Corporate virtue and the joint-stock company.
Hawtrey, Kim ; Dullard, Stuart
Introduction
In the eyes of scholars and the community at large, the corporate
sector should be intentional and collegial about virtue, for "great
moral responsibility is inherent in the existence of corporations."
(1) For more than a century, this has been a recurring theme of business
legislation and analysis: for instance, in 1928, an early corporate
finance text described the enterprise as an arm of society, a form of
representative government, and, in the 1960s, good corporate character
was still seen to reflect the healthy functioning of the corporate
polity. (2) The ideal that firms should self-consciously pursue a vision
of the good is still very much alive today, with issues pertaining to
corporate virtue--and vice--featured regularly in the media.
The legal personality of the business corporation has evolved
however, from its origins as an organic business partnership run by its
owners to the modern-day impersonal organizations characterized by a
transfer of control from owners to engineer managers. The resulting
ownership structure is the joint-stock company, in which stockholding is
diffuse and the owners of the firm are separate from those who control
the enterprise, an observation made famous by Berle and Means. (3) In
turn, this creates a problem of identifying exactly where the moral
center of the firm resides.
Logically it is the stockholders, as the owners of the equity of
the firm and the residual claimants, who are the final custodians of the
corporation's sense of public virtue. Paradoxically, however, the
problem facing owners is that a joint-stock company by its very nature
involves collective action. This gives rise to the principal-agent
problem: the possibility that others acting on their behalf may not
always act according to the wishes of the owners. This in turn has led
to reliance on the market to discipline unethical behavior.
In what follows, we place this modern notion of corporate virtue in
historical perspective and then ask whether a richer view of the
virtuous corporation can be nurtured with consequential benefits for the
public good.
Origins: The Corporation as a Fellowship
The early form of the corporation was a concept that the British
had borrowed from the Romans who in the ninth and tenth centuries formed
organizations known as societas maris (maritime firms) that were
ventures to provide capital for maritime voyages. (4) This
organizational structure was characterized by a socius stans, a partner
on land and a socius tractor, the individual on the ship--an early
origin of the division between capital and labor. This legal
construction spread throughout Europe, particularly France and England.
(5) In England during the fifteenth century, the church and boroughs
were granted royal charters, (6) which in accordance with the
"concession theory" were a privilege from the Crown whereby
the group could opt out of certain feudal obligations. (7) This carried
a certain degree of independence from the Crown, including the right of
perpetual succession, to own property, and limited forms of
self-governance. (8) In the sixteenth century, this legal tool of royal
charter was utilized in a business context to facilitate the raising of
capital for mercantile trade, and later turnpikes, canals, and
railroads. (9)
Williston (1909) notes that the "most striking
peculiarity" of the early history of the corporation was the lack
of distinction between public and private, which at that time was
couched in terms of lay and ecclesiastical. (10) This can be observed by
examining the ancient boroughs and guilds that negotiated a degree of
autonomy with the Crown. The Crown before the 1688 revolution and the
Parliament thereafter through royal charter, granted the public the
power to make bylaws with respect to trade and commerce. (11) Crucially,
thinkers at the time classified these associations as a fellowship that
was born of voluntary association where the members participated and
behaved as if their members believed they could decide and act as
collective unities. (12) The concept of a fellowship with "real
personality" was central to the legitimacy of corporations, and
this had consequences for the regulation of such associations: "If
associations have no real being, then they must be mere creatures of the
state, and the state is then justified in deciding ... according to its
own lights when and to which groups associational freedom and corporate
status should be permitted, and in revoking such status at will."
(13)
The active participation of a corporation's members would
impart moral rectitude to the company from which legitimacy flowed and
justify an independence from the state. Through consultation and
participation, the actions of the group would be communally regulated in
accordance with public virtue and, hence, did not require the same level
of intervention from the state. In terms of ownership and management,
this ideology held that when owners manage their own organization, there
is little need for the state to intervene in its internal governance.
