
profound meaning of political life does not emerge from a list of rights
and duties, but should be based on civil friendship and fraternity
(Comp. 390). Pacem in Terris defines rights and duties as universal,
inviolable, and proper to human nature and by extension inalienable (PT
9). It also rescues the idea of reciprocity between rights and
responsibilities (PT 30). Moreover, in their relationship with other
people, the individual must act based on his own initiative, conviction,
and the sense of responsibility and not under pressure or external
coercion (PT 34). Human society demands men act guided by justice,
respect for others' rights, and the fulfillment of their
responsibilities; but it also demands that they act guided by a love
such that they feel the needs of others as their own, and they be driven
to share their material and spiritual goods (PT 35).
The criteria that orient moral action are moral justice and the
common good, but charity goes beyond justice in CST and completes it (CV
6). The earthly city is not only about rights and duties, but much more
importantly relationships of "gratuitousness, mercy and
communion" (CV 6); for social, economic, and political development
to be authentically human it must include gratuitousness as an
expression of fraternity (CV 34). Christians should go beyond living
fraternity as a duty or even as a moral virtue as they are called to
live a mystical or contemplative fraternity, which ultimately is finding
God in every human being (EG 92).
A third challenge pertains to the scope of fraternity. From a
normative perspective, extrapolating the idea of fraternity from a local
or national community to an international community is a valid goal, as
humanity is called to live in universal fraternity. However, there exist
various obstacles that curtail the scope of fraternity, in particular
those that restrict it to regional, ethnic, or class spheres.
CST is explicit in appealing to the universality of fraternity.
Pacem in Terris underlines the importance of collaboration between all,
an assertion that for the first time in the Church's encyclicals is
directed toward all men of good faith. Gaudium et Spes prescribes that
citizens are endowed with a loyal spirit of patriotism that should be
open to the whole human family (GS 75). In Populorum Progressio,
"Paul VI clearly understood that the social question had become
worldwide and he grasped the interconnection between the impetus towards
the unification of humanity and the Christian ideal of a single family
of peoples in solidarity and fraternity" (CV 13). Indeed, Paul
indicates that the "illness" of the world is the weakening of
brotherly ties among individuals and peoples (PP 66). Benedict XVI adds
that 40 years after PP, the principal novelty has been the sudden
appearance of planetary interdependence, called globalization (CV 33).
Beyond human and natural bonds--reads Sollicitudo Rei Socialis--faith
underlines a new model of unity of the human race that must be inspired
by the life of God as one God in three Persons; a model that may be
better expressed through the word "communion"; the brotherhood
of all in Christ (SRS 40).
CST proposes that it is everyone's duty--and especially that
of Christians--to promote universal fraternity (Diz. 360). In part this
duty arises from the confirmation that all men are brothers in the unity
of the human family (PT 132), but also due to the global reach of some
contemporary problems that require joint actions (PP 13). The modern era
has also multiplied contacts among people and nations, and therefore
"the human family is gradually recognizing that it comprises a
single world community and is making itself so" (GS 33). As such,
fraternity is universal because it involves us all, but also because it
covers all areas of social relations: interpersonal, local, national,
and global.
Universal fraternity requires at least the existence of a global
political entity that promotes global common goods. Some have argued
that the ongoing globalization process will not yield a world
government, if in fact one is even possible. Indeed, political theorist
Miguel Vatter points out that although Rawls in his Theory of Justice
equates his second principle of justice with fraternity, later Rawls
went on to throw out this possibility, realizing the obstacles that such
an international order would entail. (89) The question regarding the
feasibility of such a world government can be addressed from an
empirical perspective. In fact, the international community has
generated a set of global rules and institutions that could be the
initial stages of it. An alternative perspective claims a pragmatic and
incremental approach toward universal fraternity. (90)
CST also refers to global authority and relations among nations. To
promote the common good, some form of worldwide public authority is
needed (PT 137). To be legitimate, this universal public authority
should be accepted by all, and endowed as such with power to safeguard
security, justice, and respect for human rights (GS 81). A sufficiently
powerful authority at the international level would prevent the threat
of war (GS 79). Populorum Progressio advances the idea of establishing a
world fund by diverting military expenditures to relieve the needs of
the poor (PP 51). In PT the relationships between states should be
regulated by justice, which assumes the recognition of mutual rights and
responsibilities (PT 91). This also assumes that the purpose of a civil
authority is to protect the common good of the state, which cannot be
divorced from the common good of the entire human family (PT 98). These
relationships should also be regulated by the principle of liberty, and
no country has the right to oppress or interfere in the affairs of
another without justification. An important and final idea is that
Christians should cooperate decisively to establish an international
order built upon universal brotherhood and the respect of freedoms (GS
88).Through Catholic social thought, Christians should feel compelled to
act for the sake of their fellow human beings a concern identified by
several scholars as key to the development of global citizenship. (91)
Conclusion
In this preliminary study we have dipped into the analysis of how
the concept of fraternity has been revealed in social sciences and in
CST through kindred notions that appear in fact to describe the same
phenomenon. Contemporary political philosophy and other social sciences
have somehow forgotten or challenged the concept of fraternity and
prefer to frame the function that this notion performs in democracy as
civic friendship, social cohesion, and solidarity. Likewise, the concept
of fraternity is absent in economics, but similar ideas have been
considered in the extensive literature of trust and social capital. For
its part, CST has long used the notion of fraternity to mean many
things. At some point early in its history, fraternity was used
synonymously with the Church itself. In more recent documents, it has
been given more specific meaning. In particular since Pacem in Terris,
Gaudium et Spes, and especially Caritas in Veritate, it has been
proposed as a fundamental principle that can properly justify both
liberty and equality and provide a moral root to democracy.
