The clergy and economists: two windows on common objectives.
Lee, Dwight R.
Introduction
There are important differences between the clergy and economists,
though not as many as most believe. I shall argue that there is little
to distinguish the clergy from economists on humanitarian grounds. Their
worldly objectives are similar. The differences between them are in
their emphasis on how to achieve their common objectives. These
differences in approach are important and should not be understated, but
neither should they be overstated as they almost always are. While the
clergy and economists emphasize different paths to their common
objectives, those paths complement each other. Yet, they are commonly
discussed as if they represent morally irreconcilable differences in
objectives because of a tendency to confuse means with ends.
My hope is that members of the clergy, in their desire to achieve a
better world, will see economists as allies instead of as adversaries.
This hope may be dismissed as preposterous by some because I argue that
market incentives are the most effective way of achieving many of the
social outcomes that most of the clergy favor. Those most opposed to
market incentives for achieving desirable objectives have the most to
gain by taking a look through the economic window presented here. Much
of the skepticism, indeed hostility, toward markets is based on
distorted and mistaken views of how markets operate and what they
accomplish.
Better Angels vs. Economic incentives
Religious differences notwithstanding, most people respect the
clergy for their noble objectives and effort to achieve those objectives
by encouraging and celebrating the better angels of our nature mentioned
in Lincoln's first inaugural address. Most approve of the
clergy's concern with encouraging behavior such as sharing with,
and serving the interests of, others; helping the poor; sacrificing for
the good of the wider community; acting as good stewards of the
earth's resources; being concerned with protecting the environment;
and generally living a life that promotes social cooperation and
harmony.
Such a claim on behalf of economists would be met with incredulity
and probably derision. The common view is that they are primarily
interested in money and financial success; more likely to celebrate
economic competition than social cooperation, with little regard for
those left behind; prone to see profit and private property as ends in
themselves, with little regard for the unfortunate consequences that can
result from their pursuit, including the harm imposed on the environment
and future generations; and more concerned with how greedy individuals
can secure more for themselves than with how they can share with, and
promote the general well-being.
This view of economists, and their objectives, is a caricature.
Like most caricatures, it may contain an ounce of truth, but it also
contains several pounds of distortion. Economists are indeed interested
in money, competition, profits, private property, and the influence of
self-interest on human action, but they are interested in these things
not as ends, but as a means of achieving more social cooperation,
service to others, and better stewardship of the environment and our
resources. The earthly objectives of economists are quite similar to
those of the clergy.
To understand why this similarity in objectives is seldom
recognized, we must recognize that the clergy and economists are looking
at the world through different windows, and these different windows
suggest different ways of reaching common objectives. Instead of the
clergy and economists acknowledging that their views yield
understandings that are neither completely correct nor completely wrong,
they tend to become overly critical of the other's view and let
that obscure many of their common objectives.
It is useful to consider two broad approaches to improving the
world. The first is to improve people so that they do the right things
out of a sense of moral duty. The second approach is to improve
incentives so people are motivated to do the right things because it is
in their interest to do so. A reasonable generalization is that the
clergy emphasizes the former approach to improving the world, while
economists emphasize the second. It is easier to see the connection
between improving people and creating a better world than to see the
connection between improving incentives and creating a better world.
Furthermore, improving people has far greater emotional appeal than
improving incentives. The result, I shall argue, is a tendency to
confuse means and ends and to conclude that the clergy's objectives
are both different and nobler than those of economists.
Consider Charles Dickens' A Christmas Carol published in 1843.
In Dickens' story, Ebenezer Scrooge, "a squeezing, wrenching,
grasping, scraping, clutching, covetous old sinner" ends up helping
the Cratchit family and their crippled son Tiny Tim because Scrooge
becomes a better person after being visited on Christmas Eve by the
ghost of his former business partner and the three ghosts of Christmas.
The emotional impact of A Christmas Carol has sustained its popularity
for well over 160 years. Imagine if the story had been written by an
economist. Scrooge would have remained the same "covetous old
sinner," but he would have helped the Cratchit family because of an
increase in the tax deduction for charitable contributions. What a
touching story that would have been! It is easy to see the
transformation of Scrooge in A Christmas Carol as a noble objective by
itself. An increased tax break for charitable contributions is also
easily seen as an objective but hardly as a noble or emotionally
satisfying one.
