Personality and opinion.
Simon, Yves R.
I WISH TO START BY REMARKING THAT there are things that are above
opinion. Let us be convinced of that before we begin to reflect upon
opinion itself. There are things that involve certainty, and qualified
certainty, and there are things that are not matters of opinion. We need
to keep those things in mind as we try to decide how to behave with
regard to problems of opinion and how our personality should be involved
in matters of opinion.
What are those things that are above opinion? Very briefly, we can
say that they are first the propositions of faith. The propositions of
faith are revealed by the Divine Word and, yes, they are indeed obscure.
Obscurity is essential to faith. But it is not just a matter of opinion.
We have here, in obscurity, in darkness, the best possible guarantee,
the guarantee of the Divine Witness.
There are also a number of natural certainties that we have no
right to treat as matters of opinion. In morality, for instance, there
are many things that are undecided, many problems that indeed change
from one social goal to another, sometimes from individual to
individual. But there are also a few ethical essences--I mean essences
of ethical character--and in particular a few ethical things that
involve intelligible necessity and that are either right or wrong. We
will be inspired if we give all possible attention to circumstances, if
we are well aware of the contingencies that may cause exceptional
situations. When all that is perfectly understood, however, there
remains the basic proposition that with regard to a number of ethical
subjects there are natural certainties that are far above matters of
opinion. Why do we need to speak of those things? For the obvious reason
that we are often tempted to treat things that are above opinion as if
they were matters of opinion.
And why? Because of the overwhelming fact that concerning these
things that are above opinion, whether we speak of faith propositions
revealed by the Divine Witness, or of natural certainties, in both
cases, minds are actually divided. This is our temptation and it is a
really treacherous one. Our temptation is to consider that wherever
there is division among minds, there is no real certainty. We like to
assume that where there is certainty, there is also unanimity, and a
consensus. Well, that is not true. When there is complete and qualified
certainty, there may still be a hundred accidental reasons why there
should be no factual consensus, no unanimity. Let me use an example.
Suppose, for instance, that we discuss whether it is lawful for parents
to cut the throat of their twelve-year-old child. I think we will all
agree that, all other things being equal, it is not lawful to cut the
throat of a twelve-year-old child. But what if he is only nine years
old? Is it the same? We would be unanimous in saying that it is wrong to
cut the throat of a nine-year-old child. What about cutting the throat
of a three-year-old child? We achieve about the same level of unanimity.
What if we consider the cases of a newly born or an unborn child? In
such cases our unanimity becomes less and less certain.
I remember a case that happened near my native province in
Normandy, France. A young woman with a famous name who belonged to an
upper-class family had surreptitiously become pregnant. She succeeded in
disguising and concealing her pregnancy until the baby was born, and
then she just killed him and buried him. The incident became publicly
known, there was a trial, and the jury was not moved. They gave her a
two-year jail sentence but then suspended it. So a jury made up of
ordinary people might have considered that so long as a child is
newborn, is not twelve years old, or nine, or three, but is newborn, if
his mother wants to get rid of him, perhaps that can be tolerated.
What if the baby is unborn? Now we know that many people think that
a mother has a sacred right to do whatever she pleases with what she
considers is still a part of her body, and so it is with regard to
something as serious as the murdering of children: we do not achieve
unanimity. Perhaps we would, here, in a group be unanimous. But if we
opened the door and invited a few people at random to join our
conference, I am sure that we would be at a variance in regard to such a
rather clear subject as the murdering of children.
Does this mean that the question is uncertain, and that it is only
a matter of opinion, that it may be the opinion of a person that a newly
born baby can be killed, just like that? Is this just a matter of
opinion? No, it is not a matter of opinion. There is a natural certainty
here and if we do not perceive it, if we do not share in this natural
certainty, it is because of some accident that may be due to our own
lack of intelligence or to our lack of morality, or to the influence of
an environment, or to the failure of whoever took care of our moral
upbringing to direct our mind properly in those matters.
There are a hundred reasons why things that are really matters of
natural certainty do not create a consensus, do not cause agreement.
Treating them as if they were matters of opinion is dangerous. To
suppose that there must be lack of certainty wherever there is factual
disagreement and a lack of consensus is a treacherous way to reason. It
would be good reasoning if disagreement could not be caused by accident,
but such is the fact. When there is natural certainty and perfect ground
for agreement, disagreement still can be caused by a hundred accidental
factors.
The first thing we have to think of when we speak of opinion is how
strongly we may be tempted to treat as matters of opinion things that
are far above opinion. Why are we so tempted? Because we all naively
reason that if there is certainty there "should" be a
consensus. Yes, there should be but the "should" is held in
check by a variety of accidents.