The philosophy embodied the concept of fellowship by granting
self-governing powers. (14) In short, business corporations were not
seen as wholly distinct from moral and political concerns, but rather
these were all bound up together, one reason being that the fields of
business (especially roads, canals, and railroads) were essentially
public goods.
The Separation of Ownership and Control
The seventeenth and eighteenth centuries brought a shift in
approach. The period experienced a financial revolution that saw a rapid
growth in joint-stock companies, banking, insurance, and the first
active stock market in Amsterdam. (15) The advent of the stock market
was significant as it represented anonymous buyers and sellers who
rarely participated directly in corporate governance. The speculative
trading of shares soon followed (prompting the Bubble Act of 1720), and
the concessional theory that incorporation as a privilege was now
effectively being superseded. (16) The new reality was that ownership
and control in the corporation had been separated and the corporate
entity had moved beyond the notion of a fellowship of personal
acquaintances to that of an impersonal collective. (17) This form
developed the notions of the corporation as a distinct legal entity, or
"persona ficta," separate from its members.18 This concept of
the firm as legal fiction has since been adopted by economists who
perceive the firm as a nexus of contracts.19 Jensen and Meckling state
that
The personalization of the firm is seriously misleading. The firm
is not an individual. It is a legal fiction which serves as a focus
for a complex process in which the conflicting objectives of
individuals are brought into equilibrium within a framework of
contractual relations. In this sense the behavior of the firm is
the behavior of a market, the outcome of a complex equilibrium
process. (20)
As time progressed, the business enterprise adapted to the
privileges afforded by a separate legal entity such as limited
liability, perpetual succession, and the ability to contract on its own
behalf. (21) Inevitably, the moral center of the firm grew more nebulous
with time.
Matters were further complicated by the rise of the specialist
managerial class. The corporation as a purely economic (vis-a-vis
sociomoral) vehicle proved extremely successful as the wealth held by
corporations grew exponentially in the twentieth century. This growth in
size meant the business enterprise was no longer limited to family or
partnership structures whereby owners managed, controlled, and were
liable for their business. (22) Professional managers were the new
captains of industry who effectively controlled wealth previously only
known to royalty. The rise of managerialism marked a profound
transition, one that Chandler later dubbed the "managerial
revolution." (23) The class of professional managers possessed
greater technical expertise than the stockholders of the firm and
consequently began to wield huge influence over the social priorities
and ethical stance of the business sector. The corporation's
origins as a unified fellowship with an inherent moral unity were deeply
affected by the crevice that now existed between management and
ownership.
The Principal-Agent Problem
A problem that flowed from the above was ensuring that managers act
on the wishes--whether commercial or ethical--of stockholders, a problem
known to economists and legal scholars as the principal-agent problem.
This problem arises due to the separation of ownership and control
whereby the owners of a corporation (shareholders) employ agents
(managers) to administer corporate resources on their behalf. To the
extent that corporations were operated by nonowners who might behave
according to self-interest rather than in the public interest, the
solution was seen to lie in an outside force that would act as a
restraint. One possibility was regulation by the state, and the other
was regulation by the market. Over time, the prevailing philosophy to
emerge was that sanctions on the corporation should predominantly lie
with the marketplace, with the state playing a supporting role.
Arguably the foremost mechanism that serves to keep the
principal-agent problem in check and foster good corporate citizenship for the public good is the market for corporate control.
Extrinsic Virtue: The Market for Corporate Control
As theorized by Manne, (24) the market for corporate control is
predicated upon the share market as an objective criterion for guiding
managerial performance. In the event an agent neglects its duty to act
on the wishes of the principal, corporate performance will wane, causing
the stock price to fall. This presents a profit opportunity for third
parties to respond by launching a bid for an underperforming company to
gain control and install a new managerial team, all with the aim of
enhancing corporate performance. In this manner, the market for
corporate control ensures diligence and virtue amongst corporate
managers, and the threat of takeover has a disciplinary effect on
management. Corporate governance would follow the "Wall Street
Rule" that if an investor does not agree with the fashion in which
a corporation is being governed, the investor can sell the stock.
