The Moral Consequences of Economic Growth.
Hill, Peter J.
The Moral Consequences of Economic Growth
Benjamin M. Friedman
New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 2005 (570 pages)
It is a shame when what could be a good book is made into a
somewhat mediocre one by overreaching. Friedman has written an
interesting and well-researched economic history of the relationship
between economic growth and certain aspects of political and economic
life. His main thesis is that economic growth "more often than not
creates greater opportunity, tolerance of diversity, social mobility,
commitment to fairness, and dedication to democracy" (4). He
provides considerable evidence, not all of it convincing, for his thesis
that there is a relationship between growth and those particular aspects
of our moral culture. His claim to be laying out the relationship
between growth and moral progress, however, suffers from both too
limited a focus and too much generalization.
Friedman wants to counter the argument that economic growth is
simply about material well-being and also to argue that it is
"simply not true that moral considerations argue wholly against
economic growth" (14). The author undertakes an admirable task and
one that needs much more attention. The moral and ethical issues
surrounding economic growth are of great importance, and as he points
out, many commentators have seen an inherent conflict between morality
and economic progress. This book could be a useful antidote to the
rather constricted view that economic growth only provides material
well-being and that moral arguments do not favor a private property
market system, but it has only limited success in that respect.
Friedman carefully summarizes Enlightenment thinking with regard to
moral progress and also connects it well to religion and religion's
impact on economics. He begins his argument by pointing to recent
periods of economic stagnation and economic growth in the American
economy and the impact of these conditions on certain aspects of our
civic culture. He also provides a well-researched economic history of
the United States, again connecting the rates of economic change that
have existed at various periods in time to attitudinal changes on the
part of the American populace. Friedman analyzes other economies as
well, taking up the history of Britain, France, and Germany and changes
in their legal and social structure. Finally, the argument is extended
to the developed world and the relationship between growth and
democracy. The book concludes with policy recommendations for
maintaining economic growth in the United States, based on
Friedman's belief that moral progress, as he defines it, is
crucially dependent upon a flourishing economy.
However, Friedman's book suffers from serious flaws. He is too
quick to take the Enlightenment perspective that economic and moral
progress go hand in hand, and he has a very narrow perspective on the
essential components of morality. In his attempts to resurrect
Enlightenment thinking with respect to moral progress, he takes a
limited view of what counts for improvements in morality; namely, more
openness, tolerance, and a greater degree of political democracy. If he
wishes to take up issues of morality and the economy, it is unfortunate
that he does not treat the basic question of whether or not market
economies, which he seems to favor, are morally legitimate in their
fundamental structure. He has no discussion of individual rights,
whether these rights are morally defensible or not, or the ethical
implications of engaging in consensual transfers of property rights
through market exchange. He does not take seriously the possibility that
increased material well-being and expanded opportunities may remove
certain moral constraints in society and change perceptions of what ends
are worth striving for. Neither does he take up basic issues of honesty,
personal integrity, or commitment to family and marriage. Because these
issues are fundamental to any discussion of the morality of the economic
system, much less the morality of economic growth, his discussion leaves
one with the impression that the only interesting moral questions are
those connected to issues of openness and tolerance. Even openness,
though, does not mean that he is taking up the moral issue of open
borders with regard to trade. He presents a case for globalization as an
enhancer of economic growth, but he denies that his term openness might
refer to the ability to trade across political boundaries.
Finally, the book treats the whole issue of poverty reduction
reasonably well, but the author does not connect his discussion to his
moral arguments. Surely poverty is a moral issue, and the reduction of
poverty has moral implications. However, because Friedman has limited
himself to questions of tolerance and openness, he does not include
poverty amelioration as an important moral argument for economic growth.
The other substantial problem with the book is the measures that
Friedman uses for openness and tolerance. In his framework, we are a
more open society when we have greater government intervention that
redistributes income, provides entitlements, or enhances opportunity for
some groups through affirmative action programs. Some of the
interventions that he presents as morally desirable surely fit within
that framework, but others are much more questionable.
The 1996 Welfare Reform Legislation is depicted as a rolling back
of our level of tolerance and openness rather than as a serious effort
to reform our welfare laws that had strong disincentive effects for
entering and staying in the workplace and for maintaining family
stability. Likewise, the debate over the appropriate level of enforced
affirmative action and the efforts to slow down some affirmative action
programs all represent moral regress rather than legitimate concern
about conflicting moral claims.
Even if one accepts Friedman's index of moral improvement as
greater government regulation and involvement in the economy, there are
still anomalies that he does not deal with well. The Great Depression is
the origin of much of the modern regulatory state that also grants
massive entitlements to citizens. Friedman recognizes that this does not
fit well with his theory that in periods of stagnation people become
less concerned with each other and in periods of growth more concerned,
with concern represented by growth in government. Similar pieces of data
from Britain, France, and Germany do not fit his basic hypothesis, a
fact that he acknowledges but does not adequately address. The numerous
times that political and social change does not fit within his model
raises serious questions about its overall applicability.
An alternative hypothesis keeps rearing its ugly head as one reads
through the book. Perhaps, as economies mature, citizens ask too much of
their government--more than they are willing to pay for or more than
government can effectively deliver. The interplay between government and
the economy can represent a moral failing unless government is
appropriately constrained to those areas where it can act effectively.
There is a hint of this argument in the discussion of the problem
of labor-market regulation in western Europe, but Friedman never takes
seriously much of the recent work in economics that does not always see
government intervention as a benign force but as an agent that can be
captured by special interests for their own purposes. In his last
chapters (actually the best in the book) Friedman does discuss the
interplay between institutions and the economy and the problems of
financing Social Security and Medicare, but again, this is not well
connected to his arguments about growth and morality.
At one level, Friedman has written a well-researched and
well-argued book that makes a reasonable case for certain positive moral
impacts of economic growth. One should not discount those aspects of
morality that he thinks are important and that tend to flourish more
fully in a growing economy. At another level, Friedman too easily adopts
the Enlightenment view that economic progress and moral progress go
together. He transforms the Enlightenment perspective on moral progress
into a constrained perspective on morality that ignores other important
components of a moral and ethically fulfilling world. Even though
Friedman makes passing reference to some authors who offer moral
critiques of society, he does not treat in any serious way the
possibility that economic growth, while enhancing certain moral aspects
of our society, could have a deleterious effect on other aspects.
Neither does he offer anything close to a full discussion of the
morality of the institutions that produce economic growth. Friedman
leaves too much out of his moral framework to claim that he has made a
convincing case for the moral consequences of growth.
--Peter J. Hill
Wheaton College, Wheaton, Illinois, and Property and Environment
Research Center, Bozeman, Montana