The moral dimensions of poverty, entitlements, and theft.
Block, Walter ; Wirth, Harold E.
In the view of many commentators and pundits, all citizens have an
entitlement to be relieved of their poverty, which, they believe, would
best be accomplished by throwing other people's money at the poor.
This article makes the case that not only do the impoverished not have
any such right, but the attempt to furnish them with wealth earned by
others constitutes theft and does not help them in any case. Given,
however, that such entitlements exist, what is the proper moral
response? To approach an answer to this question, this article defines
and then applies "libertarian class analysis" to the question
and derives from this perspective some counterintuitive conclusions
regarding welfare recipients and reparations for past invasions of
person and property.
The Ideal World
For the limited government, free-enterprise-oriented classical
liberal, there is only one type of entitlement the citizen may properly
receive from the state: security of his person and property. This
entitlement entails an army to protect him from foreign despots, a
police force to shield him from domestic villains, and a court system to
determine who is and who is not an initiator of violence against another
person or his property. Any and all other entitlements are
illegitimate--at least from the perspective of this economic philosophy.
(1) One defense of this limited notion of government is that entitlement
programs (2) are counterproductive, which means such programs actually
hurt their presumptively intended beneficiaries.
The list of such instances is long and woeful. Perhaps the most
egregious is the welfare program, Aid to Families with Dependent
Children (AFDC). Originally introduced as a means of helping the needy,
(3) AFDC has instead promoted dependency, eviscerated personal ambition,
and created whole generations of unwanted and often abused children. (4)
These children, in turn, often graduate to a life of crime and continue
the practice of rearing still other children of the same ilk. (5) The
reason for this is not difficult to discern: Supply curves slope in an
upward direction, the more one pays for an item, the more of it is
called forth in the market. Welfare is the offer of money for people who
are poor. The more money offered for this purpose, the more incentive
people have to change their behavior to be eligible for these funds,
which is not to say that a Bill Gates or a Donald Trump will be
attracted to this lifestyle. But there are always people on the margin,
teetering on the edge, where, on one side, lies the (lower) middle class
life of honesty and probity, and, on the other, the underclass of
dissolution. In their precarious position on the fence they are
particularly vulnerable to a slight push in either direction. AFDC
provides that impetus, and it is all in the wrong direction--for our
society in general, as well as for the particular people involved. (6)
Then there is the issue of public housing. Originally based on
similar benevolent motives, (7) this attempt to help the poor, too, has
instead boomeranged into disaster. The Cabrini Green projects in Chicago
are world-famous for feces and urine in the (often nonfunctioning)
elevators, ripped out light bulbs, boarded-up windows, crime, gangs,
drugs, and other accouterments of a return to barbarism. The Pruit-Igoe
homes in Saint Louis were so uncivilized that they had to be bombed, not
by terrorists, (8) but by the government housing authority charged with
their upkeep and maintenance.
The cause of this dissolution is not hard to understand. Socialist
to the core, the governments involved with these entitlements precluded
commercial establishments such as stores, banks, and restaurants from
these environs. But without the pedestrian traffic of shoppers, people
living in the apartments above are less likely to keep their "eyes
on the street." (9) This, in turn, leads to increased crime rates
as criminals prefer to ply their trade without witnesses. Tipper income
cut-offs are generally used by bureaucrats to determine eligibility for
public housing. Thus, when a poor tenant family surpasses a certain
level of income, it is booted out of its accommodation. One can easily
appreciate the disincentive effects here. Worse yet, those who prosper
and then are forced to leave, are the most successful among the
inhabitants. They are the natural neighborhood leaders, typically adult
males, who are desperately needed to serve as role models for teenagers.
In this situation, the cream rises to the top and then is skimmed off,
leaving a helpless and victimized mass of people in its wake.
