Smith and Tocqueville on the commercial ethos.
Smith, Brian A.
Students of political economy's intellectual history
frequently focus on the laws and institutions that serve as the
necessary supports for commercial society. Without denying the insights
this approach conveys, such an emphasis generally overlooks some crucial
moral and cultural elements that help maintain support for commerce in
democratic society. A close reading of Adam Smith and Alexis de
Tocqueville's writings on the subject suggests another way of
thinking about this matter, one that places neither laws nor
institutions in the dominant position. (1) Instead, these authors assume
that a people's social habits and mores bear incredible importance
for the character of their commerce and that this is the deeper ground
on which we might sustain economic life. (2) This article explores one
aspect of what Smith and Tocqueville saw as the necessary prerequisite
for any society that would embrace a commercial ethos.
Both authors suggest that robust commercial life requires that the
population willingly accept risk and bear the consequences--for good or
ill--of their financial choices. This attitude must necessarily prevail
among all those involved in the economic sphere because all participants
in commerce face constant uncertainty. Be they factory workers,
oceangoing traders, or the owners of businesses, their livelihood
depends on a number of factors entirely out of their control. At a
minimum, workers' fortunes rise and fall on the continued success
of the business they operate within, and their fates rest on the demand
for the specific product or service they help produce. (3) Merchants and
traders face a different, but no less imposing set of uncertain
conditions. Tocqueville describes the extraordinary fortitude of the
American sailor who braves incredible dangers and contrasts them to more
timid Europeans:
The European navigator is prudent about venturing out to sea; he
only does so when the weather is suitable; if any unexpected
accident happens, he returns to port ... The American, neglecting
such precautions, braves these dangers; he sets sail while the
storm is still rumbling; by night as well as by day he spreads full
sails to the wind; he repairs storm damage as he goes. (4)
The enterprising American merchant-sailor risks enormous physical
hardship to accomplish his goal of selling goods more cheaply and more
often. Moreover, he and most other participants in commercial life must
live with uncertainty about the future--and this takes a psychological
toll. (5)
At first glance, we might understand this entrepreneurial spirit as
a form of individualism or independence. Yet, somewhat paradoxically,
Smith and Tocqueville tie this willingness to embrace the market's
fortunes with our choice to actively incur obligations and accept
dependence on other people in community. In turn, these relationships
better our minds and morals through habits of conversation and
association. (6) Without these ties, people lose the solid ground on
which to rest while the rest of the world constantly changes.
Exceptionally solitary or asocial individuals aside, both authors insist
that the typically risk-accepting and self-interested behavior of the
market can only persist over the long term among people who maintain
salutary bonds of emotional and physical interdependence.
Our culture's tendencies toward liberal individualism lead
many of us to assume that any degree of dependence on others makes us
akin to slaves. For Smith and Tocqueville, this represents a grave
error. They suggest that the ideal of totally autonomous individuality
denies many natural human tendencies. We realize our full humanity only
in community. (7) Moreover, Smith and Tocqueville show that the sort of
isolation radical individualism fosters may lead us directly into
another, more dangerous bondage. I argue that both authors show us that
the mirror image of healthy interdependence fostered by family, public
life, and voluntary association can be found in tutelary dependence on
impersonal authorities and institutions. Whenever we shed the healthy
restraints of family and community, this form of bondage poses a grave
threat to the commercial ethos by undermining these ties.
This argument bears particular importance because of Smith and
Tocqueville's common assumption that the market is an associational
principle whose proper functioning rests on psychological and moral
foundations that it alone cannot renew. Worse still, they observe at
many points in their writings that the day-to-day mobility and
instability that the market fosters may well erode these foundations.
(8)
Both authors endorse a moral psychology based on sympathy. Put
simply, our ability to extend moral recognition to others rests on our
imaginative capacity to see their plight impartially, as any human being
might when they imagine themselves in the actor's position. Neither
cares much for abstract moralizing because of their conviction that
without a culture supporting moral rules and concrete habits reinforcing
moral behavior, people all too easily fall into self-interested
solipsism. (9) A few examples from both authors will illustrate this
danger.