While improving incentives lacks the sense of moral uplift provided
by improving people, better incentives can, and often do, lead to a
better world. For example, in the late eighteenth century, a large
percentage of prisoners being transported from England to Australia on
British ships were dying en route. Moral appeals to captains to
transport prisoners more humanely had no noticeable effect on the death
rate. Finally, a change in incentives was suggested--pay the ship
captains on the basis of how many prisoners walked off the ship in
Australia, instead of how many walked on in England. Implementing this
recommendation resulted in an immediate drop in the death rate of
prisoners being shipped to Australia, from as much as 37 percent to less
than 1 percent on most trips. (1)
The point is not that improving the world by improving people is
futile. Looking through their window may result in economists being too
dismissive of the possibilities and benefits of improving people.
Looking through their window may cause the clergy to be too dismissive
of better incentives as a sorry substitute for morality improvement. A
more reasonable view is that both improving incentives and improving
people complement each other. This was recognized by Dennis Robertson, a
colleague of John Maynard Keynes at Cambridge University (but not a
Keynesian himself), who observed:
There exists in every human breast an inevitable state of tension
between the aggressive and acquisitive instincts and the instincts
of benevolence and self-sacrifice. It is for the preacher, lay or
clerical, to inculcate the ultimate duty of subordinating the
former to the latter. It is the humbler, and often invidious, role
of the economist to help, so far as he can, in reducing the
preacher's task to manageable dimensions. (2)
In addition to Robertson's recognition that the clergy and
economists have, in their different ways, joint responsibilities in
working toward a better world, it is important to note that he also
recognizes that human nature consists of both the acquisitive and the
benevolent. This is an obvious point, noteworthy only because so many
people assume that economists believe human behavior is motivated
entirely by self-interest, or more pejoratively, greed. That is not true
now, and never has been. Economists have always recognized that people
are motivated by some mix of the narrow and the noble. Indeed, Adam
Smith, who is often mistakenly dismissed as an apostle of greed, begins
his first book, The Theory of Moral Sentiments, with the sentence (Smith
[1982, 9]), "How selfish soever man may be supposed, there are
evidently some principles in his nature, which interest him in the
fortune of others, and render their happiness necessary to him, though
he derives nothing from it except the pleasure of seeing it."
Economists do commonly assume that people are motivated solely by
self-interest to better understand what social institutions, and the
incentives they embody, best motivate widespread cooperation among those
who have no direct knowledge of, or concern for, each other. While this
"economic man" assumption is useful as an analytical device,
few economists believe he is commonly observed or hold him up as an
ideal. As the late economist Ken Boulding (1969, 10) said, "No one
in his senses would want his daughter to marry an economic man, one who
counted every cost and asked for every reward, was never afflicted by
mad generosity or uncalculating love.... Economic man is a clod."
Most economists agree with Boulding's assessment. If ever someone
needed improving, it is the economic man.
The Economists' Window on the World
The connection between better incentives and better results is
straightforward in the example of shipping prisoners. A more complete
explanation of the benefits economists see from good incentives requires
an examination of the social cooperation achieved in market economies.
Market incentives are certainly not perfect, and are subject to
improvement, but the same can be said for the efforts to improve people.
What market incentives accomplish, admittedly in conjunction with
ongoing efforts to appeal to our better angels, is truly impressive
given the magnitude of the task we depend on them to perform.
Each of us benefit daily from the efforts of literally hundreds of
millions of people from all over the globe, whom we will never know, but
who cooperate with untold numbers of others whom they will never know,
to provide us with almost everything we consume, and to provide it so
reliably and conveniently and in return for so little effort on our part
that we seldom realize, or take time to appreciate, what a blessing we
are experiencing.
Economists do appreciate this blessing of social cooperation for a
number of reasons, one of which is that we are concerned with reducing
poverty. People can produce more wealth when they work together in
mutually beneficial ways, and economists are convinced that the most
effective way of helping the poor is by creating new wealth, not by
redistributing existing wealth. This is not a blanket criticism of
redistribution, but wealth has to be produced before it can be
redistributed. Who can deny that the tremendous increase in the material
welfare of humans over the last two hundred years, despite the huge
increase in population, was possible only because of the enormous
increase in the production of wealth? (3)
Economists have tried to understand and explain how untold numbers
of complete strangers from all corners of the world have been able to
cooperate in ways that have increased wealth by pushing back the limits
of scarcity. The explanation is certainly not obvious. No matter how
virtuous those who work for our benefit may be, we cannot rely on their
concern for us to motivate their effort. It is their concern for
themselves and their loved ones that primarily motivates them. Neither
can others rely on our concern for them for most of the benefits they
receive from our efforts. Even if somehow we all developed an abiding
concern for multitudes of others, how would we acquire the information
needed to best serve them, and how would they acquire the information
needed to best serve us? Economists have developed a powerful
explanation for the impressive social cooperation, clearly seen by
anyone who cares to look, in terms of the communication and incentives
of the marketplace.