Another criticism of entitlements is that they have perverse income
effect. (10) While most people see transfers as helping the poor at the
expense of the rich, in fact, an inordinate number go to (sectors of
the) middle class and the rich. (11) Listed under this rubric are farm
subsidies (which go mainly to large-scale agri-business), bailouts for
big business (Lockheed, Chrysler), rescues for the banks (e.g., the
billions spent to undergird the Mexican peso), protective tariffs (which
benefit domestic manufacturers while despoiling local consumers and
Third World industry), minimum wages (which oppress poor, unskilled,
minority group workers to further aggrandize rich, well-organized labor
unions). (12) It is not without good reason that such recipients have
been well and truly castigated as "corporate welfare bums."
If we have learned anything from the Public Choice School (13) it
is that the more well-off are able to assert their will not only in the
private but also in the public sector. It should not occasion much
surprise that this also holds true with regard to transfers. The rich
are simply too well-organized to allow a system of subsidies to function
contrary to their own best interests.
A further difficulty with government largesse with taxpayers'
money is that it engenders the idea that these funds come as a matter of
right. The so-called welfare rights movement is only the tip of the
iceberg. People now believe that they have the "right" to such
diverse benefits as social security, education, food stamps, Workers
Compensation, unemployment insurance, to mention only a few. But how can
two separate people have the right to one-and-the-same thing? How is it
possible for both the rightful owner (the one who earned the money
through voluntary market activity), as well as for the recipients of all
these programs, to have a right to this wealth? This is impossible,
since, if properly construed, there can be no such thing as a conflict
in rights.
Adherents of entitlements often argue that these programs came
about as a result of democratic institutions. Duly constituted
politicians, who derive their authority from the electorate, inaugurated
them. They, in turn, appointed bureaucrats and administrators who
received a warrant for their subsequent actions indirectly from the
voters through Congress and the President. Entitlements, then, are
justified as part and parcel of our democracy.
While this may sound reasonable, in my opinion, it fails utterly.
The argument is a variation on legal positivism--the claim that the law
is always just--since it can trace its beginnings back to a majority
vote. Why is a forced transfer of money rendered any less of a theft
because more than half the voters supported it? Suppose two hoodlums
break into my apartment and are walking off with my television set. When
I object that they are stealing my property, they agree to hold a
referendum on the issue. One of them (a philosophical robber) says,
"How many object to us taking Block's television set?"
Whereupon l raise my hand. He then asks, "How many favor this
action?" and the two thieves register their approval. Does this
veneer of democracy legitimize their act of theft? Hardly. Nor can it be
objected that in the case of the United States--unlike the democratic
robbers--we had all agreed beforehand to be bound by the results of
elections because of the Constitution. In point of fact, no one ever
signed any such agreement. (14) Hitler, to cite one extreme case, came
to power as the result of an exercise of the ballot. Does this fact
alone legitimize all his political acts? Certainly not. But if not, how
can mere democracy justify the United States government's forcibly
transferring money from some to give to others?
In addition to harming the poor both directly (e.g., welfare
creates dependency) and indirectly (elements (15) of the middle class
and the rich attain the lion's share of the wealth) these
entitlements are immoral. We have focused thus far on the harm to the
supposed beneficiaries of these programs, but no discussion of the moral
dimensions of poverty and entitlements can ignore the fact that these
initiatives are financed by coercive tax levies. The money to pay for
welfare, public housing, and other such transfers, is taken from
innocent taxpayers at gunpoint. If the sole justification for the
limited state is to protect the person and property of the citizen, then
these entitlements must be seen as a contradiction or violation of that
principle. The point is, if we are to undertake a thorough moral
analysis of entitlements, we must not constrict the scope of our
deliberations merely to the recipients. Even on the unwarranted
assumption that the people who receive these monies actually benefit
from them, the transfers cannot be morally sanctioned because they
violate the rights of those who made the contributions.
The Real World
So far, we have discussed the ideal classical liberal world in
which entitlements would be entirely absent. (16) In the real world,
however, such programs are all too common, which furnishes us with the
opportunity to engage in further analysis. To wit, given the fact that
entitlement programs exist, how should the moral agent act in regard to
them?