For it to expand its capacity to transform society, CST requires
deep dialogue with the social sciences, as it can contribute in its
effort to forge a new culture. The building of a common language is an
essential part of such a dialogue. We aim to contribute to this effort
by bringing into focus possible points of common construction, where
social sciences can be enlightened by CST, and CST can find spaces for
entering the cultural and analytical discussions that result in
policymaking and institutional arrangements.
If in fact reason is capable of giving significance to equality and
the need for peaceful coexistence among nations, it nonetheless cannot
establish fraternity (CV 19). Modernity tried to build a universal
brotherhood based on equality (LF 54). The historical trajectory of the
triptych of the French Revolution generated an "unequal
liberalism" and an "unfree equality" as a result of the
lack of fraternity (Diz. 359). Fraternity according to CST is a
"link necessary for harmonizing, in social life, liberty and
equality" (Diz. 361). But in the end, for brotherhood to endure, it
needs as its ultimate foundation a reference to a common Father (LF 54).
Of course, the latter raises the question of how to transform fraternity
from a demanding theological and even teleological category to an
actionable social and political category that needs to be embedded in
political institutions and culture--a challenge that remains.
Notes
(1.) An earlier version of this essay was presented at the Catholic
Social Tradition conference "Peace Yesterday, Today, and Tomorrow:
Celebrating 50 Years Since Pacem In Terris" (University of Notre
Dame, South Bend, IN: March 21-23, 2013). We wish to express our
appreciation for comments from participants at this conference. We are
also grateful for comments from Antonio Baggio, Osvaldo Barreneche,
Luigino Bruni, Sebastian Cea, and Pasquale Ferrara.
(2.) Antonio M. Baggio, El Principio Olvidado: La Fraternidad. En
la Politica y el Derecho (Buenos Aires: Ciudad Nueva, 2006).
(3.) David Blacker, "Civic friendship and democratic
education," in Citizenship and Education in Liberal-Democratic
Societies: Teaching for Cosmopolitan Values and Collective Identities,
ed. Kevin McDonough and Walter Feinberg (New York: Oxford University
Press, 2003), 92.
(4.) Roberto Mancini, Esistenza e gratuita: Antropologia della
condivisione (Assisi: Cittadella, 2009), 162-92, quoted by Severino
Dianich and Carmelo Torcivia, Forme delpopolo di Dio:Tra comunita
efraternita (Milan: San Paolo, 2012), 163-64.
(5.) Alberto Lo Presti, "El poder politico en busca de nuevos
paradigmas" in El Principio Olvidado: La Fraternidad. En la
Politica y el Derecho, ed. Antonio M. Baggio (comp.) (Buenos Aires:
Ciudad Nueva, 2006), 210.
(6.) Rodrigo Mardones, "Hacia una precision conceptual de la
fraternidad politica," in Estudios Recientes sobre Fraternidad, ed.
Osvaldo Barreneche (Buenos Aires: Ciudad Nueva), 33-62.
(7.) Carlos Pena, "El concepto de cohesion social. Debates
teoricos y usos politicos," in Redes, Estado y Mercados: Soportes
de la Cohesion Social Latinoamericana, ed. Eugenio Tironi (Santiago:
Uqbar Editores, 2008), 42-43.
(8.) CEPAL, Cohesion Social: Inclusion y Sentido de Pertenencia en
America Latina (Santiago: Naciones Unidas, 2007), 25-29.