What is rather terrible is that we have to live with people who are
in disagreement with us even when disagreement in not permissible. It is
easy to live with people who disagree with me in matters in which
disagreement is permissible, but when I know that disagreement is not
permissible, that's a lot more difficult. And yet that has to be
done. It has to be done: we cannot change the great accidents of human
history that cause us to be short of agreement on a number of
matters--many of which are vital subjects--that are far above opinion.
So with regard to those matters we have to be very firm and not yield to
the temptation to consider them just as matters of opinion. At the same
time we have to get along and be friendly with people who will consider
murder legitimate in some cases when we are so convinced that murdering
is always by essence an irretrievably very great crime.
All of which is by way of introduction. We need, before we begin to
reflect upon opinion, to think of those matters that are above opinion
and that we are so badly tempted to mistake for matters of opinion just
because of the conspicuous fact that they have no factual consensus.
Now I wish to present a few remarks on personality and
teachability. All problems, theoretical and practical, pertaining to the
person are exceptionally difficult. What is a person? What constitutes
personality? In what sense can it be said that the development of
personality is an altogether desirable thing, the most desirable thing
in the world? All of these questions are extremely difficult.
We all have a sound feeling that to be a person is something noble
and worthy, and that we have no right to live as if we were not persons.
So we all have, in other words, a sentiment that the development of an
assertive personality is a desirable thing. However, we can see at once
that it is a process surrounded by the greatest dangers, that the
slightest deviation may cause a catastrophe and instead of bringing
about the sound growth of the person, it may produce a destructive state
of affairs-destructive for the person himself as much as for the
community. But this sense of danger is something we feel and a rational
validation of that feeling would necessitate a study of personality that
would take, at the least, a semester. So we have to proceed on the basis
of those feelings. After all, we are able to distinguish which of our
feelings are sound from those that are not.
I spoke of teachability, the ability to be taught, the willingness
to be taught. I have a great deal of experience with young people. The
youngest of my six children is a high school junior. Among young people
there is an understandable tendency to think that the proper assertion
of personality, toward parents and other authority figures, involves an
attitude of distrust, perhaps even an attitude of rebellion. As
Descartes remarked so many times, "We were children before we
became men." And, when we were little children we had to trust our
elders. We had to believe the stories they told us, some of which turned
out not to be completely reliable. But most of all, as we grew up, we
had the feeling that the time would come when we could not depend upon
witnesses or authorities or teachers. In short, we would have to look at
things for ourselves and develop our own opinions. I don't need to
elaborate on the psychological features that are extremely familiar to
all of you whether you are still of the age when things are felt very
strongly or in a more advanced age when it is possible to remember how
strongly those things were felt. At all events, one fine day we
discovered that we were no longer children and that we had to be persons
on our own ground and with our own merits.
Concerning personality and teachability, the essentials of the
issue can be summed up, I think, in very simple words. Universally, a
witness is a person who has a substitutional job, who fulfills a
substitutional function--substitutional, provisional, and transitional.
In the sciences, for instance, before we can see for ourselves we are
told by reputably reliable witnesses that things are such and such. Now,
if a teacher has any sense of professional conscientiousness, he is most
eager to have his students become independent of him as soon as
possible. Suppose the subject is the science of nature. A man who has
made similar experiments or computations is proposing his results for
the belief of beginners. Well, how might they react? They will have to
believe, otherwise they will never learn anything. But it should be
understood on both sides that the role of the witness and that of a
teacher is nothing else than a certified public witness, a witness
certified as dependable by society. Academic examinations, doctor's
degrees, academic appointments, all of that, signifies that society
considers that "So and So" is a reliable witness in such
matters as calculus, physics, philosophy, or other subjects.
To summarize: the desire of a good teacher is that his students no
longer have to depend upon him but can see for themselves. If the
subject is one of the sciences, then he or she will endeavor to lead the
students to attain scientific knowledge and perhaps even an accomplished
scientific knowledge. And if the subject is a matter of opinion, the
teacher will encourage the students to work out an opinion for
themselves. That is what any witness, and very particularly any teacher,
must desire.
I express these words without hesitation because I am so convinced
that they convey the truth. It is purely and simply desirable at all
stages in the work of upbringing and education that a young person
should, as soon as possible, see for himself, attain scientific
understanding and the understanding of demonstrations if the subject
matter admits of demonstration, or at least work out an opinion of his
own, if it is a matter of opinion. When will it become possible for the
young person to realize that he or she is able to do these things? Here
we have one of the most difficult problems in the upbringing of the
young, and that holds both for character training and the education of
the mind.