One possibility, which is the simplest and perhaps the most
emotionally satisfying response, is that they simply be ignored. (17)
After all, if these initiatives are unjust, what could be more
appropriate than remaining detached from them? But there are problems
with this view. Superficially, such a course of action is highly
impractical. If a person were to eschew benefiting from any government
expenditures or to refrain from taking part in any welfare or public
housing programs, this would mean that citizens could not use the post
office, streets, roads, highways, lighthouses, schools, libraries,
museums, symphony halls, and so forth. Life under such conditions might
not approach Hobbes' description of society as "nasty,
brutish, and short," but would come too close for comfort, and
public life would be impoverished.
Another possibility is that participation in entitlement programs
is a matter of mere pragmatism unworthy of moral analysis. More
important, it might be argued, is that classical liberal principles
simply do not mandate avoiding governmental largesse, for advocates of
strictly limited government, too, have been forced to finance these
entitlements. If they avail themselves of the benefits thereto, their
actions can be interpreted as merely seizing (the use of) their own
money back and not as theft.
Contrary to this simplistic solution, the problem with entitlements
is the whole process of government seizing our wealth and giving it to
others. Since we are all victims and beneficiaries of this game, the
whole process of forcing the entire society to pay for things its
members are unwilling to finance themselves is morally objectionable. In
isolation, then, it is not improper for people to seek to recover the
taxes that have been levied against them.
Who, then, should accept government entitlements? To what extent
should this be occurring in society? To answer the first question, we
must avail ourselves of libertarian class theory. (18) Suppose, for
instance, there were a classical liberal Nuremberg Trial, the purpose of
which was to discern who was guilty for perpetuating the welfare state
entitlement system. Would everyone be responsible, since, willy-nilly,
all people (excluding a few hermits) participate in it? No. As we have
seen, it is morally justified for at least some people to get their own
money back. Instead, the answer is given that the ruling class is guilty
for perpetuating the entitlement system.19 Members of this class are
considered to be in violation of the strictures of free enterprise. But
who are members of the ruling class? How can they be distinguished from
other people, all of whom accept government transfers?
First of all, the distinction is based on whether a person actively
works to support, aid, and abet the entitlement system, or works to
dismantle it. (20) As a first approximation, the former at least
potentially qualify for ruling class status, the latter do not, but this
is only a presumption. It can be defeated on several grounds. Take, for
example, the issue of free speech. In a free society, anyone can say
nearly anything he pleases. (21) Mere verbal support of entitlements
will not suffice. Another exception is for low-level administrators. Not
every mail carrier or typist in the Social Security administration,
would be deemed to be in violation of libertarian law.
Standard protocol in war may shed some light on these
deliberations. Typically, in war, the officers of the defeated army are
found guilty. By contrast, the enlisted men, who were usually drafted in
any case, are incorporated into the victor's army, and subsequently
treated as relative equals with the other soldiers. Likely to be in the
dock, then, are the politicians who enacted entitlement legislation, and
the senior bureaucrats who carry it out. The senior bureaucrats would be
equivalent to the officers in our model. Furthermore, all those involved
at any level in impermissible activities would be forced to defend their
actions. Candidates for this category might include the East German
soldiers who shot their compatriots who were fleeing to the West, or to
a lesser extent, our own police forces who systematically violate civil
rights.
According to the philosophy of classical liberalism, it is to
members of the ruling class that we owe the forced transfer society and
who alone would be ineligible from receiving entitlement benefits. All
others would not be precluded from accepting government grants on moral
grounds.
An immediate objection might be registered to this scenario.