For Smith, the division of labor in a relatively free commercial
environment brings about rapid improvement in the material quality of
life for all men, freeing them from old ties to the land, (10) but this
set of changes in economic life creates a severe dilemma in that the
simple and repetitive operations that occupy the worker's day leave
him with "no occasion to exert his understanding, or to exercise
his invention," generally becoming "as stupid and ignorant as
it is possible for a human creature to become." If the everyday
bonds of society--that is, our simple conversations and social
habits--remain the source of the commercial man's ability to bear
the risks of the market, then Smith's belief that an extreme
division of labor in industry "renders him ... incapable of
relishing or bearing a part in any rational conversation" bears
real importance. (11) Shorn from real conversation, neither the ordinary
laborer nor the single-minded trader retains much space to recognize one
another's moral importance; for both authors, this solitude abets
self-interested solipsism. (12)
Seeing the progress of industry decades later, Tocqueville remarks
that the enormous increases in opulence and comfort that commerce
fosters "have not been obtained without a necessary cost" in
the way the "industrial class, which gives so much impetus to the
well-being of others, is thus much more exposed to sudden and
irremediable evils." (13) The social movement commercial society
fosters leads to a situation where "nobody's position is quite
stable" and "a man's interests are limited to those near
himself." (14) When tied with the native Cartesianism of democratic
and commercial culture, where "each man is narrowly shut up in
himself, and from that basis makes the pretension to judge the
world," these forces present severe dangers to society. Because of
them, men might treat those outside their families with a sort of benign
neglect rather than an engaged sympathy--a tendency that I will argue
leads directly into the danger of tutelary dependence. (15)
If the means businessmen use to foster commerce undermine the very
ethos through which individuals find the strength to bear the
market's instability, then a decent political economy must foster
the social habits and cultural resources that support enterprise. (16)
Stripped to their purest forms, the market forces that both Smith and
Tocqueville describe encourage a type of unmoored independence that
quickly undermines the energy that drives the system along. When
unchecked, this situation leads commercial people into a sleepy
dependence on authorities for their security. (17) The seemingly
paradoxical alternative both authors present us is not that we should
seek more freedom but, rather, that we place increased attention on the
ways healthy interdependence actually works to preserve our liberty and
prosperity. (18)
I wish to focus on three sets of associations and the manner in
which they help maintain the commercial ethos. Each of them bears
particular importance because of the way they mitigate the danger of
solipsism and help guard individual commercial men against the
psychological burden of market-related risk. These include the personal
relationships of the family, obligations as public members of a local
community, and the value of wider voluntary associations, particularly
churches.
In addition to being an important reason for entrepreneurs to work
diligently to improve, family forms the bedrock of our ability to embark
on the sort of behavior the market demands of those who would succeed.
First and perhaps most importantly, families provide constant
reinforcement of whatever habits and mores prevail in their corner of
society. While this may have both good and ill effects, the wider
society has no hope of maintaining decent order without a virtuous
foundation in the home. (19) Schools and other associations can help
generate the individual security that participants in the market need,
but they cannot alone suffice. Moreover, members of well-ordered
families help one another from day to day. Even in a society that
emphasizes resolute autonomy, family represents an instance where mutual
aid and interdependence remains normal and expected. Smith and
Tocqueville suggest a number of consequences that follow from this most
foundational of associations.
For Smith, perhaps the most essential benefit of family comes by
way of its stability. We require sympathy above all other psychological
needs. However, our ability to extend this response to those who deserve
it comes only from long habit. (20) We need the space carved out by the
home because it remains the central place in our lives within which we
might be cared for and grow to believe that we deserve this affection.
(21) Obviously, market relationships pose a stark contrast to familial
ones. Early in Wealth of Nations, Smith observes that commercial man
"stands at all times in need of the cooperation and assistance of
great multitudes, while his whole life is scarce sufficient to gain the
friendship of a few persons.... But man has almost constant occasion for
the help of his brethren, and it is in vain for him to expect it from
their benevolence alone." (22) While in the market people interest
one another by paying for their time, the home normally remains quite
different. The family does not so much directly prepare us for market
behavior as it does carve out an emotional space where we can find
respite from the competitive world.