Manne perceived the market for corporate control as a mechanism by
which market forces would promote the responsive corporation.
Manne's theory is that if corporate managers pursue their own ends
instead of the social good, the stock price will fall.
As an existing company is poorly managed, the market price of
shares declines relative to the shares of other companies or relative to
the market as a whole. This theory is predicated upon the public share
market providing an effective check on managerial performance. The role
of the market can thus be seen as serving the public interest:
[Corporations law] should serve in the future--as it has in the
past two generations--to provide a free, fair and informed market
that allows [an] investor to exit from the corporation when he
believes it is to his interest to make an exit. The share market
thus operates as the external adjunct of the corporation's internal
governance structure. (25)
In respect to promoting virtue or vice, the theory relies on the
market for corporate control to reduce the need for governmental
monitoring and provide management with sufficient incentive to behave
properly. A corollary of this theory is that public regulation should
serve to facilitate the effective functioning of the market, as market
forces will lead to the most efficient outcome, therefore serving
investors'--and society's--best economic and social interests.
Intrinsic Virtue: Renewing the Firm from Within
Does Manne's ubiquitous market constitute a satisfactory
vision for the virtuous corporation? We can be justified in feeling
uneasy about the notion that the corporation of the twenty-first century
is to have no conscience other than that implied by the impersonal
marketplace. One reason is empirical: The track record shows that
despite the disciplinary effect of the market, serious breaches still
occur. A series of episodes have continued to raise the community's
eyebrows about the (lack of) public-spiritedness of the corporate
sector, from highly geared entrepreneurs and junk bonds through to
high-profile ethical breaches such as Enron, WorldCom, and the Barings
Bank collapse. The East Asian currency crisis highlighted the issue of
corporate responsibility in emerging markets. (26)
Another equally important reason for unease is theological. The
market for corporate control, while useful as a negative discipline on
bad behavior, has a major shortcoming: it does not encourage any
particular positive vision for the public good. It does not push the
virtuous corporation to be all that it has the potential to be, nor does
it encourage social entrepreneurship. It imparts a minimum view of
corporate responsibility, for which we can be grateful, but does not
imagine a maximum moral vision, or mandate the contribution that the
joint-stock company as an organic "fellowship" might make, or
envision a view of the firm sustained by faith principles.
Such a vision for the virtuous joint-stock company must come from
within the organization. As we saw in the historical survey, the idea
that the business enterprise can see itself as a motivated moral entity
has traditional roots in the origins of the corporation itself. If we
recover the view of the enterprise not as a mere machine or as a fiction
but as the sum of persons, then the concept of a fellowship with
"real personality" can again inform the self-understanding of
the joint-stock enterprise. As in days of old, active participation by a
firm's members can once again impart moral rectitude to the
company, and from this can flow renewed moral legitimacy. This will
justify a continuing and even stronger independence from government
because through consultation and participation the actions of the
corporation would be communally regulated in accordance with public
concerns.
The Strategic Role of the Reflective "Agent"
How can a vision of the corporation as a virtuous fellowship be
regained? The individual agent, in our view, is strategically placed.
Novak asked whether a Christian can work for a corporation; perhaps the
question does not go far enough. (27) Our response to Novak's
excellent question is not just yes, but there is profound value in
persons of faith and character populating our corporations. Recent years
have witnessed how just one or two people can make an adverse difference
to an organization (Enron, WorldCom, and others), but the same applies
in reverse: one person acting as "salt and light" (Matt.
5:13-16) can make a significant positive difference for good.
The full practical outworking of this program is a big subject.
Here, we can but begin to sketch some of the practical areas where
thoughtful insiders might have a salt-and-light effect by way of three
examples: the board of directors, fiduciary duties, and executive
compensation.