According to this analysis, then, the welfare mother will still receive
her benefits. She, after all, is a poor candidate for membership in the
ruling class. I concede that this conclusion may seem paradoxical coming
from a perspective that condemns welfare root and branch. If the logic
of the case leads in this direction, then it really does not matter
whether it is counterintuitive. The point is, given that there are
entitlement programs, anyone who is not a member of the ruling class can
possibly (but is not required to) make a moral claim to the existing
benefit. While there is no justification, in my estimation, for
entitlement benefits in the first place, the fact that they exist in the
real world places no ethical barrier against the aggrieved making use of
them.
Reparations
While reparations and entitlements share some characteristics--both
are payments from one party to another--there is a gigantic moral chasm
between the two. Entitlements, as we have seen, amount to no less than
theft. Parties of the first part, taxpayers, are forced by law to
subsidize parties of the second part, welfare recipients, corporate
welfare bums, and agribusiness. Reparations, by contrast, are the
opposite of theft because they attempt to reverse the effects of
stealing by returning property to its rightful owner. Indeed, a large
part of libertarian punishment theory is predicated upon restitution.
(22)
But can entitlements such as welfare not be justified on the ground
that they are an implicit form of reparation? After all, AFDC recipients
are poor; the taxpayers, on average, are certainly richer than those at
the lowest income brackets. The problem with this line of reasoning is
that mere wealth does not imply theft. Mere poverty does not imply
victimization by robbers since people can become rich without stealing
and become poor without being pilfered. It is only a bit of vulgar
Marxism to contend that the rich are rich because the poor are poor.
Whom, after all, did Ray Kroc, Steve Jobs, or Bill Gates rob? The
millions of dollars of new wealth they created simply did not exist
before them, nor, by definition, did anyone rob a starving group of
Stone Age tribesman who were suddenly discovered in Africa or South
America. No one denies that robbery can sometimes be a sufficient
condition for wealth, but it is certainly not a necessary one as implied
by this argument.
But what about the case of slavery? Indeed, this institution
amounted to theft of labor (and much more, of course). Therefore, a
classical liberal perspective certainly could justify reparations in the
case of slavery. (23) However, if the payments are to be morally
enacted, several conditions must be met. First, if there is any case for
reparations, these should come from guilty parties, not from the entire
citizenry through the tax system. To make all citizens pay for the
crimes of a few would be to extend--not diminish--the effects of
robbery. Second, if the reparations are for an act that took place many
years ago, a direct link between the historical victims and the present
recipients must be forged. For example, although virtually all slaves in
the United States were black, and many present welfare recipients are of
the same race, not all of the latter can trace their roots to the
former. That is, many present African-Americans are the children not of
slaves, but of people who came to this country after 1865, from Africa,
from the Caribbean, and so forth. Third, for historical cases, a close
connection between the guilty and those called upon to make the payments
must be established. Most important, in all such cases, we must cleave mightily to the basic legal axiom: "Possession is nine-tenths of
the law." That is, the presumption must always be that the present
owner is the rightful owner. It is the burden of the one who would upset
property titles to prove, beyond a reasonable doubt, that reparation is
justified.
In the case of slavery, these somewhat stringent conditions can
conceivably be met. (24) It is common knowledge that plantations
throughout the old Confederacy were established with slave labor. When
the Civil War ended, if more complete justice were to have taken place,
the slaves would not merely have been freed. The lands they had been
forced to cultivate would have been given to them and would not have
remained in the hands of their former owners. Full compensation might
even have contemplated enslaving these former masters to the newly freed
slaves--a sort of poetic justice.
Unfortunately, in 2001, those slaveholders are beyond reach of the
civil authorities. But the plantations, houses, farms, and the wealth
that was left to their progeny, which should have been given to the
newly freed slaves, are still in existence and now owned by the great
grandchildren of the slave masters. If any present black person can
prove family connection with a slave who endured forced labor at a
specific plantation, he should be given that property. If there is more
than one claim to the property, then it should be divided equally among
all legitimate claimants.