For this reason, Smith emphasizes the indecency of applying the
terms of market relations within the family and the insufficiency of
mere justice within its bounds. Rooting his moral theory in sympathy
rather than justice, Smith understands the latter in terms of restraint,
as an ideal that "is upon most occasions, but a negative virtue,
and only hinders us from hurting our neighbor." As a consequence,
people may "often fulfill all the rules of justice by sitting still
and doing nothing." By contrast, he identifies the family as a
space of active benevolence where merely obeying the minimum standards
of the law usually commands outright blame. By denying aid to our
family, we might not violate any laws but in so doing our reputation and
ability to cultivate sympathy in others will likely diminish. (23)
Both authors suggest that the home helps maintain the commercial
ethic in two major ways: as a moral restraint and a place of rest. The
contrast between domestic benevolence and self-interest in the wider
world clarifies our moral obligations. Our sympathies lie close to home
and magnify our need to work for the benefit of specific people rather
than humanity as a whole. Even though the commercial man's family
members enjoy "his warmest affections" and remain the persons
"upon whose happiness or misery his conduct must have the greatest
influence," Smith does not necessarily see this limitation on
sympathy toward the outside world as an incentive to act wrongly toward
others. Our social nature makes it difficult to hide who we are and what
we do with our lives. He argues that we wish to be the proper object of
love and sympathy. A good family actually restrains excesses of
self-interest precisely because it reinforces moral behavior through
common action and conversation. (24)
While Smith primarily emphasizes the family in general as a moral
restraint, both he and Tocqueville note the way family provides a
protected space from the worries of the market. He observes that
American fortunes are highly unstable, and implies that it is the
prudential actions of American wives that keep their families from being
likewise unstable. (25) While Smith does not explicitly discuss the
importance of equality, both he and Tocqueville highlight aspects of the
division of household labor between husbands and wives. Smith claims
that men and women naturally tend to act on their sympathies rather
differently--women's "humane" actions emphasize caring
and emotional support for those close to home and men might be more
disposed to action in the outside world. (26) These forms of benevolence
most common to the family renew the personal energy and will necessary
for the commercial ethic to flourish.
Tocqueville likewise suggests that amidst the upheavals of life in
commercial society, women renew the energy of the family, providing a
strength and respite for their loved ones that allows them all to face
the instability of the market. (27) Today many of us would vehemently
disagree with the details of their argument, but this need not lead us
to deny that commercial peoples need a family unit that provides respite
to allow us to work outside the home. (28) Tocqueville and Smith suggest
that markets tend to narrow our sense of interests to ourselves and a
few others but that strong family life naturally moderates excesses of
self interest. At the same time, both observe the myriad ways our
dependence on a spouse and obligations to children renew our capacity to
accept risk in the world. The family prepares us for our encounter with
the world--and as we shall see below, our public duties and chosen
affiliations also reinforce our ability to develop virtues suitable for
commercial life.
For both authors, obligations in public life--particularly the
involuntary ones--also serve as a kind of salutary interdependence. (29)
In commercial societies, this bears particular importance. Commerce
thrives on social mobility but it in turn abets rootlessness. Smith
observes that city life, or really life in any new locale filled with
strangers, creates a situation where the average person sinks into a
sort of "obscurity and darkness." (30) Even more than Smith,
Tocqueville emphasizes the ways in which modern people would prefer to
remain at home, tending their own business rather than the commonweal.
Without anyone to care for them or groups with which to associate, they
fall into the danger of isolated solipsism. Public duties present one
way to draw men out of themselves and connect them to the larger
community, even if they are relative newcomers. Such roles engage us in
the lives of others, an association we desperately need in order to feel
rooted in a community we would rather leave to its own devices. Both
Smith and Tocqueville suggest that the wide variety of responsibilities
that inhere in citizenship help us stay morally and psychologically
capable of dealing with the risks of the market. Both suggest that
commercial peoples need grounding in a community because this
relationship to the wider world encourages at least two valuable
character traits.
First, activity in public life fosters wider sympathy for many
people with whom we would not otherwise commonly associate. Without some
duty or incentive drawing them out of their private affairs, rootless
commercial men will normally leave their fellow citizens alone, neither
helping nor harming them. (31) However, participation in juries and the
practical administration of the community places us in contact with
those more emotionally distant from us and may foster the sorts of
sympathy that allow for benevolence among strangers: "By making men
pay attention to things other than their own affairs, they combat that
individual selfishness which is like rust in society." (32) In
curbing egotism, this practice assists the moral life of the family, and
for those already actively engaged in public life, reinforces our sense
of belonging in a community.