The social cooperation we benefit from every day depends on a vast
communication network that allows each of us to inform others how they
can best serve us and how we can best serve them, with this
communication motivating us to act as if we value the interests of
others as we do our own. This may seem to assume a completely
unrealistic level of technological sophistication and human virtue. In
fact, it assumes neither. Market communication has existed as long as
people have engaged in exchange (although it has been improved by
expansions in the network of those exchanges and technological
advances), and the use of the information communicated by markets for
the benefit of others requires rather modest levels of virtue.
Understanding the cooperation of the marketplace begins by
recognizing the informational role of market prices. Although seldom
seen as such, market prices that emerge from the exchange of private
property are one of our most effective ways for communicating vital
information. The prices we face in the marketplace tell us the value of
additional units of products to others and the value of the sacrifice
others experience making those additional units of products available to
us. (4) However, market prices not only communicate information on how
our decisions affect others, they also motivate us to use that
information to make choices that best serve the interests of others.
A few examples can illustrate the desirable social objectives that
are seen by economists as being achieved through the information and
incentives provided by market prices.
Consumers Cooperating with Consumers
Assume that Canadians decide that they want to consume more bananas
and would like Americans, and others around the world, to cooperate with
them by consuming fewer bananas. Canadians could try persuading others
to reduce banana consumption by communicating their consumption desires
through emails, text messaging, or other state-of-the-art communication
technologies. Far more effective communication, however, is the increase
in banana prices resulting from the Canadians' increase in demand
for bananas. In response to higher banana prices, people around the
world will reduce banana consumption, acting as if each is saying,
"Canadians are informing me that they now value additional bananas
more than I do, so I will share with them by consuming fewer so they can
consume more." Of course, no one is really saying or thinking this.
Few, if any, will have any idea why banana prices went up in their
neighborhood stores, or consider sharing bananas for the benefit of
Canadians, or anyone else. The advantage of price communication is that
it provides the minimum amount of information needed for people to best
accommodate the interests of others and provides them with the incentive
to do so. Market prices make it possible for people to simultaneously
and harmoniously coordinate their consumption decisions on a multitude
of goods.
No government agency could possibly keep current on the constantly
changing information necessary to know how people could best harmonize
their interests as banana consumers, much less do so for an untold
number of goods. Assume, though, that an agency could obtain and
constantly update all the necessary information, and immediately send
out understandable directives to all consumers requiring adjustment in
their consumption patterns. The responses would hardly be as harmonious
as that motivated by impersonal market prices. Changes in market prices
are the unintended consequences of the decisions of large numbers of
people, none of whom are telling you what to do. Directives from
government officials do tell you what to do and are far more likely to
be taken personally and resented. Why should I reduce my consumption of
bananas for the Canadians because some bureaucrat tells me to? Changes
in market prices are not always accepted passively as occasionally seen
with gas price increases when people blame them on oil companies and do
take them personally. Such animosity becomes far more prevalent, and
social harmony is reduced, when government directives are substituted
for market prices.
Producers and Consumers Cooperating with Each Other
Continuing with the banana example, the first ones able to respond
to the desires of Canadian consumers for more bananas are other
consumers. The higher prices, and profits, also provide banana producers
with the information and incentive to serve the interests of consumers,
both in Canada and elsewhere, by increasing banana production by way of
competing productive inputs away from other employments. This expansion
will continue as long as the market price informs suppliers that it is
socially beneficial--as long as the price indicates that the value of
additional bananas is greater than the cost of producing and shipping
them to consumers.
At the same time, price communication motivates consumers to take
into consideration the interest of producers. Assume, for example, that
insects increase the discomfort workers experience when harvesting
bananas. This will be reflected in higher wages for banana harvesters
and higher prices for bananas. Once more, without consumers knowing why
banana prices went up, they will respond to the higher prices in ways
that consider the interests of others--including those harvesting
bananas. Consumers will act as if they are saying, "Banana
harvesters are communicating to us that the extra discomfort they
experience making the last few bananas available is greater than the
benefit we realize from those bananas, so we will reduce our banana
consumption as long as the benefit to the harvesters is greater than our
sacrifice."