A witness is a person who has to disappear, to make himself
unnecessary as soon as possible. About that there is no doubt. On the
other hand, we know by sad and frequent experience that if the young
person gets rid of the witness prematurely, then, whether the matter is
one of demonstration or one of opinion, he is unlikely ever to think
soundly.
We are all very familiar with those youngsters who were given
autonomy prematurely. If they had been given autonomy "just as soon
as possible," it would have been perfect, but very soon is
sometimes sooner than "as soon as possible." All too often it
happens in the education of the mind as well as in the training of
character that for having failed to depend upon guidance until the mind
was mature enough to work out an opinion of its own, the conditions of a
sound opinion have been ruled out forever.
I remember a few years ago we had a visitor, a young man of about
thirty-two. I call him a young man because thirty-two is still young but
this one was particularly so. We had dinner with him. During our
conversation he uttered any number of stupidities although we knew him
as a gifted young man. As he left, my wife and I remembered that when he
was a youngster, having lost his father early on, he quickly told his
mother that she should better keep out of his way because he considered
himself mature enough to manage his own life. My wife said, "He is
still thirteen years old." According to vital statistics he was
thirty-two, but in terms of his maturity, he was only thirteen years
old. This was understandable since this youngster deprived himself so
soon of needed guidance, of needed witnesses, that his mind never grew,
and at thirty-two he was as immature as if he were thirteen. The
triviality of this example is, I suppose, excused by its familiarity and
its significance. The case is by no means exceptional.
Now I wish to present a few remarks on the subject of faithfulness
to one's opinions. It is a very common sentiment that there is
something noble about abiding by the opinion that one has been holding
for a long time, even for a lifetime. We all know people who derive
pride from the fact that they voted Republican forty years ago and never
quit voting Republican since then. Now I say Republican, I might just as
well say Democrat. I have no preference. Just consider this psychology.
The psychology of such a person is of stable, unchanging opinion, who is
proud of that fact, and derives a sense of nobility from his very steady
adherence to his opinions. It is something of interest that we do not
dislike people who are faithful to their opinions. We are less impressed
and appreciate people less who change their opinion casually, or who
catch an idea or a trend in the present atmosphere and let themselves be
guided by that trend, regardless of the opinion to which they have
generally adhered in the past. We all think that there is some sort of
nobility about faithfulness to one's opinions. That feeling or
sentiment cannot be completely deceptive; I do not think it is. In fact,
I think it conveys something. The bad thing about it is that it is
terribly confused. When a man derives a sense of nobility, not to say a
sense of pride, from the fact that he has been faithful to his opinions
for so long a time, to what exactly has he been faithful?
I remember when I was a very young teacher I shared the teaching of
philosophy in a very respectable university with a man who started
teaching in the year I was born. He was a man of fine character, and he
never missed a chance to recall that true honesty is something rare and
to specify what he meant by true honesty as faithfulness to one's
ideas. The fellow was very straight, very respectable, very noble. What
he placed behind the words "faithfulness to one's ideas"
was something beautiful and I knew it. Yet, I was struck by the
ambiguity of that expression. To what or to whom are we faithful when we
boast of being faithful to our opinions?
That faithfulness may be faithfulness to truth, steady adherence to
truth, steady determination to find the truth. That is one possibility,
and such was the case with my very respectable and respected older
colleague in France. Very often, when we brag of being faithful to our
opinions, we think of being faithful to our own self. There is a world
of difference between faithful commitment to truth and faithful
commitment to one's own self. All the difference between the best
thing in the world--dedication to truth--and the ugliest thing in the
world--the exaltation of the self. Those two are very easily confused.
As we are coming of age, it is really a thing from which we derive
some satisfaction, a thing that brings us some consolation: to consider
that this is how we have always thought, and we have not changed, and we
do not intend to change. But what does that mean? If it means that,
having been lucky enough to get an early start on the right track, on
the track that leads to truth, and having an honest conviction that this
was the right track, we stayed on that track and are determined to stay
on it regardless of the cost, then we have the best thing in the world:
dedication to truth. But how easy it is, under the appearance of
dedication to truth, to be dedicated only to one's self. This is
what faithfulness to one's opinion may convey. It does not do so
necessarily. The expression and the feeling that it stands for are
frightfully ambiguous. Let us be aware of this ambiguity.