Consider first the board of directors. Shareholders vote to elect
representatives who are delegated the power and duty to monitor
management and the affairs of the corporation, the theory being that the
corporation is run in accordance with the vision of shareholders. Boards
are composed of executive directors (EDs) and nonexecutive directors
(NEDs) who carry out the task of guiding the company. There is an
inherent trade-off with executive directors: on the one hand, they
possess specialized and firm-specific skills but, on the other, face
potential conflicts of interest because they are charged with the
responsibility of monitoring themselves. There has been a recent push
(particularly in the United Kingdom) (28) to increase the number of
independent, or nonexecutive directors on boards. While the reforms
resulted in larger boards and a higher percentage of NEDs, (29) the
empirical evidence suggests that the level of board independence and the
firm's decision-making are not linked. (30) One explanation for
this is that the CEO typically appoints and replaces NEDs, which are
well-paid positions and are perceived as a position of privilege and
esteem. NEDs thus have an incentive to retain these positions, a
consequence of such is to not oppose or contradict the CEO. (31) In
turn, this situation can blunt the board's ability to promote the
path of virtue and combat corporate excess. A theology of corporate
virtue can address such conflicts of interest.
Next, consider the efficacy of fiduciary duties. These are
equitable duties that arise in a relationship where one party acts for
the benefit of another, and fiduciary duty is the highest legal standard
of obligation that the law imports. Such duties are imposed upon
directors as general-law duties complemented by statutory duties, which
generally include the duty of care, skill, and diligence; the duty to
act in good faith and for a proper purpose; the duty to not improperly
use their position for personal advantage; and the duty not to
improperly use information obtained as a director. These laws manage the
balance inherent in directors being charged with the responsibility of
other people's money, whilst leaving scope for risk taking, a
balance reflected in the "business judgment rule" that
essentially says a business discussion will not be found to be in breach
of the duty of care if it is found to be made in good faith, on an
informed basis, in the best interests of the company. While the rule
itself is not objectionable, the application has in practice set a low
threshold for directors to evade liability. (32) Arguably, the law in
various countries has not placed a high enough level of care, skill, and
diligence onto company directors, thereby mitigating the threat of
prosecution from stockholder actions against directors and in turn
shackling the ability of the law to provide a disincentive for directors
to shirk their responsibilities.
In this context, reflective insiders with a vision for the company
as a self-aware virtuous fellowship can make a difference.
Another mechanism is executive compensation packages. These seek to
overcome the agency problem by aligning managerial incentives with
stockholder's interests. These packages exist within what is known
as the executive labor market. Empirical studies of management
compensation focus upon the sensitivity of pay to performance. In the
1990s, a consensus began to form that compensation was not linked
clearly enough to performance, that good performance was not rewarded,
and that poor performance was not penalized. (33) More recent studies
have confirmed this somewhat depressing picture by finding no
significant relationship between executive compensation and corporate
performance. (34) The rejection of the hypothesis that performance-based
executive remuneration improves corporate performance suggests that the
managerial labor market is not functioning effectively. (35) In turn,
this casts doubt on the responsiveness of managers to not only fulfill
the economic expectations of owners but also fulfill their moral
standards.
As the above brief discussion serves to demonstrate, significant
opportunities surround the internal mechanisms within the firm for
reflective individuals to guide the corporation to a clearer ethical
vision for the broader public good.
Conclusion
This article has contrasted two understandings of corporate virtue:
extrinsic and intrinsic. It has documented the ambiguity that has arisen
over time as to the moral center of the modern joint-stock company, and
it has pointed toward the need for a reconceptualization of the virtuous
corporation that rediscovers this center. We have argued that the
virtuous behavior of business decision-makers is a subject worthy of
theological reflection. We have particularly emphasized the desirability
that corporations have an effective internal moral compass, and the role
that reflective insiders can play in fostering this. A few individuals
with courage and faith can spread their influence and permeate the whole
entity with a sense of public purpose.