Second, participation in public affairs helps commercial people
maintain confidence in their judgment and helps restore certain virtues
often lost in the humdrum of work. For both authors, an advanced
division of labor begets a narrowing of the mind and a diminished
capacity for action outside of established routines: "When a
workman has spent a considerable portion of his life in this fashion,
his thought is permanently fixed on the object of his daily toil; his
body has contracted certain fixed habits which it can never shake
off." The central problem here is that "the understandings of
the greater part of men are necessarily formed by their ordinary
employments." (33) Both authors suggest that public activity is a
means for shaking commercial men out of this torpor.
Tocqueville emphasizes the way juries "teach each individual
not to shirk responsibility for his own acts, and without that manly
characteristic no political virtue is possible"; even if they do
not confer any specialized knowledge of the law, they do however, convey
some of the "habits of the judicial mind into every citizen."
(34) Although time-consuming, participation expands the
individual's confidence in their judgment and reinforces their
ability to come together to accomplish their ends. Because of this,
Tocqueville suggests that "one may think of political associations
as great free schools to which all citizens come to be taught the
general theory of association," without which liberty and commerce
cannot long survive. (35) Similarly, Smith commends militia service
because of the manner in which it opens the mind to new and different
forms of activity, forcing the citizen-soldier to apply their character
and virtue to the perfection of another art and to contemplate the needs
of the whole community. (36) In both cases, this counteracts the
winnowing effects of the advanced division of labor by opening
additional paths of mental activity. This might give a larger percentage
of the population a taste of what members of more elevated professions
that encompass a wider range of activity (such as scholars and teachers)
enjoy: practices that "necessarily exercise their minds in endless
comparisons and combinations, and renders their understandings ... both
acute and comprehensive." (37) This mental stimulation and
practiced habit of action outside of the norm stands as a reminder of
their ability to self-organize and remedies difficulties without help
from government--a habit vital to fostering entrepreneurship. (38)
The third sort of salutary interdependence men incur that helps
keep them disposed toward the market is that of the wider set of
voluntary associations. Associations particularly address the dangers of
exhaustion, isolation, and solipsism that threaten the commercial ethos.
Tocqueville tells us that without habits of coming together, commercial
men easily grow weary of engaging in society and thus lose sight of the
practices that foster entrepreneurship. The consequent isolation unmoors
him from the moral and psychological supports community provides. As I
noted earlier, solipsism opens the door to purely self-interested
behavior, which in turn further exacerbates the other dangers. Voluntary
association addresses these threats in several concrete ways, as well as
some intangible but even more crucial ones.
Where public duties thrust members of a polity into contact with a
wide variety of strangers who pursue different private ends, voluntary
associations bring citizens who share common goals together to achieve
them. Concretely, associations assist their members with various kinds
of education and welfare, but they also further reinforce the sense of
interdependent individualism that commerce requires to sustain itself.
(39) More specifically, Tocqueville remarks on the many ways that
voluntary associations reinforce the sort of spirit that commercial men
need. In the market, people need habits of self-reliance--or at least
reliance on particular people who share common goals and interests. A
small charitable group can do things others cannot: "It devotes
itself to the greatest miseries, it seeks out misfortune without
publicity, and it silently and spontaneously repairs the damage."
(40) These groups can mitigate some of the risks inherent in the market;
they reinforce commercial society's healthy interdependence while
reducing the need to look to the state for additional support. Among the
groups that do this, both Tocqueville and Smith point toward religious
institutions as the most important.
Smith and Tocqueville place enormous weight on the nature of the
church as simultaneously a moral tutor and a powerful support allowing
commercial peoples to accept risk. Without certainty in their beliefs,
"men are soon frightened by the limitless independence with which
they are faced." Constantly pressured by the marketplace, they
"are worried and worn out by the constant restlessness of
everything."41 We cannot escape religious belief: "It is by a
sort of intellectual aberration, and in a way, by doing moral violence
to their own nature, that men detach themselves from religious beliefs;
an invincible inclination draws them back. Incredulity is an accident;
faith is the only permanent state of mankind." (42) Moreover,
religious belief cannot simply be limited to the status of a moral
teaching, for the point is not so "much to render the people good
citizens in this world, as to prepare them for another and better world
in a life to come." (43) By emphasizing the general character of
faith as a teaching about reality and our utterly dependent place within
the cosmos, both authors recognize the importance of religion for
creating characters able to bear hardship in the world.