I began this very informal little talk, by remarking that there are
things above opinion and that the first thing we must do when we think
of our duties in the shaping of our opinions is to have the deepest
regard for those things that are above opinion, such as revealed
propositions, those obscure propositions that are guaranteed by the best
of all witnesses, the Divine Witness, the Word of God, or natural
certainties, concerning for instance murder, assassination, and a few
other moral topics. We are tempted to treat those things as matters of
opinion because we are factually divided, but, again, that factual lack
of consensus does not mean a thing concerning the certainty of those
propositions that are above opinion.
We have been thinking in terms of truth and error, rather than in
terms of action. Let us now turn to the latter, and we shall see that
here opinion is in close connection with dispositions of greater power,
dispositions involving certitude and capable of attaining certainties.
Can we be so sure of what we ought to do in relation to our
problems of action? We live in a world of contingency where things can
be otherwise than they are so that when we have conscientiously
deliberated on a subject, carefully weighed the pros and cons, we still
know that, although it is reasonable to act this way, we do not know,
after all, what is going to happen.
Let me use a very simple example. Suppose that at the beginning of
the summer, a family deliberates about how to spend their summer
vacation. One possibility is to stay at home, another possibility is to
go to the mountains, a third possibility is to go to the seashore, a
fourth possibility is to go to a place describable neither as the
mountains nor as the seashore. If everybody in the family is in good
health and psychological condition, and if they have sufficient economic
means, they really have plenty of choices. The good of the family can be
attained by any of the four options, so any of those choices will be
reasonable enough. Suppose they decide to go to the mountains.
Everything has been carefully examined, and it is with a very good
conscience that the head of the family concludes, "Let's do
it. The trip will be a good thing for our family."
The trip may easily be done by train, bus, plane, or automobile.
The last is by far the most dangerous, but the other three also involve
some danger. The least dangerous of all is, perhaps, traveling by train.
But what if a train wreck occurs and the family's child is killed.
Then the proposition, "This trip will be a good thing for our
family," becomes a lie. It turns out to be false. Now this is a
very interesting point. The proposition, that "This trip will be a
good thing for our family" was a proposition in a matter of
opinion.
The felicities and the infelicities in the trip to the mountains or
to the seashore are things broadly subject to contingencies. A car may
be in very good mechanical condition and the driver may be an excellent
driver, yet a blowout even with a new tire can happen, and at the most
inopportune time: when the car is going at great speed, colliding
head-on with a bus resulting in the death of fourteen people. Such
things do happen and it is impossible to certify that the accident will
not happen.
Consider another example. I intend to take a train tomorrow to
return to my home, which happens to be a little far from my workplace. I
won't deliberate about it. I have a twenty-five ride coupon book,
so I don't even have to purchase a ticket. I shall just sit in the
train. But no matter how infrequently train wrecks occur, I know that I
may never see my home again. Once in a while, one person--or two, five,
twenty, forty, or sixty--are killed in a train wreck. I recently read
about such an awful accident--was it in Cuba, Puerto Rico, or Jamaica?
There were over forty people killed in a train wreck. I am also reminded
of the worst accident in contemporary history, which happened in a
tunnel in Italy some years ago. A train got stuck in a tunnel and the
fumes from the engine caused the death by asphyxiation of four hundred
people. We can't certify that it will not happen to our children
next time they take a train that happens to go through a tunnel. Those
things are contingent. Thanks to modern science and engineering, we have
impressive and ever-increasing regularity of favorable conditions, but
the possibility of a catastrophe always remains.
Now this is the question I wanted to ask. Suppose that under the
circumstances I have described, a father has decided that it will be a
good thing for his family to spend the vacation in the mountains and off
they go. Would you say that an unpredictable accident, the accident that
was not probable, the accident that is just an expression of the
wretchedness of our nature, of its constant exposure to destruction,
that this accident invalidated the wisdom of the decision? By no means!
Prior to the trip it was wise, certainly wise, to say, "Let's
go. That trip will be a good thing for our family." It was
certainly wise. It was a sound rule for the welfare of this little
community. The accident does not change anything. The decision does not
cease to have been what it has been: a wise decision, a sound direction
of action.
We now have all that we need to know about the subject when we are
deliberating about what we are going to do--most of the time at least. I
say most of the time, because there would be an exception for the case
when our deliberations lead us to conclude in favor of something that we
ought not to do, something that is obviously sinful, but let us leave
that out of the picture. When we deliberate about what we are going to
do, we are really concerned with two things.