Such persons can be sustained by recovering a view of the
corporation as a fellowship whose legitimacy rests on its sense of civic
vocation. Such understanding will not be content to delegate truth and
meaning to an impersonal market mechanism but will value the notion that
true virtue is personal, intrinsic, and endogenous. A richer theology of
the corporation will help create a renewed vision of the joint-stock
enterprise sustained by higher principles.
References
Aboody, D., and R. Kasznik. 2000. "CEO Stock Option Awards and
the Timing of Corporate Voluntary Disclosures." Journal of
Accounting and Economics 29, no. 1:73-100.
Abowd, J. M., and D. S. Kaplan. 1999. "Executive Compensation:
Six Questions That Need Answering." Journal of Economic
Perspectives 13, no. 4:145-68.
Alchain, A., and H. Demsetz. 1972. "Production, Information
Costs and Economic Organization." American Economic Review 62, no.
4:777-95.
Angell, J., and S. Ames. 1832. A Treatise on the Law of Private
Corporations Aggregate. London: Hillard, Gray, Little, and Wilkins.
Barbour, V. 1963. Capitalism in Amsterdam in the Seventeenth
Century. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
Bebchuk, L. A., J. M. Fried, and D. I. Walker. 2002.
"Managerial Power and Rent Extraction in the Design of Executive
Compensation." University of Chicago Law Review. 69:751-846.
Becht, M., P. Bolton, and A. Roell. 2003. "Corporate
Governance and Control." In Handbook of the Economics of Finance.
Edited by G. Constantinides, M. Harris, and R. Slutz. Amsterdam:
Elsevier.
Berle, A. A., and G. C. Means. 1932. The Modern Corporation and
Private Property. New York: Macmillan.
Bhagat, S., and B. S. Black. 1999. "The Uncertain Relationship
Between Board Composition and Firm Performance." Business Lawyer
54:921-63.
Black, A. 1990. "Editor's Introduction." In
Community in Historical Perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Blair, M., and L. South. 2001. "Trust, Trustworthiness, and
the Behavioral Foundation of Corporate Law." University of
Pennsylvania Law Review. 14:17-35.
Braudel, F. 1982. The Wheels of Commerce: Civilization and
Capitalism, Fifteenth-Eighteenth Century, vol. 2. London: Collins.
Butler, H. 1986. "General Incorporation in Nineteenth Century
England: Interaction of Common Law and Legislative Process."
International Review of Law and Economics 6:169-88.
Cadbury, A. 1992. Report of the Committee on the Financial Aspects
of Corporate Governance. London: Gee & Co.
Carver, T. N. 1925. The Present Economic Revolution in the United
States. Boston: Little Brown and Company.
Chandler, A. 1977. The Visible Hand: The Managerial Revolution in
American Business. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Coase, R. 1937. "The Nature of the Firm." Econometrica
4:386-405.
Clough, S., and D. Moodie. 1965. "Charter of the East India
Company." In European Economic History. Edited by W. Davisson and
J. Harper. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Core, J., W. Guay, and D. Larcker. 2003. "Executive Equity
Compensation and Incentives: A Survey." Federal Reserve Bank of New
York Policy Review. 8, no. 1:27-50.
Dahya, J., J. McConnoll, and N. Travalos. 2002. "The Cadbury
Committee, Corporate Performance, and Top Management Turnover."
Journal of Finance 57, no. 1:461-83.
Dickson, P. 1967. The Financial Revolution in England. London:
Macmillan.
Du Bois, A. 1971. The English Business Company After the Bubble
Act. New York: Octagon Press.
Easterbrook, F., and D. Fishel. 1991. The Economic Structure of
Corporate Law. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Eells, R. S. F. 1960. The Meaning of Modern Business: An
Introduction to the Philosophy of Large Corporate Enterprise. New York:
Columbia University Press.
Ezzamel, M., and R. Watson. 2002. "Pay Comparability Across
and Within UK Boards: An Empirical Analysis of the Cash Pay Awards to
CEOs and Other Board Members." Journal of Management Studies 39,
no. 2:207-32.