Again, our banana example illustrates the type of social
cooperation that is constantly taking place among literally billions of
people, involving a multitude of goods and services, and made possible
only by the information and incentives communicated through market
prices.
Producers Cooperating with Producers
Few products we use can be made from scratch by any one person or
firm. Even the simplest products require the cooperative effort of many
firms and individuals to cooperate. Consider a simple wooden pencil. As
Leonard Read (1958) pointed out in a famous article, no one can make a
standard wooden pencil. Its production requires workers and firms in
many countries coordinating their use of a number of widely dispersed
resources. Yet, pencils are so readily available at such low prices that
they are commonly given away to advertise businesses and products. The
complex network of global cooperation required to produce pencils, as
well as far more elaborate products (such as automobiles, computers,
televisions, compact disks, iPods, and cell phones) at costs almost
everyone can afford, is possible only because of the information and
incentives created by market prices. Those market prices, and the
profits and costs they determine, inform suppliers where in the
production chain of different products they can move to create the most
net value and what provides the incentive for them to do so.
Unfortunately, for producers to cooperate in remaining responsive
to constant changes in technologies, preferences, and general economic
conditions to best serve consumers, they have to take actions that are
commonly seen by members of the clergy, and many others, as socially
unjust. For example, when technological improvement makes it possible to
produce electronic calculators, consumers will communicate through
market prices that the resources and workers being used to produce slide
rules would now be more valuably employed producing the calculators. In
response to this market information and incentives, slide-rule producers
cooperate with producers of electronic calculators and consumers by
laying off their workers and going bankrupt. It is as if slide-rule
firms and their workers are saying, "We are not serving consumers
as well as we would if we released our resources and labor to be used by
other firms. So, we will go bankrupt and accept the loss of our current
jobs to make it easier for other firms to better serve consumers by
expanding their production." As before, this is not what firms and
workers in unprofitable firms are actually saying. They do not want to
go bankrupt or lose their jobs and would prefer a government subsidy
forcing consumers to continue paying for their products (slide rules)
through taxes. The advantage of the market is that without government
policies overriding the interests of consumers, it is constantly
conveying information to all of us on how to make the best use of our
resources to serve others and then imposing the discipline to ensure
that we do exactly that.
In Defense of Economic Pain
No economist would claim that the wealth realized through market
cooperation is all gain and no pain. Profits and losses are inherent
features of market competition, and as Milton Friedman emphasized many
times, the losses are as important as the profits. Those failing to use
their resources to best serve others suffer losses as their resources
and opportunities are competed away by those doing a better job serving
others. The resulting bankruptcies, layoffs, and financial reversals are
painful, and we all suffer that pain from time to time. This pain is
easily seen, widely condemned, and invariably blamed on the dog-eat-dog
callousness of the market. Economists are commonly criticized for
condoning this economic pain and defending the market process that
inflicts it. However, as seen through the economists' window on the
world, the pain inflicted by markets is essential to communicating the
information and incentives that create the social cooperation from which
we all benefit.
While no one enjoys pain imposed by market competition, living in
an economy that failed to impose that pain would be far worse. Living in
such an economy has much the same disadvantage as living in a body that
did not register pain. A few unfortunate infants are born without the
ability to feel pain--a defect known as congenital analgesia. These
children seldom live long, dying early from injuries they never feel or
learn to avoid. As with physical pain, the economic pain imposed by
markets informs people when they are making harmful economic decisions
and motivates them to either correct those decisions or transfer the
resources under their control to those who will make better use of them.
When governments go beyond moderate attempts to disguise the pain
of market incentives their citizens suffer far greater pain from a
general
waste of resources. Parents of a child with congenital analgesia
would, if they could, move that child into a body that imposed pain.
Similarly, when people can migrate across borders, the flow is
overwhelmingly away from countries where authorities are aggressively
attempting to suppress the pain of market incentives as parents move
themselves and their children to countries where that pain is given
freer rein.
Economists Are Interested in Money
Economists are interested in the role of money in the economy
because it is important to communicating the incentives economists
believe serve to make the world a better place. Money is not of interest
to economists as an end in itself, as common criticisms of economists
seem to imply. Economists see money as a convenient claim on goods and
services that facilitates the exchanges and from which market prices,
denominated in money, naturally emerge. Money is then nothing more than
the physical material that embodies those prices that communicate the
information and incentives that economists see as creating more social
cooperation, opportunity, and prosperity--the ends in which economists
are very much interested.