First, we are concerned with the cognition of the future. So we
check the tire pressure before we leave for a long trip to determine
whether the tires are in dependable condition. We discover that there
are a few cuts in the tires, so we can predict with a disquieting ratio
of probability that a blowout may happen. We cannot certify that a
blowout will occur at an opportune moment. So before we leave we had
better replace the undependable tire with a new one. Here you see how we
are concerned with what is going to happen. We are concerned with
predicting the future as best we can. Of course, we can't achieve
more than an opinion. We can consider that it is perfectly reasonable to
go on a long trip with these four tires, all of which were recently
purchased and show no evidence of being ready to blow out.
What will probably happen? You see how I am concerned with the
future, not the accomplished fact, but the fact to be accomplished, or
the fact to come. I try to make my proposition adhere as closely as
possible to what is going to happen in the future, and I know very well
that this adherence can never be unqualified; it will always be the
loose adherence of opinion. So far as the cognition of things is
concerned, in a domain like that of human action, we will always have to
be satisfied with opinion and probability. We may succeed in achieving
very strong probability, very well-grounded opinion, and sometimes we
have to act on a very uncertain basis. Should we say that there is a
greater probability in favor of a felicitous outcome? We may have acted
under extremely risky circumstances. At all events, we need not develop
anxiety in an insane search for certainty in a domain which purely and
simply does not admit of certainty. That is the domain of opinion.
But there is something that does admit of certainty. It is the
direction of our action. And this is the second of our two concerns. The
proposition, "Let's go, a vacation in the mountains will be
good for our family," when taken as prophecy, as prediction of what
is going to happen, is uncertain. It may be very reasonably probable,
highly probable in fact, but it is purely and simply uncertain. We never
really know. But if you take the same proposition as the rule of action,
as a rule for the direction of our action, then it is quite a different
story. Here a gentleman who is in charge of the family community has
been deliberating conscientiously, examining the state of character of
each of the members of the family community, the state of their health,
the financial problems involved, the transportation problems involved,
and having done his best, has come to a conclusion that is precisely
what conscientiousness wants it to be. He has come to the conclusion
that is precisely what virtue wants it to be. It is a conclusion that is
precisely what good will wants it to be, what right intention wants it
to be, and here we have a relationship between good will and judgment
that is capable of certainty.
Although I do not know how my tires are going to hold up, although
I really do not know if the train that I am absolutely determined to
take tomorrow is going to take me home or take me to the hospital, dead
or alive, the proposition--"That is what I shall do; I shall take
that train tomorrow as usual, and I won't even be concerned about
possible danger"--that proposition is possessed of certainty. Not
at all as an expression of a coming event, but as an expression of
harmony between good will and judgment. It is the very judgment that
good will demands. It is a judgment in harmony with good will. A man of
good will cannot do any better under the circumstances.
This is the rule: The direction is in harmony with good will, with
faithfulness, with justice, with charity, with dedication; it is in
harmony with all that makes up a good will. This harmony is something
certain. Here we have, beyond the weak power of opinion, a certainty of
purely practical character that in a purely practical order, in the
order of human action--by no means does it have anything to do with
science and the contemplation of truth--in this order of human action,
we have here a judgment that attains unqualified certainty.
What I wanted to say is that opinion is placed between two systems
that are better than opinion itself. If we consider opinion as relative
to the knowledge of truth, then above it there is faith in revealed
dogmas and there is sound adherence to natural certainties. If we
consider opinion as related to the order of action, then there is
something beyond opinion which is the certainty of direction in our
action. The certain agreement of our rule of action with the demands of
good will, with the demands of a right, righteous, clean, pure,
straightforward intention is the deepest meaning of opinion. Of itself,
it is a weak thing, since by definition it cannot attain certainty, but
its glory is to be, to a considerable extent, preparatory and
introductory to things that are above the probabilities of opinion,
either in the order of truth or in the order of action.
In the answer to the problem of opinion and personality, the deep
answer to the problem of what we should do in order to be true persons,
genuine persons in the shaping of our opinions, is most likely to be
found if we consider those two poles of certainty between which opinion
takes place and moves: the theoretical certainty, and the certainty
regarding truth which is found in revealed faith and also in a great
many propositions of natural character; and at the other extremity, in
the order of action, the certainty of harmony between the wise decision
and the demands of a really honest will.
This article was transcribed from a tape recording of a lecture by
Yves R. Simon and edited by Raymond Dennehy, University of San
Francisco, and Anthony O. Simon, director of the Yves R. Simon
Institute. It was originally delivered at the department of philosophy
at St. Joseph's University, East Chicago, Illinois, in 1957.