Thus, for both Smith and Tocqueville, the family, public service,
and voluntary associations help foster salutary interdependence and
carve out moral and psychological space for individuals to maintain a
robust economic life driven by innovation and entrepreneurship.
Together, they allow us to develop habits of action necessary for
commerce. However, when these healthy forms of interdependence fail,
both authors note that the spirit of commerce falters--but it does so
for reasons students of the market seldom fully recognize. (44) Both
Smith and Tocqueville present an intriguing analysis of how this comes
about.
The failure to maintain deep associational bonds and faith opens a
space where vulnerable, isolated individuals lose the habit of coming
together for action. Tocqueville warns that if commercial peoples
"did not learn some habits of acting together in the affairs to
daily life, civilization itself would be in peril." (45)
Ultimately, such peoples find themselves entirely unable to accept
political, emotional, or economic risk. (46) Yet, this does not by any
means imply that they successfully avoid chance and fortune. Instead,
they find themselves in a new position of even deeper dependence than
they existed in before, and what is worse, with no way out. Having no
group outside their immediate family they can turn to for help, weakened
commercial men increasingly turn to powerful individuals and the state
to fill this void. (47)
In light of the rapid changes and complexity of commercial society,
neither doubts the need for the state to stand above the market; they
both inexorably link economics to politics and the laws. After
establishing national defense and the rule of law, Smith argues that
government's final duty rests in establishing important public
institutions and projects that no individual or group could afford or
have any incentive to build. (48) Tocqueville claims that as commerce
proceeds, two things change: "On the one hand, among these nations,
the most insecure class continuously grows. On the other hand, needs
infinitely expand and diversify, and the chance of being exposed to some
of them becomes more frequent each day." (49) As a matter of
defending the commercial republic from political instability, he
endorses some provision for aiding those harmed most by the business
cycles a free market makes inevitable. (50) Both share a profound
concern for the means the state and its agents use in interacting with
citizens' economic and social lives--and particularly, the danger
that comes from the moral and psychological dispositions the
state's actions foster.
While Smith did not foresee the growth of a welfare state, he
nonetheless feared the increasing tendency of ideologues to impose grand
theoretical systems on politics. Usually driven by an exaggerated,
general sentiment of benevolence, this character, a
man of system ... is apt to be very wise in his own conceit; and is
often so enamoured with the supposed beauty of his own ideal plan
of government, that he cannot suffer the smallest deviation from
any part of it.... He seems to imagine that he can arrange the
different members of a great society with as much ease as the hand
arranges the different pieces upon a chess-board. (51)
Such ideologues despise the individual motives of private citizens,
and, as such, they represent an enormous threat to any private
enterprise. In subjecting the laws to their frequently changed plans,
they remove the stability and order that commerce so desperately
requires. They would in time subsume all private enterprise to the needs
of the system, removing "obstructions" from the supposed good
of society. (52) In so doing, they could not help but undermine the
healthy moral links between benevolent individuals to replace them with
the ideal system. However, from his vantage point before the growth of
industry and attendant laws to regulate aid to the poor, Smith could
only see part of the danger.
In the wake of those historic changes, Tocqueville tells us that
the state easily crowds out individual and associational action, and
that a failure to see the consequences of poorly structured aid can
completely undermine the commercial ethic on each of the levels that I
outlined above. First and foremost, he observes that poorly considered
benevolence can shatter the family and implies that other perilous
unintended consequences can flow from the best of intentions. In
England, unwed mothers faced a perverse set of incentives regardless of
their partner's circumstances: "The relief granted to them ...
exceeds the expenses caused by the infant. So they thrive from their
very vices," and continue to bring children into an environment
that mandates dependence on the state. (53) Tocqueville and Smith argue
that in a well-ordered society, legislators must maximize the ways
individual self-interest aligns with the common good. Ill-considered
benevolence that harms the family--in this case by encouraging children
to be born out of wedlock--erases the principal means by which society
passes on moral restraint; at the same time, it models a malign
dependency on the state for the generations to come.