Letting the Motives Obscure the Accomplishment
Admittedly, the cooperation of the marketplace is not cooperation
in the noblest sense of the word. Ideally, cooperation results from
people working together for a common goal out of a genuine concern for
each other. Market cooperation is motivated primarily by the various,
and often conflicting, goals of many individuals who are far more
concerned with themselves and their loved ones than they are with most
of those with whom they are cooperating. This type of cooperation is not
completely satisfying and does not even qualify as cooperation in the
minds of many.
Economists can respond that surely it is preferable to realize the
social benefits from global cooperation for reasons less exalted than
universal goodwill than to realize them hardly at all. We can point out
that even if we did achieve universal goodwill, it would be insufficient
for anything more than the most limited cooperation. Even if everyone
possessed a saintly concern for all, whether in distant parts on the
globe or across the street, we would have little information on how to
convert our concern into effective action without the information
communicated by market prices. Such arguments, however, are unlikely to
be persuasive to many. It is easy to take the benefits of market
cooperation for granted, concentrate on what are seen as the base
motives motivating those benefits, and dismiss the market process as
unworthy. There is probably no completely effective way to combat this
tendency.
My attempt in this article can be successful, however, without
convincing market skeptics among the clergy to embrace the market
process with enthusiasm. As indicated in the introduction and by the
title, I hope, rather, to convince members of the clergy that economists
want to achieve many of the same worthy objectives that they do, even
though our means of doing so are different. The tendency for members of
the clergy to concentrate on the means economists recommend (a tendency
they share with many others) makes it difficult for them to recognize
our common objectives. Consider two examples of ends that are
universally to be considered noble being obscured when they are achieved
by market means considered less than noble.
Almost everyone, including economists, favors protecting the
environment by reducing pollution. Indeed economists have given
considerable thought to achieving the social cooperation necessary to
reduce as much pollution as possible for a given sacrifice in other
things we value. Not surprisingly, they have concluded that creating a
market in pollution reduction is more effective than having a government
agency issue directions to polluters on how and/or how much pollution to
reduce--an approach known as command and control. Creating a market in
pollution reduction involves distributing, or auctioning off, enough
transferable pollution permits to allow the discharge of the permitted
amount of the pollutant under consideration. Those who can reduce
pollutant at low cost find reducing it more profitable than buying
permits, and they reduce a lot. Those who can reduce pollutant only at
high cost will profit by buying permits and not reducing by much. The
result is abatement patterns that achieve pollution reduction at far
less cost (or achieves more pollution reduction for a given cost) than
is achieved with commands and controls that tend to be applied uniformly
on all polluters. (5) Yet, recommendations to reduce pollution through a
market approach have met with resistance by many whose interest in
reducing pollution cannot be doubted. The achievement of a cleaner
environment at less cost is trumped by an aversion to the selfish
motives that lead to the achievement.
Consider next the popularity of resource conservation. Almost
everyone responds favorably to the idea of conserving our resources to
ensure that they are available for future generations. Yet, few consider
how much of a resource is desirable to conserve. Obviously, we should
conserve a resource when it is worth less today than it will be in the
future. It makes no sense to continue conserving a resource after it
becomes worth more today than in the future. Even if we knew how much of
a resource to conserve, how do we motivate people to conserve the
desirable amount? Conservation requires current sacrifice, and the
temptation is strong for people to hope others will do the conserving.
What few recognize, or appreciate, is that the most effective force
for conserving resources is speculators communicating through and
responding to market prices in search of profits. Speculators constantly
anticipate how much resources will be valued in the future, and they buy
those resources they believe can be profitably stored for later
sale--those that are worth conserving. These speculative purchases drive
up current prices, which motivates consumers to reduce their current
consumption; for example, to conserve. While there would be little
conservation without the incentives of higher market prices, and people
universally claim they approve of conservation, most of them despise
speculators as profit-seeking hoarders who drive up the prices of
important resources. This negative view of the motives obscures, if not
obliterates entirely, the desirable end being accomplished when those
motives are directed by market incentives.