(9.) Gary S. Becker, Accounting for Tastes (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1996), 3.
(10.) Sebastian Cea and Alejandra Marinovic, "Capital social,
confianza y educacion," in Fraternidad y Educacion: Un Principio
para la Formacion Ciudadana y la Convivencia Democratica, ed. Rodrigo
Mardones (Buenos Aires: Ciudad Nueva, 2012), 205-42.
(11.) James S. Coleman, Foundations of Social Theory (Cambridge,
MA: Belknap Press, 1990), 304.
(12.) Michael Woolcock, "The place of social capital in
understanding social and economic outcomes," Canadian Journal of
Policy Research 2, no. 1 (2001).
(13.) Brian Keely, Human Capital: How What you Know Shapes your
Life, OECD Insights (Paris: OECD, 2007).
(14.) Francis Fukuyama, Trust: The Social Virtues and the Creation
of Prosperity (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1995).
(15.) Peter Nannestad, "What have we learned about generalized
trust, if anything?," Annual Review of Political Science 11 (2008):
414.
(16.) Margaret Levi and Laura Stoker, "Political trust and
trustworthiness," Annual Review of Political Science 3 (2000): 476.
(17.) Russell Hardin, "Trustworthiness," Ethics 107, no.
1 (1996): 32.
(18.) Eric M. Uslaner, The Moral Foundations of Trust (Cambridge,
UK: Cambridge University Press, 2002), 18.
(19.) William D. Leach and Paul A. Sabatier, "To trust an
adversary: Integrating rational and psychological models of
collaborative policymaking," American Political Science Review 99,
no. 4 (2005): 492-95.
(20.) Vittorio Pelligra, IParadossi della Fiducia: Scelte Racionali
e Dinamiche Interpersonale (Bologna: Il Mulino, 2007).
(21.) Karen Jones, "Trust as an affective attitude,"
Ethics 107, no. 1 (1996); Lawrence C. Becker, "Trust as
noncognitive security about motives," Ethics 107, no. 1 (1996).
(22.) Nannestad, "What have we learned about generalized
trust, if anything?," 414.
(23.) Marek Kohn, Trust: Self-Interest and the Common Good (New
York: Oxford University Press, 2008), 89-90.
(24.) Dianich and Torcivia, Forme del popolo di Dio, 113.
(25.) Luigino Bruni, "Communitas," in Dizionario di
economia civile, ed. Luigino Bruni and Stefano Zamagni (Roma: Citta
Nuova, 2009).
(26.) Sally J. Scholz, "Political solidarity, and violent
resistance,"Journal of Social Philosophy 38, no. 1 (2007): 38;
Sally J. Scholz, Political Solidarity (University Park: Pennsylvania
State University Press, 2008).
(27.) Rocio Caro Gandara and Antonio Marquez Prieto, "Il
diritto di comunione di Georges Gurvitch e l'economia di comunione.
Primi esplorazioni," in Per una Economia di Comunione: Un Approccio
Multidisciplinare, ed. Luigino Bruni and Luca Crivelli (Rome: Citta
Nuova Editrice, 2004).
(28.) Kurt Bayertz, "Four uses of solidarity," in
Solidarity, ed. Kurt Bayertz (Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer, 1999).
(29.) Scholz, "Political solidarity, and violent
resistance," 42.
(30.) Erhard Denninger, "'Security, diversity,
solidarity' instead of 'freedom, equality,
fraternity,'" Constellations 7, no. 4 (2000): 514.
(31.) Blacker, "Civic friendship and democratic
education," 249.
(32.) Sibyl A. Schwarzenbach, "On civic friendship,"
Ethics 107, no. 1 (1996): 107.
(33.) Oscar Godoy, "La amistad como principio politico,"
Estudios Publicos 49 (1993): 18.
(34.) Pablo Ramirez Rivas, "De la utopia a la eutopia. Apuntes
criticos para pensar y actuar la fraternidad hoy," in Estudios
Recientes sobre Fraternidad, ed. Osvaldo Barreneche (Buenos Aires:
Ciudad Nueva), 63-90.
(35.) Godoy, "La amistad como principio politico," 6.
(36.) Sibyl A. Schwarzenbach, On Civic Friendship: Including Women
in the State (New York: Columbia University Press, 2009).
(37.) Julie Nelson, "A response to Bruni and Sudgen,"
Economics & Philosophy 25, no. 2 (2009): 187-93.
(38.) Dianich and Torcivia, Forme del popolo di Dio, 140-41.