Tocqueville identifies another tendency that he thinks tends to
undermine political participation in favor of increasing uniformity of
public opinion alongside the growth of central power. It is true,
Tocqueville writes, that the
constitution and needs of democratic nations make it inevitable
that their sovereign power should be more uniform, centralized,
extensive, and efficient than those of any other people. In the
nature of things society there is more active and stronger, and the
individual more subordinate and weaker: society does more and the
individual less. That is inevitable. (54)
Commercial people will quickly admit the necessity for some
significant types of government action in their everyday lives. A few of
these that Smith and Tocqueville observe include uniform codes of law,
the administration of justice, and the maintenance of roads. While Smith
and Tocqueville laud these aspects of governmental centralization, they
both recognized the likelihood that such reforms would be accompanied
with attempts to centralize the administration of their people's
lives in detail. (55) This naturally strips power from localities and,
with the loss of power, any interest people might have to participate in
local politics. Moreover, administrative centralization cuts off another
path to enlarging the sympathies and quality of the commercial
man's heart and in turn further undermines the commercial ethos.
Tocqueville observed that his contemporaries thought that as
individuals grew proportionally weaker, the state should step in to
replace their activity. (56) If the incentives for voluntary
associations diminished and the habits of participating in them faded,
another great source of commercial vitality might wither and die. (57)
His terror rests in the idea that isolated, solipsistic individuals who
constantly rebel against the idea they should depend on others might
begin to look to the state alone for guidance and for security of their
livelihood. He drew the tendency quite starkly:
The taste for well-being is always increasing and the government
gets more and more complete control of the sources of that
well-being. Thus men are following two different roads to
servitude. The taste for well-being diverts them from taking part
in the government, and that love of well-being puts them in even
closer dependence on governments. (58)
He saw the first glimmer of this in the desire for sinecures with
the government in what he called "place hunting." There, the
isolated society's desire for stable places to rest without
engaging in the tumult of the market leads them into seeking
appointments in the civil service, creating a permanent constituency
forever desiring the expansion of the administration into more and more
areas of life. (59)
Policies, social habits, and personal choices that undermine the
integrity of family, public obligations to local government, and the
vibrancy of voluntary association necessarily diminish the commercial
ethos. Without these salutary interdependencies, commercial people lose
the strength to undertake risk and seek respite in the only remaining
alternative: the state. This creates a vicious dependence, one anathema
to the spirit of commerce precisely because it relies on a tutelary
administrative state to care for all citizens, one which "likes to
see the citizens enjoy themselves, provided they think of nothing but
enjoyment." (60) The choice Smith and Tocqueville present to us
falls between two extremes. One requires embracing natural forms of
interdependence with particular individuals, joining small groups to
achieve specific ends, and investing one's time in the
administration of local government. The other, by default, evacuates the
meaning and power of association and local government, while neutering
the power and moral authority of the family. Thus, understood rightly,
Smith and Tocqueville encourage us to foster local life without
undermining our incentive to take risks, care for ourselves, and save
for our future. The challenge, implicit in their writings and of
particular resonance for us today is to do all this while remaining
mindful of all the ways we really do need the state.
* I would like to thank Ralph Hancock, Joseph Reisert, Sarah Morgan
Smith, and the audience at the 2008 New England Political Science
Association Conference for their helpful comments.
References
Clark, Henry C. 1992. "Conversation and Moderate Virtue in
Adam Smith's Theory of Moral Sentiments" The Review of
Politics 54, no. 2 (Spring).
Den Uyl, Douglas J., and Charles L. Griswold, Jr. 1996. "Adam
Smith on Friendship and Love." The Review of Metaphysics 49, no. 3
(March).
Devine, Donald J. 1977. "Adam Smith and the Problem of Justice
in a Capitalist Society." The Journal of Legal Studies 6, no. 2
(June).
Fleischacker, Samuel. 1999. A Third Concept of Liberty: Judgment
and Freedom in Kant and Adam Smith. Princeton: Princeton University
Press.
Henderson, Christine Dunn. 2005. "Plus ca change...:
Innovation and the Spirit of Enterprise in America." The Review of
Politics 67, no. 4 (Autumn).
Lawler, Peter Augustine. 1995. "Tocqueville on Pride,
Interest, and Love." Polity 28, no. 2 (Winter).
Lerner, Ralph. 1979. "Commerce and Character: The
Anglo-American as New-Model Man." The William and Mary Quarterly
36, no. 1 (January).
Mathie, William. 1995. "God, Woman, and Morality: The
Democratic Family in the New Political Science of Alexis de
Tocqueville." The Review of Politics 57, no. 1 (Winter).