One objection to this modest proposal is that to enact this idea
would be to punish the grandchild for the sins of the grandparent. But
this is simply not true. To take away a farm from a white person in
Alabama and give it to an African-American person is, in some sense, to
"punish" the former. But this is not really true--the white
relative should not have been given the farm, in the first place. The
reparation is merely the return of stolen property to the heir of the
rightful owner. If my grandfather stole your grandfather's ring and
then gave it to me, I am not the rightful owner of the ring even though
I have possession of it. On the contrary, you are the rightful owner. If
justice is to prevail, I must turn it over to you. I will not have been
punished--only made to do what returning stolen property implies.
Another objection to reparations is that there should be statute of
limitations on past crimes. The enslavement of blacks by white
Americans, or of biblical Jews by Egyptians, land theft from the
Indians, the seizing of Japanese-American property during World War II,
Arab-Israeli land conflict, the latifundia, are lost in the winds of
time and should remain so. But why should there be any statute of
limitations on justice? Suppose that we know that A stole X from S, and
then gave it to his progeny, a, and we also know of b, the latter's
grandchild. Surely justice requires that we right this wrong, even if it
is an ancient one. (25)
Finally, there are legitimate concerns about fairness. How do we
know the reparations are actually justified, when the theft took place
so long ago? At this point, the classical liberal conditions come back
to the forefront of discussion. Possession is nine-tenths of the law and
the burden of proof is always on those who seek to overturn present
property titles. If the robbery took place in biblical times, or before
there was a written language, then, to that extent, it is exceedingly
unlikely that anyone can prove anything. This stricture lends a
conservative element to the reparation proceedings. Reparations are very
different from entitlements. When properly construed, they amount to no
more and no less than a return of stolen property; however, by contrast,
entitlements constitute the theft of legitimately owned property.
Walter Block
Harold E. Wirth Eminent Scholar and Chair in Economics
College of Business Administration
Loyola University
New Orleans
Notes
(1.) Observe that this conclusion is similar--but not precisely
equal--to the vision of appropriate entitlements as provided for in the
United States Constitution. There, in addition to the aforementioned
courts, armies, and police, the citizen is also entitled to a post
office and other public enterprises. These services and institutions
would be strictly prohibited under a libertarian limited-government
vision, the model we shall assume for the purpose of this article.
(2.) Now and henceforth, we use the term entitlement program to
refer to other initiatives of the state over and above armies, courts,
and police. These latter three we characterize not as entitlement
programs, which are always illegitimate uses of government force, but as
the sole legitimate functions of government. For a critique of this
limited government philosophy from within libertarianism, see Bruce L.
Benson, The Enterprise of Law: Justice Without the State (San Francisco:
Pacific Research Institute, 1990); "The Impetus for Recognizing
Private Property and Adopting Ethical Behavior in a Market Economy:
Natural Law, Government Law, or Evolving Self-Interest," The Review
of Austrian Economics 6, 2 (1993): 43-80; "Customary Law as a
Social Contract: International Commercial Law," Constitutional
Political Economy 2 (1992): 1-27; "An Evolutionary Contractarian
View of Primitive Law: The Institutions and Incentives Arising under
Customary Indian Law," The Review of Austrian Economics 5, 1
(1991): 41-65; "Enforcement of Private Property Rights in Primitive
Societies: Law Without Government," The Journal of Libertarian
Studies IX, 1 (Winter 1989): 1-26; "Legal Evolution in Primitive
Societies," Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 144
(1988): 772-88; "The Lost Victim and Other Failures of the Public
Law Experiment," Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy 9 (1986):
399-427; Anthony De Jasay, The State (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1985);
David Friedman, The Machinery of Freedom: Guide to a Radical Capitalism,
2nd ed. (La Salle, Ill.: Open Court, 1989); "Private Creation and
Enforcement of Law: A Historical Case," Journal of Legal Studies 8
(1979): 399-415; Hans-Hermann Hoppe, The Economics and Ethics of Private
Property: Studies in Political Economy and Philosophy (Boston: Kluwer,
1993): "The Economics and Sociology of Taxation," in Taxation:
An Austrian View, ed. L. Rockwell (Boston: Dordrecht, 1992); A Theory of
Socialism and Capitalism: Economies, Polities, and Ethics (Boston:
Kluwer, 1989); David Osterfeld, "Anarchism and the Public Goods
Issue: Law, Courts, and the Police," The Journal of Libertarian
Studies 9, 1 (Winter 1989): 47-68; Joseph R. Peden, "Property
Rights in Celtic Irish Law," The Journal of Libertarian Studies 1,
2 (Spring 1977): 81-96; Murray N. Rothbard, For a New Liberty (New York:
Macmillan, 1973); Power and Market: Government and the Economy (Menlo
Park, Calif.: Institute for Humane Studies, 1970); The Ethics of Liberty
(Atlantic Highlands, N.H.: Humanities Press, 1982); Lysander Spooner, No
Treason (Larkspur, Co.: Tannehill, Morris, and Linda, 1966 [1870]); The
Market for Liberty (New York: Laissez-Faire Books, 1984); William C.