(39.) James Griffin, Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement, and
Moral Importance (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986).
(40.) Gerald L. Johnston, "Liberty, equality, fraternity:
democratic ideals and educational effects," British Journal of
Sociology of Education 12, no. 4 (1991): 492-93.
(41.) Griffin, Well-Being, 388.
(42.) Kenneth D. Benne, "The uses of fraternity,"
Daedalus 90, no. 2 (1961).
(43.) John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Belknap
Press, 1971), 105-06.
(44.) Maria Nieves Tapia, "Educacion y fraternidad: la
pedagogia del aprendizaje-servicio solidario," in Fraternidady
Educacion: Un Principio para la Formacion Ciudadanay la Convivencia
Democratica, ed. Rodrigo Mardones (Buenos Aires: Ciudad Nueva, 2012),
27-61.
(45.) Antonio M. Baggio, "Introduction al principio olvidado.
El redescubrimiento de la fraternidad en la epoca del Tercer
'89," in El Principio Olvidado: La Fraternidad. En la
Politicay el Derecho, ed. Antonio M. Baggio (comp.) (Buenos Aires:
Ciudad Nueva, 2006), 39.
(46.) See also: Enrique Dussel, "From fraternity to
solidarity: Toward a politics of liberation," Journal of Social
Philosophy 38, no. 1 (2007).
(47.) Caritas in Veritate, [section]32. Hereafter cited in text as
CV, with references to section numbers.
(48.) Pacem in Terris, [section]2. Hereafter cited in text as PT,
with references to section numbers.
(49.) Gaudium et Spes, [section]81. Hereafter cited in text as GS,
with references to section numbers.
(50.) Lumen Fidei, [section]50, 51 and 55. Hereafter cited in text
as LF, with references to section numbers.
(51.) Pontificio Consiglio della Giustiza e della Pace, Dizionario
di Dottrina Sociale della Chiesa (Rome: Libreria Ateneo Salesiano,
2005), 134-35. Hereafter cited in text as Diz., with references to
section numbers.
(52.) Ut Unum Sint, [section]4 and 11. Hereafter cited in text as
UUS, with references to section numbers.
(53.) Populorum Progressio, [section]44. Hereafter cited in text as
PP, with references to section numbers.
(54.) Stefano Zamagni, "Fraternity, gift, and reciprocity in
Caritas in Veritate," Revista Cultura Economica 27, no. 75/76
(2009): 22.
(55.) Pontificio Consejo "Justicia y Paz," Compendio de
la Doctrina Social de la Iglesia (Rome: Libreria Editrice Vaticana,
2005), no. 103. Hereafter cited in text as Comp., with references to
section numbers.
(56.) Sollicitudo Rei Socialis, [section]40. Hereafter cited in
text as SRS, with references to section numbers.
(57.) Uzochukwu Jude Njoku, "Discourse on the foundations of
solidarity in the social encyclicals of John Paul II," Ethical
Perspectives 14, no. 1 (2007): 81.
(58.) Laborem Exercens, [section] 8.
(59.) Njoku, "Discourse on the foundations of solidarity in
the social encyclicals of John Paul II," 92.
(60.) Rerum Novarum, [section]25.
(61.) Dianich and Torcivia, Forme del popolo di Dio, 140.
(62.) Antonio Maria Baggio, Laboro e dottrina sociale cristiana:
Dalle origini al Novecento (Rome: Citta Nuova Editrice, 2005), 49.
(63.) Enrique Cambon, Trinidad, 1modelo social? (Buenos Aires:
Ciudad Nueva, 2013).
(64.) Alejandra Marinovic, "Chiara Lubich and the
Transformation of Relationships: A Response to 'Chiara Lubich and
Gender Sociology,'" Claritas: Journal of Dialogue and Culture
4, no. 1 (2015): 36-38.
(65.) Jn 17:21.
(66.) 1 Mac 12:10, 17.
(67.) 1 Pet 2:17; 5:9.
(68.) 1 Pet 3:8; and 1 Pet 1:22.
(69.) Dianich and Torcivia, Forme del popolo di Dio, 141-43.
(70.) Ibid., 147-49.
(71.) Joseph Ratzinger, Christian Brotherhood (London: Sheed &
Ward, 1966). Originally published as Die christliche Bruderlichkeit
(Munchen: Kosel, 1960), quoted by ibid., 177.
(72.) Baggio, Laboro e dottrina sociale cristiana, 53.
(73.) Ibid., 46-47.