Conclusion
I am not trying to convince members of the clergy to forsake the
perspective from their window on the world and shift their allegiance to
the economists' perspective. First, I could not succeed even if
that was my purpose. People invest serious effort in achieving an
understanding of the world, and this understanding, along with an
accompanying belief system, provides a valuable sense of coherence and
meaning to our lives not easily given up. Einstein recognized this value
when stating:
Man tries to make for himself in the fashion that suits him best a
simplified and intelligible picture of the world. He then tries to
some extent to substitute this cosmos of his for the world of
experience, ... he makes this cosmos and its construction the pivot
of his emotional life in order to find in this way the peace and
serenity which he cannot find in the narrow whirlpool of human
experience. (6)
Just as I cannot imagine giving up my economic understandings, and
the beliefs informed by them, I certainly do not expect to convince
members of the clergy to give up their understandings and beliefs.
I have no desire to convince members of the clergy to shift their
perspective to that provided by the economic view of the world. The
window that informs the clergy is an important one. The clergy have
insights and understandings that are useful in improving our lives and
our world in ways that cannot be clearly seen, if seen at all, through
the economists' window. By specializing in helping people improve
themselves through spiritual and moral teachings, I believe the
understandings of the clergy complement those of economists in achieving
the noble objectives we have in common. My desire is to convince members
of the clergy that they and economists really do share common objectives
and have complementary approaches for achieving them.
When economists talk about such things as private property,
exchange, market prices, money, and financial profits and losses, we
honestly believe we are talking about social arrangements that make the
world a better place--a more humane and prosperous place, where billions
of people cooperate through a global network of communication, service,
and sharing to reduce poverty, feed the hungry, care for the sick,
protect our environment, conserve and expand our resource base, and
promote a host of other noble objectives. Some members of the clergy,
along with others, will disagree with this economic understanding of the
world. However, do not conclude from this, as many do, that economists
are not committed to achieving these noble objectives.
References
Boulding, Kenneth E. "Economics as a Moral Science." The
American Economic Review 59, no. 1 (March 1969): 1-12.
Navarro, Peter. "The Politics of Air Pollution." The
Public Interest, no. 50 (Spring 1980): 36-44.
Pirsig, Robert M. Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance. New
York: HarperTorch, 2006.
Read, Leonard. "I, Pencil." The Freeman (December 1958):
32-37.
Roberts, Russell. The Invisible Heart: An Economic Romance.
Cambridge: MIT Press, 2001.
Robertson, Dennis H. Economic Commentaries. London: Staples Press,
1956.
Smith, Adam. The Theory of Moral Sentiments. Indianapolis:
LibertyClassics, 1982.
Tietenberg, Tom. Environmental and Natural Resource Economics, 7th
ed. Boston: Pearson Education, 2006.
Notes
(1.) For a more detailed discussion of the effect of changing the
incentives on shipping prisoners from England to Australia, see Roberts
(2001, 267-68).
(2.) See Robertson (1956, 148).
(3.) One can make a host of arguments that the increase in wealth
has come at great cost. Clearly, the additional wealth has been realized
very unequally over the globe. However, few today, even among the
poorest, would want to exchange their condition today for the working
conditions, infant mortality rates, life expectancy, educational
opportunities, and general level of comfort and convenience that existed
at the beginning of the nineteenth century.
(4.) No one would argue that price information is perfect. There
are often what economists refer to as externalities created in the
production and use of products that are not reflected in their market
prices--for example, the environmental costs from using electricity
generated by a coal-fired plant that is external to the calculation of
those producing and consuming the electricity. These problems invariably
result from the lack of market exchanges that would require compensation
for the harm being done--by the smoke in the electricity example. While
it is theoretically possible for government to correct such
externalities with regulation or taxes, government decisions are often
distorted by their own externalities, as organized groups see political
opportunities to secure benefits paid for by others. For example,
government regulation of coal-fired plants has been used by eastern coal
interests to protect themselves against competition from western coal at
the expense of electricity consumers and the environment--see Navarro
(1980). The information communicated by market prices does not have to
be perfect to be extraordinarily impressive and far better at motivating
social cooperation than any known alternative.
(5.) Numerous studies have estimated the ratio of the cost of
reducing pollution with commands and controls to the cost of reducing it
by the same amount with market approaches. The ratios vary, but they
average a little over six in the representative studies cited in
Tietenberg (2006, 380)--it costs a little over six times more to reduce
pollution with command and control than with market approaches.
(6.) Cited in Pirsig (2006, 138).
Dwight R. Lee
William J. O'Neil Chair of Global
Markets and Freedom
Cox School of Business
Southern Methodist University