Mitchell, Joshua. 1995. The Fragility of Freedom: Tocqueville on
Religion, Democracy, and the American Future. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Newbert, Scott L. 2003. "Realizing the Spirit and Impact of
Adam Smith's Capitalism through Entrepreneurship." Journal of
Business Ethics 46, no. 3 (September).
Smith, Adam. 1981. An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the
Wealth of Nations. Edited by R. H. Campbell and A. S. Skinner. 2 vols.
Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.
--. 1984. Theory of Moral Sentiments. Edited by D. D. Raphael and
A. L. Macfie.
Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.
Tocqueville, Alexis de. 1969. Democracy in America. Edited by J. P.
Mayer. Translated by George Lawrence. New York: Harper Collins.
--. 1997. Memoir on Pauperism. Translated by Seymour Drescher.
Chicago: Ivan R. Dee.
Brian A. Smith
Assistant Professor
Department of Political Science and Law
Montclair State University
Notes
(1.) Joshua Mitchell, The Fragility of Freedom: Tocqueville on
Religion, Democracy, and the American Future (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1995), 157.
(2.) On the common ideas of Tocqueville and Smith on the commercial
society, see Ralph Lerner, "Commerce and Character: The
Anglo-American as New-Model Man," The William and Mary Quarterly
36, no. 1 (January 1979): 8-11. On Smith's vision of
entrepreneurship, see Scott Newbert, "Realizing the Spirit and
Impact of Adam Smith's Capitalism through Entrepreneurship,"
Journal of Business Ethics 46, no. 3 (September 2003); for an account of
some of the issues related to Tocqueville's understanding of trade
in society, see Mitchell, Fragility of Freedom, 115-20, 132-10, and
152-61.
(3.) Adam Smith, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the
Wealth of Nations, 2 vols., ed. R. H. Campbell and A. S. Skinner
(Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1981), 51-52, 84-87; Alexis de Tocqueville,
Memoir on Pauperism, trans. Seymour Drescher (Chicago: Ivan R. Dee,
1997), 46-47.
(4.) Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in America, ed. J. P. Mayer,
trans. George Lawrence (New York: Harper Collins, 1969), 402-3.
(5.) Christine Dunn Henderson, "Plus ga change...: Innovation
and the Spirit of Enterprise in America," The Review of Politics
67, no. 4 (Autumn 2005) emphasizes the extraordinary use American
entrepreneurs make of time (756-59). This connects to my argument in
that the innovations she notes rest on vital psychological traits
fostered only by salutary interdependence.
(6.) Henry C. Clark, "Conversation and Moderate Virtue in Adam
Smith's Theory of Moral Sentiments," The Review of Politics
54, no. 2 (Spring 1992), 187; Henderson, "Plus ca change ...,"
755.
(7.) Douglas J. Den Uyl and Charles J. Griswold, "Adam Smith
on Friendship and Love," The Review of Metaphysics 49, no. 3 (March
1996): 625-26; Peter Augustine Lawler, "Tocqueville on Pride,
Interest, and Love," Polity 28, no. 2 (Winter 1995): 227.
(8.) Smith, Inquiry, 795-96; Tocqueville, Memoir on Pauperism,
536-38.
(9.) Adam Smith, Theory of Moral Sentiments, ed. D. D. Raphael and
A. L. Macfie (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1984), 9-26; Tocqueville,
Memoir on Pauperism, 561-67; Samuel Fleischacker, A Third Concept of
Liberty: Judgment and Freedom in Kant and Adam Smith (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1999), 142-43; Den Uyl and Griswold,
"Adam Smith on Friendship and Love," 630-31.
(10.) Smith, Inquiry, 13-24; Fleischacker, A Third Concept of
Liberty, 156.
(11.) Smith, Inquiry, 782; Clark, "Conversation and Moderate
Virtue," 192-98.
(12.) Smith, Inquiry, 267, 637; Smith, Theory, 17.
(13.) Tocqueville, Memoir on Pauperism, 46-47. Echoing Smith and
also noting the technical improvements industry brings about,
Tocqueville nevertheless remarks that when "the principle of
division of labor is ever more completely applied, the workman becomes
weaker, more limited, and more dependent. The craft improves, the
craftsman slips back" (Democracy in America, 556).
(14.) Tocqueville, Democracy in America, 507.
(15.) Tocqueville, Memoir on Pauperism, 430-34.