(74.) Osvaldo Barreneche, "De principio olvidado a principio
objetado. Discusiones sobre la fraternidad como categoria politica y
como perspectiva de estudios academicos," Revista do Curso de
Direito Amicus Curiae 9, no. 9 (2012).
(75.) See Stefano Zamagni, L'Economia del bene comune (Rome:
Citta Nuova Editrice, 2007); Leonardo Becchetti, Oltre L'homo
Oeconomicus: Felicita, Responsibility, Economia delle Relazioni (Rome:
Citta Nuova Editrice, 2009); Tibor Scitovsky, The Joyless Economy: An
Inquiry into Human Satisfaction and Consumer Dissatisfaction (New York:
Oxford University Press, 1976); Pier Luigi Sacco, Paolo Vanin, and
Stefano Zamagni, "Chapter 9: The economics of human
relationships," in Handbook of the Economics of Giving, Altruism
and Reciprocity, ed. Serge-Christophe Kolm and Jean Mercier Ythier
(Amsterdam: North-Holland/Elsevier, 2006).
(76.) There are multiple studies about the behavior of economic
agents that explore beyond the maximization of individual utility. See:
Samuel Bowles, Microeconomics: Behavior, Institutions, and Evolution
(New York: Russell Sage Foundation, 2004); Samuel Bowles and Herbert
Gintis, "Social preferences, homo economicus and zoon
politikon," in The Oxford Handbook of Contextual Political
Analysis, ed. Robert E. Goodin and Charles Tilly (New York: Oxford
University Press, 2006); A Cooperative Species: Human Reciprocity and
Its Evolution (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2011).
Literature reviews about we-rationality and team agency can be found in
Luigino Bruni and Stefano Zamagni, Dizionario di economia civile (Rome:
Citta Nuova Editrice, 2009).
(77.) See "Going beyond GDP, UNDP proposes human development
measure of sustainability," accessed April 8, 2012,
http://hdr.undp.org/en/mediacentre/press/. Previous references can be
found in UNDP (2011). Also see the first report on global human
happiness: John Helliwell, Richard Layard, and Jeffrey Sachs, World
Happiness Report, vol. 1 (New York: The Earth Institute, Columbia
University, 2012).
(78.) Cardinal Peter K. A. Turkson, "Caritas in Veritate, Good
News for Society," Logos: A Journal of Catholic Thought and Culture
15, no. 3 (2012).
(79.) Becchetti, Oltre L'homo Oeconomicus.
(80.) Spanish, French, and Italian translations use the term
"fraternity" instead of "brotherhood." Available at
http://www.ohchr.org/en/udhr/pages/searchbylang.aspx, accessed on May
17, 2010.
(81.) Michael T. Gibbons, "The idea of fraternity
revisited," Pespectives on Political Science 35, no. 4 (2006).
(82.) Jacques Attali, Fraternidades: Una Nueva Utopia (Barcelona:
Paidos, 2000), 140.
(83.) Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire (Cambridge, MA: Belknap
Press, 1986).
(84.) Wilson Carey McWilliams, The Idea of Fraternity in America
(Berkeley: University of California Press, 1973).
(85.) Christopher Heath Wellman, "Friends, compatriots, and
special political obligations," Political Theory 29, no. 2 (2001):
220-25.
(86.) Jason A. Scorza, "Liberal citizenship and civic
friendship," Political Theory 32, no. 1 (2004): 85-87.
(87.) Luigino Bruni, "Fraternita," in Dizionario di
Economia Civile, ed. Luigino Bruni and Stefano Zamagni (Rome: Citta
Nuova, 2009), 442. See also: Luigino Bruni and Robert Sudgen,
"Fraternity: Why the market need not be a morally free zone,"
Economics and Philosophy 24, no. 1 (2008); Zamagni, "Fraternity,
gift, and reciprocity in Caritas in Veritate."
(88.) Luigino Bruni and Stefano Zamagni, Civil Economy: Efficiency,
Equity, Public Happiness (Oxford, UK: Peter Lang, 2007).
(89.) Antonio M. Baggio et al., "Seminario 'Libertad,
igualdad, fraternidad,'" Revista de Ciencia Politica 27, no. 1
(2007): 148.
(90.) Pasquale Ferrara, Global Religion and International
Relations: A Diplomatic Perspective (New York: Palgrave Macmillan,
2014).
(91.) See for example: Martha Nussbaum, "Tagore, Dewey, and
the imminent demise of liberal education," in The Oxford Handbook
of Philosophy of Education, ed. Harvey Siegel (New York: Oxford
University Press, 2009).