Frug, G. 1980. "The City as a Legal Concept." Harvard Law
Review 93:1059-71.
Gugler, K., ed. 2001. Corporate Governance and Economic
Performance. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Habib, M. A., and A. P. Ljungqvist. 2002. "Firm Value and
Managerial Incentives." Mimeo. New York: New York University and
London Business School.
Higgs, D. 2003. Review of the Role and Effectiveness of
Non-Executive Directors. London: Department of Trade and Industry.
Holdsworth, W. S. 1908. A History of English Law, vol. 3. London.
Ireland, P. 1983. "The Triumph of the Company Legal Form,
1856-1914." In Essays for Clive Schmittoff. Edited by J. Adams.
Nashville: Abingdon.
Jensen, M. C., and R. S. Meckling. 1976. "Theory of the Firm:
Management Behavior, Agency Costs and Ownership Structure." Journal
of Financial Economics 3:305-60.
Jensen, M. C., and K. J. Murphy. 1990. "Performance Pay and
Top-Management Incentives." Journal of Political Economy.
98:225-64.
Lippmann, W. 1914. Drift and Mastery; An Attempt to Diagnose the
Current Unrest. New York: Holt & Co.
Mace, M. 1971. Directors: Myth and Reality. Boston: Harvard
Business School Press.
Manne, H. 1965. "Mergers and the Market for Corporate
Control." Journal of Political Economy 73:110-20.
Mead, E. S. 1928. Corporation Finance. 6th ed. New York: Appleton.
Murphy, K. 1999. "Executive Compensation." In Handbook of
Labor Economics, vol. 3. Edited by O. C. Ashenfelter and D. Card.
Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Novak, M. 1981. Toward a Theology of the Corporation. Studies in
Religion, Philosophy, and Public Policy. Washington: American Enterprise
Institute.
Pollock, F., and F. Maitland. 1968. The History of English Law. 2d
ed. London: Collins.
Ripley, W. Z. 1927. Main Street and Wall Street. Boston: Little,
Brown.
Vancil, R. 1987. Passing the Baton: Managing the Process of CEO
Succession. Boston: Harvard Business School Press.
Veblen, T. 1923. Absentee Ownership and Business Enterprise in
Recent Times: The Case of America. New York: B. W. Huebsch.
Webb, L. 1958. Legal Personality and Legal Pluralism. Oxford
University Press.
Werner, W. 1981. "Corporation Law in Search of Its
Future." Columbia Law Review. 81:1611.
Williams, J. 1985. "The Invention of the Municipal
Corporation: A Case Study in Legal Change." Auckland University Law
Review. 34:369.
Williston, S. 1909. "The History of the Law of Business
Corporations Before 1800." In Select Essays in Anglo-American Legal
History, vol. 3. Edited by Association of American Law Schools. Boston:
Little, Brown, and Company.
Worsman, I. M. 1931. Frankenstein Incorporated. New York:
McGraw-Hill.
Yermack, D. 1997. "Good Timing: CEO Stock Option Awards and
Company News Announcements." Journal of Finance 52:449-76.
Kim Hawtrey
Department of Economics,
Management, and Accounting
Hope College, Holland, Michigan
Stuart Dullard
Blake Dawson Waldron
Sydney, Australia
Notes
(1.) M. Novak, Toward a Theology of the Corporation, Studies in
Religion, Philosophy, and Public Policy (Washington, D.C.: American
Enterprise Institute, 1981), 52.
(2.) E. S. Meade, Corporation Finance, 6th ed. (New York: Appleton,
1928); R. S. F. Eels, The Meaning of Modern Business: An Introduction to
the Philosophy of Large Corporate Enterprise (New York: Columbia
University Press, 1960).
(3.) A. A. Berle and G. C. Means, The Modern Corporation and
Private Property (New York: Macmillan, 1932).
(4.) For discussion, see F. Braudel, The Wheels of Commerce:
Civilization and Capitalism, Fifteenth-Eighteenth Century, vol. 2
(London: Collins, 1982).