(16.) Although she focuses on the issue of innovation, Henderson
("Plus ga change...") develops an important parallel to my
argument.
(17.) Tocqueville would emphasize the role egalitarianism and
popular sovereignty play in fostering this illusion of autonomy:
"Aristocracy links everybody, from peasant to king, in one long
chain. Democracy breaks the chain and frees each link.. There are more
and more people who. have gained or kept enough wealth and enough
understanding to look after their own needs. Such folk owe no man
anything and hardly expect anything from anybody.... Each man is forever
thrown back on himself alone, and there is danger that he may be shut up
in the solitude of his own heart" (Democracy in America, 508). Also
see Lawler, "Tocqueville on Pride, Interest, and Love," 225.
(18.) Lawler, "Tocqueville on Pride, Interest, and Love,"
218; Mitchell, Fragility of Freedom, 195.
(19.) Clark, "Conversation and Moderate Virtue," 187.
(20.) Smith emphasizes this idea of stability: "Vice is always
capricious: virtue only is regular and orderly" (Inquiry, 225).
(21.) Smith, Theory, 113, 219; Den Uyl and Griswold, "Adam
Smith on Friendship and
Love," 623-24.
(22.) Smith, Inquiry, 26.
(23.) Smith, Theory, 81-82; Tocqueville, Democracy in America, 585;
Donald J. Devine, "Adam Smith and the Problem of Justice in a
Capitalist Society," The Journal of
Legal Studies 6, no. 2 (June 1977): 400-404.
(24.) Smith, Theory, 113-15, 219-20; Clark, "Conversation and
Moderate Virtue," 192-98.
(25.) Tocqueville, Democracy in America, 593.
(26.) Smith, Theory, 190-91.
(27.) Tocqueville, Democracy in America, 593-94.
(28.) Lawler, "Tocqueville on Pride, Interest, and Love,"
233-34. Mathie rightly suggests that the power of liberal individualism
in society complicates this ("God, Woman, and Morality: The
Democratic Family in the New Political Science of Alexis de
Tocqueville," The Review of Politics 57, no. 1 [Winter 1995]:
11-12).
(29.) Both authors mention a variety of public services ordinary
citizens should perform. Tocqueville's description of the Puritan
township mentions many of these (Democracy in America, 61-98);
Smith's repeated insistence on militia service and other public
works echoes many of the same sentiments (Inquiry, 689-788).
(30.) Smith, Inquiry, 795.
(31.) Smith, Theory, 10, 30; Tocqueville, Democracy in America,
563-64.
(32.) Tocqueville, Democracy in America, 274.
(33.) Tocqueville, Democracy in America, 555; Smith, Inquiry, 782.
(34.) Tocqueville, Democracy in America, 274.
(35.) Ibid., 522.
(36.) Smith, Inquiry, 697.
(37.) Ibid., 783.
(38.) Tocqueville, Democracy in America, 162.
(39.) Tocqueville, Democracy in America, 513-17; Smith, Inquiry,
723, 758-88.
(40.) Tocqueville, Memoir on Pauperism, 69.
(41.) Tocqueville, Democracy in America, 444.
(42.) Ibid., 297.
(43.) Smith, Inquiry, 788.
(44.) Elsewhere Smith notes that liberty depends on this as well.
See Smith, Inquiry, 334 and Fleischacker, A Third Concept of Liberty,
152-53.
(45.) Tocqueville, Democracy in America, 514.
(46.) Henderson, "Plus ca change...," 767-68.
(47.) Tocqueville, Democracy in America, 672.
(48.) Smith, Inquiry, 723.
(49.) Tocqueville, Democracy in America, 50.
(50.) Ibid., 554.
(51.) Smith, Theory, 233-34.
(52.) Ibid., Theory, 234.
(53.) Tocqueville, Memoir on Pauperism, 67-68.
(54.) Tocqueville, Democracy in America, 696.
(55.) Smith, Inquiry, 689-816; Tocqueville, Democracy in America,
87-98.
(56.) Tocqueville, Democracy in America, 515.
(57.) Tocqueville, Democracy in America, 523.
(58.) Ibid., 682-83n8.
(59.) Ibid., 632-34.
(60.) Tocqueville, Democracy in America, 692; Lawler,
"Tocqueville on Pride, Interest, and Love," 221.