Woolridge, Uncle Sam the Monopoly Man (New Rochelle, N.Y.: Arlington
House, 1970).
(3.) For an alternative Marxist perspective, one that analyzes
welfare as enabling capitalists to control labor markets, see Frances
Fox Piven and Richard A. Cloward, Regulating the Poor: The Functions of
Public Welfare (New York: Random House, 1971).
(4.) See Thomas Sowell, The Vision of the Anointed (New York: Basic
Books, 1995); Race and Economics (New York: Longman, 1975); Ethnic
America (New York: Basic Books, 1981); The Economics and Politics of
Race: An International Perspective (New York: Morrow, 1983); A Conflict
of Visions: Ideological Origins of Political Struggles (New York:
Morrow, 1987); Race and Culture: A World View (New York: Basic Books,
1994); Charles Murray, Losing Ground: American Social Policy from 1950
to 1980 (New York: Basic Books, 1984); In Pursuit: Of Happiness and Good
Government (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1990); Walter F. Williams,
"Good Intentions--Bad Results: The Economic Pastoral and
America's Disadvantaged," Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics,
and Public Policy 2, 1 (1985): 179-99; Gary M. Anderson, "Welfare
Programs in the Rent Seeking Society," Southern Economic Journal 54
(1987): 377-86; Martin Anderson, Welfare: The Political Economy of
Welfare Reform in the United States (Stanford: Hoover Institution Press,
1978); Marvin Olasky, The Tragedy of American Compassion (Chicago:
Regnery Gateway, 1992).
(5.) Observe how the illegitimate entitlement of the dole is
incompatible with the legitimate state function provided by the courts,
armies, and police. One protects person and property from attack; the
other exacerbates these problems.
(6.) Anderson, "Welfare Programs in the Rent Seeking
Society."
(7.) Of course, as the old adage goes, "The road to hell is
paved with good intentions."
(8.) This is a debatable point.
(9.) Jane Jacobs, The Death and Life of Great American Cities (New
York: Vintage, 1989).
(10.) This phraseology is particularly unfortunate because it
implies that while there is something perverse about robbing the poor to
enrich the wealthy, no such opprobrium applies to stealing from the rich
and giving their money to the poor. However, at least for the classical
liberal, theft is theft, no matter what the income status is of the
victim or the recipient of the stolen goods.
(11.) Terry Anderson and P. J. Hill, The Birth of the Transfer
Society (Lanham, Md.: University Press of America, 1989).
(12.) This is perhaps the most egregious and deceitful entitlement
plan in that all experts know full well the effects of minimum wages on
the poor. See Walter F. Williams, The State Against Blacks (New York:
McGraw-Hill, 1982).