(5.) J. Angell and S. Ames, A Treatise on the Law of Private
Corporations Aggregate (London: Hillard, Gray, Little, and Wilkins,
1832) trace this process.
(6.) F. Pollock and F. Maitland, The History of English Law, 2d ed.
(London: Collins, 1968) provide a more detailed description.
(7.) J. Williams, "The Invention of the Municipal Corporation:
A Case Study in Legal Change," Auckland University Law Review 34
(1985): 369.
(8.) More detail is provided by L. Webb, Legal Personality and
Legal Pluralism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1958).
(9.) P. Dickson, The Financial Revolution in England (London:
Macmillan, 1967) is a useful source for this history.
(10.) S. Williston, "The History of the Law of Business
Corporations Before 1800," in Select Essays in Anglo-American Legal
History, vol. 3, ed. Association of American Law Schools (Boston,
Little, Brown, and Company, 1909).
(11.) For more discussion, see G. Frug, "The City as a Legal
Concept," Harvard Law Review 93 (1980): 1059-71.
(12.) A. Black, "Editor's Introduction," in
Community in Historical Perspective (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1990) examines this aspect.
(13.) Ibid.
(14.) For instance, the charter of the East India Company in 1600
reflected this, granting the "power to judge (criminal and civil)
all persons belonging to the said Governor" and "to send ships
to war" (S. Clough and D. Moodie," Charter of the East India
Company," in European Economic History, ed. W. Davisson and J.
Harper [New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1965]).
(15.) V. Barbour, Capitalism in Amsterdam in the Seventeenth
Century (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1963) provides
discussion.
(16.) See A. Du Bois, The English Business Company After the Bubble
Act (New York: Octagon Press, 1971) for general discussion.
(17.) This suggestion is put forward by H. Butler, "General
Incorporation in Nineteenth Century England: Interaction of Common Law
and Legislative Process," International Review of Law and Economics
6 (1986): 169-88.
(18.) W. S. Holdsworth, A History of English Law, vol. 3 (London:
Methuen, 1908). The move from a fellowship to a legal fiction is
confirmed in Salomon v Salomon (1897, AC 22) where the British House of
Lords clearly regarded the legal form as a legal fiction, a fiction that
did meet the strict letter of the law. In overruling the Court of
Appeal, the House of Lords cemented the corporation's status as one
of a mere creature of legislation.
(19.) A view along these lines can be found in A. Alchain and H.
Demsetz, "Production, Information Costs and Economic
Organization," American Economic Review 62, no. 4 (1972): 444-95
and R. Coase, "The Nature of the Firm," Econometrica 4 (1937):
386-405.
(20.) M. C. Jensen and R. S. Meckling, "Theory of the Firm:
Management Behavior, Agency Costs and Ownership Structure," Journal
of Financial Economics 3 (1976): 305-60.
(21.) See the description by P. Ireland, "The Triumph of the
Company Legal Form, 1856-1914," in Essays for Clive Schmittoff, ed.
J. Adams (Nashville: Abingdon, 1983).
(22.) This point was well articulated in the early twentieth
century by commentators such as W. Lippman, Drift and Mastery: An
Attempt to Diagnose the Current Unrest (New York: Holt & Co., 1914),
T. Veblen, Absentee Ownership and Business Enterprise in Recent Times:
The Case of America (New York: B. W. Huebsch, 1923), T. N. Carver, The
Present Economic Revolution in the United States (Boston: Little Brown
and Company, 1925), W. Z. Ripley, Main Street and Wall Street (Boston:
Little Brown and Company, 1927), and I. M. Worsman, Frankenstein
Incorporated (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1931).
(23.) A. Chandler, The Visible Hand: The Managerial Revolution in
American Business (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1977) provides a
general discussion.
(24.) H. Manne, "Mergers and Market for Corporate
Control," Journal of Political Economy 73 (1965): 110-20.