(13.) Thomas J. DiLorenzo, "Competition and Political
Entrepreneurship: Austrian Insights into Public Choice Theory," The
Review of Austrian Economics 2 (1988): 59-71; James M. Buchanan, Cost
and Choice: An Inquiry into Economic Theory (Chicago: Markham, 1969);
James M. Buchanan and Gordon Tullock, The Calculus of Consent: Logical
Foundations of Constitutional Democracy (Ann Arbor: University of
Michigan Press, 1971); Robert Lloyd and Joseph P. McGarrity, "A
Profit Analysis of the Senate Vote on Gramm-Rudman," Public Choice
85 (November 1995): 81-90; Kevin B. Grier and Joseph P. McGarrity,
"The Effect of Macroeconomic Fluctuations on the Electoral Fortunes
of House Incumbents," Journal of Law and Economics XLI (April
1993): 143-61; James M. Buchanan, Robert D. Tollison, and Gordon
Tullock, eds., Toward a Theory of the RentSeeking Society (College
Station: Texas A&M University Press, 1980).
(14.) Nor can our agreement to abide by majority rule be predicated
on the fact that we continue to reside in the United States. Some might
argue, "If you do not like the way we run things here, you are
always free to leave. Since you choose to stay, this indicates your
willingness to be bound by electoral processes." As Spooner makes
clear, many present residents can trace their property titles, in an
unbroken chain, back to a time before the birth of our nation. The
government, presumably, is set up to safeguard our property. How, then,
can such people be told to leave if they do not support democratic
conclusions? See Spooner and Lysander, No Treason.
(15.) It is impossible for the entire middle and upper classes to
benefit at the expense of the poor. By definition, the poor have little
that can be taken from them. The former cannot exploit them to a great
degree since "You can't get blood out of a stone." But
different categories of the rich and middle classes most certainly
enrich themselves at the expense of other members of society.
Agricultural subsidies, for example, benefit wealthy and middle class
farmers. The same is true for tobacco subsidies, automobile subsidies,
subsidies to scientific research and development, and so forth. When all
of the taxes and subsidies are taken into account, there are only two
possibilities: (1) everyone ends up with exactly what he had before,
rendering the whole process absurd and nugatory, or (2) there are
winners and losers. The contention here is that segments of the rich and
middle class are the main beneficiaries, not the poor. See Franz
Oppenheimer, The State (New York: Free Life Editions, 1975 [1914]).
(16.) In the economic literature there are numerous attempts to
justify entitlements. For a criticism of these attempts, see Robert
McGee, "Mergers and Acquisitions: An Economic and Legal
Analysis," Creighton Law Review 22, 3 (1938): 665-93; Jack High,
"Bork's Paradox: Static Versus Dynamic Efficiency in Antitrust
Analysis," Contemporary Policy Issues 3 (1984-1985): 21-34; Walter
Block, "Total Repeal of Anti-Trust Legislation: A Critique of Bork,
Brozen, and Posner," The Review of Austrian Economics 8, 1 (1994):
1-64; Fred McChesney, "Antitrust and Regulation: Chicago's
Contradictory Views," Cato Journal 10 (1991): 775-98; Hoppe, A
Theory of Socialism and Capitalism; "Fallacies of the Public Goods
Theory and the Production of Security," The Journal of Libertarian
Studies IX, 1 (Winter 1989): 27-46; Jeffrey Rogers Hummell,
"National Goods Versus Public Goods: Defense, Disarmament, and Free
Riders," The Review of Austrian Economics 4 (1990): 88-122; Walter
Block, "Public Goods and Externalities: The Case of Roads,"
The Journal of Libertarian Studies 7, 1 (Spring 1983): 1-33; David
Osterfeld, "Anarchism and the Public Goods Issue: Law, Courts, and
the Police," The Journal of Libertarian Studies 9, 1 (Winter 1989):
47-68; Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia (New York: Basic Books,
1974).
(17.) By stipulation, we cannot ignore paying for these programs
since they are foisted on us. But there is no law compelling us to take
part in them as recipients.
(18.) Murray N. Rothbard and Jerome Tuceille, eds., Left and Right:
Selected Essays, 1954-1965 (New York: Arno Press, 1972); Rothbard, For a
New Liberty; Hans-Hermann Hoppe, "Marxist and Austrian Class
Analysis," in Marxism: Economics, Religion, Politics, and
Philosophy, ed. Yuri Maltsev (Boston: Dordrecht, 1992).
(19.) Marxists have given ruling class theory, as they have
everything else they have touched, a bad name. In their view, to employ
someone is to exploit him, and thus to be a member of the ruling class.
For a critique of this viewpoint, see Eugen von Bohm-Bawerk, Capital and
Interest, trans. George D. Hunke and Hans F. Sennholz (South Holland,
Ill.: Libertarian Press, 1959 [1884]), particularly Part I, Chapter XII,
"Exploitation Theory of Socialism-Communism."
(20.) Conservatives often ridicule the notion of ruling class.
While their criticisms do indeed refute the Marxist version, they leave
libertarians unscathed. Consider the following statement by David
Horowitz, "Clarence Page's Race Problem and Mine,"
Heterodoxy (May/June 1996): 6. "The very phrase 'institutional
racism' is, of course, of leftist provenance. It is also a
totalitarian term. Like 'ruling class', it refers to an
abstraction, not a responsible individual being. You are a class enemy
(or in this case a race enemy) not because of anything you actually
think or do, but 'objectively'--because you are situated in a
structure of power that gives you (white skin) privilege."
This author is clearly denigrating Marxist ruling-class theory but
not the libertarian variety. For in the latter case, it is one's
actions and not status that is responsible for membership in the ruling
class. For classical liberals, it is not sufficient (nor, even strictly
speaking, necessary) to be rich to be included in this category. All one
need do is engage in theft, which is certainly something any person can
do.
(21.) Hitler himself may have never directly or personally killed a
single Jew but he gave the orders to do so. Commands of this sort must
be distinguished from free speech, at the very least, on the ground that
the former implies physical threat while the latter does not.
(22.) Randy Barnett, "Pursuing Justice in a Free Society, Part
One: Power vs. Liberty," Criminal Justice Ethics 4 (1985): 50-72;
The Structure of Liberty: Justice and the Rule of Law (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1998); Randy Barnett and John Hagel, eds., Assessing the Criminal
(Cambridge, Mass.: Ballinger, 1977); Hoppe, The Economics and Ethics of
Private Property; Rothbard, For a New Liberty.
(23.) Curiously, several classical liberal writers have rejected
the notion of reparation. They did so not for slavery but for land theft
perpetrated on the peasants by the conquistadors in Latin and South
America, a case certainly analogous to slavery. Included here are Milton
Friedman, David Friedman, Walter Berns, and Edmund Opitz. See Walter
Block, Geoffrey Brennan, and Kenneth Elzinga, eds., Morality of the
Market: Religious and Economic Perspectives (Vancouver, B.C.: The Fraser
Institute, 1985), 495-508. For a response to the anti-reparation
position, see Walter Block and Guillermo Yeatts, "The Economics and
Ethics of Land Reform: A Critique of the Pontifical Council for Justice
and Peace's Toward a Better Distribution of Land: The Challenge of
Agrarian Reform," Journal of Natural Resources and Environmental
Law 15, 1 (1999-2000): 37-69; and Walter Block, "On Reparations to
Blacks for Slavery," forthcoming.
(24.) This lends support to Malcolm X's claim for reparations
to blacks. See Malcolm X, Malcolm X Speaks: Selected Speeches and
Statements, ed. George Breitman (New York: Merit Publishers, 1965).
(25.) To be sure, there are practical objections to reparations.
Enacting them is certain to create hard feelings and to rekindle ancient
animosities, but we are concerned here with justice not practicality. We
are analyzing payments from a moral point of view and not necessarily
from a practical one. In any case, a large part of the present conflict
is due to occurrences that took place a long time ago. It is possible
that reparations might also reduce hard feelings and not exacerbate
them.