(25.) W. Werner, "Corporation Law in Search of Its
Future," Columbia Law Review 81 (1981): 1611. In a similar vein F.
Easterbrook and D. Fishel, The Economic Structure of Corporate Law
(Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1991) view the stock market as
overcoming the agency problem through an organized and public capital
market, stating that the market for corporate control "provides
some assurance of competitive efficiency among corporate managers"
thereby affording a check on self-interest.
(26.) M. Becht, P. Bolton, and A. Roell, "Corporate Governance
and Control," in Handbook of the Economics of Finance, ed. G.
Constantinedes, M. Harris, and R. Slutz (Amsterdam: Elsevier, 2003).
(27.) Novak, Toward a Theology of the Corporation, 1.
(28.) See A. Cadbury, Report of the Committee on the Financial
Aspects of Corporate Governance (London: Gee & Co., 1992) and D.
Higgs, Review of the Role and Effectiveness of Non-Executive Directors
(London: Department of Trade and Industry, 2003).
(29.) J. Dahya, J. McConnoli, and N. Travalos, "The Cadbury
Committee, Corporate Performance, and Top Management Turnover,"
Journal of Finance 57, no. 1 (2002): 461-83; M. Ezzamel and R. Watson,
"Pay Comparability Across and Within UK Boards: An Empirical
Analysis of the Cash Pay Awards to CEOs and Other Board Members,"
Journal of Management Studies 39, no. 2 (2002): 207-32.
(30.) S. Bhagat and B. S. Black, "The Uncertain Relationship
Between Board Composition and Firm Performance," Business Lawyer 54
(1999): 921-63.
(31.) M. Mace, Directors: Myth and Reality (Boston: Harvard
Business School Press, 1971); R. Vancil, Passing the Baton: Managing the
Process of CEO Succession (Boston: Harvard Business School Press, 1987).
(32.) For example, in the Australian case of Smith v van Gorkom
(488 A 2d 858 Del 1985), it was held that the requisite level of being
informed to make a decision was merely to be above the level of
"grossly negligent," which M. Blair and L. South, "Trust,
Trustworthiness, and the Behavioral Foundation of Corporate Law,"
University of Pennsylvania Law Review 14 (2001): 17-35 describe as a
situation whereby a director who is marginally above the level of being
grossly negligent will evade the liability that is imposed by the
fiduciary duty.
(33.) M. D. Jensen and K. J. Murphy, "Performance Pay and
Top-Management Incentives," Journal of Political Economy 98 (1990):
225-64.
(34.) J. Core, W. Guay, and D. Larcker, "Executive Equity
Compensation and Incentives: A Survey," Federal Reserve Bank of New
York Policy Review 8, no. 1 (2003): 27-50; L. A. Bebchuck, J. M. Fried,
and D. I. Walker, "Managerial Power and Rent Extraction in the
Design of Executive Compensation," University of Chicago Law Review
69 et al. (2002): 751-846; M. A. Habib and A. P. Ljungqvist, "Firm
Value and Managerial Incentives," in Mimeo (New York: New York
University and London Business School, 2002); J. M. Abowd and D. S.
Kaplan, "Executive Compensation: Six Questions That Need
Answering," Journal of Economic Perspectives 13, no. 4 (1999):
145-68; and K. Murphy, "Executive Compensation," in Handbook
of Labor Economics, vol. 3, ed., O. C. Ashenfelter and D. Card
(Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1999).
(35.) One explanation may be that the asymmetry of information
between corporate managers and the board presents an opportunity for
management to exploit. D. Yermack, "Good Timing: CEO Stock Option
Awards and Company News Announcements," Journal of Finance 52
(1997): 449-76 shows that management manipulate the timing of stock
option grants, while D. Aboody and R. Kasznik, "CEO Stock Option
Awards and the Timing of Corporate Voluntary Disclosures," Journal
of Accounting and Economics 29, no. 1 (2000): 73-100 find evidence that
management times the flow of good and bad news.