Controversy: do market economies allocate resources optimally? A response to Walter Block.
Murphey, Dwight D.
In these controversy exchanges, the beginning article will have
stated the opening author's thinking with a completeness and
coherence to which the later surrebuttal will neither need nor be able
to aspire. I see my function at this time as relatively limited: (a) to
clear up a confusion that inhabits Professor Block's introductory
remarks and (b) to respond to him on the main points he has made.
Clearing up confusion will not be as intellectually interesting as the
more substantive discussion but is necessary because I believe that my
message may have become obscured.
Clearing Up the Initial Confusion
Block's introduction is based on a misreading of my own
opening comments. I was not at that point giving reasons why the optimum
allocation of resources concept is wrong but, rather, telling why I am
eager to have the idea recognized as fallacious. The "purely
intellectual" reason I gave was that the concept is based on
"an elementary fallacy"--but I did not in my introduction seek
to explain what that fallacy is, leaving the discussion of that until
later. Second, I indicated that the fast-approaching,
non-labor-intensive technology will largely make the system of
income-through-wages obsolete, and that this will lead to labor
displacements and inequalities that will make the self-contained systems
of laissez-faire philosophy no longer serviceable to hundreds of
millions of people. That observation was not itself a demonstration that
the optimum concept is wrong; instead, it merely described why we must
start questioning the self-contained systems that, by justifying
anything that happens, will impede our ability to formulate sound theory
for the world that is fast-developing. As an (erstwhile?) classical
liberal, I do not want all of the values and principles of classical
liberalism to pass into disrepute because its advocates cling to inadequate theoretical systems.
The "Fallacy of Wrongly Imputed Consciousness"
Let us first examine Block's rebuttal to my point about the
optimum concept's being based on an "elementary fallacy."
This is the central point in my paper so far as the optimum claim is
concerned.
Readers will do well to reread my discussion of the source of value
judgments, in which I said that there is neither "good" nor
"bad," "best" or "better," to inanimate
objects or forces, and that value judgments must come from some
consciousness. Since the only forms of consciousness we know of (capable
of judgment) is God (or gods) and individual human beings, there is an
error of "wrongly imputed consciousness" when someone seeks to
impute judgment-making ability to some mediate entity, such as
"consumers" taken as an aggregate. I pointed out how Ludwig
von Mises had been fully aware of this mistake in other areas but fell
into it with respect to consumers in treating them holistically.
I looked forward to receiving Block's rebuttal, because I was
curious about just how he would overcome this difficulty. I see,
however, that he passes over it entirely, apparently never grasping its
importance. He considers my central argument as merely a
"gratuitous slap at Mises," and thus, dismissing it, moves on.
(I never intended to take a slap at Mises, gratuitously or not. I
remember him with the greatest affection and respect. But I do not
confuse those assessments with a need to agree on every aspect of his
thinking, which, in my opinion, is the worst form of homage that can be
shown to a serious thinker.)
As Block moves on to other matters related to the optimum concept,
it would seem that he is mainly arguing for the market's allocation
on the very ground that I myself have accepted, namely, whether the
allocation is "best" or "proper," we are willing to
accept it because it is the result of a free process. I have made the
point that this claim is something distinct from the idea of "best
allocation."
Other Conceptual Issues Raised in the Rebuttal
Let us take these randomly as they come to mind. First, Block says
that the optimum concept "is hardly the rallying cry of
libertarians," who base their thinking on deduction from
"private property rights and the non-aggression axiom." I
agree that the optimum concept is not a linchpin for that particular
axiomatic approach, as found, say, in Robert Nozick's writing. I am
critical of closed axiomatic systems, but on grounds other than those I
have expressed in my opening article. Readers should realize that this
is a subject that goes beyond our present task of criticizing the claim
of optimum allocation of resources. It is important to notice, however,
that any closed theoretical system that will not allow market theory to
meet the oncoming displacement and inequality will put the whole
classical liberal enterprise on a course to self-destruction.
Second, in endnote number fourteen, Block writes that the optimum
concept "is predicated upon the concept of Pareto efficiency: No
one can be made better off without at least one person being made worse
off." I agree that much economic literature does relate optimum to
Pareto efficiency. But the free-market, free-trade school that is so
influential in the world today, and that finds its best expression in
Mises and his followers, does not. Mises was fully aware of the fallacy
of what he called the Montaigne dogma (which, today, is often referred
to in connection with "a zero sum game"). He did not base his
ideas of consumer sovereignty and optimal allocation on the notion that
one person's gain is necessarily somebody else's loss, as
though there were a fixed pie. He argued eloquently against that
perspective as a crude fallacy.
Third, Block rightly devotes much attention to an effort to refute
my expectation that the onslaught of increasingly non-labor-intensive
technology will make the wage system untenable as a source of income for
perhaps billions of people. This is, after all, the ground for my
sensing a coming crisis for economic systems that depend on wage income
as the means by which most people participate in economic life. The two
premises that "human wants are without limit" and "if
prices and wages are left free to adjust, there will always be a demand
for everyone's services" are themselves central to current
thinking about a market economy, and seem to dispose of the possibility
of crisis. We do not need to quibble long over the unlimited nature of
wants: Even if at some point the great majority of people were to decide
that they do not want consumerism to be central to their lives, there
will still be vast tasks to be accomplished. So let us grant the
unlimited nature of wants. But the second premise, having to do with
wage adjustment providing full employment under all conditions, leaves a
lot to be desired. It provides a neat theoretical answer but makes no
comment upon how low those wages will be when non-labor-intensive
technology performs most menial tasks and billions of people (and here I
speak especially of the billions who lack the intelligence and aptitude
to master advanced skills) compete to earn a living by doing the few
tasks that remain. We can grant the theoretical "truth" of the
full-employment premise and nevertheless see the coming of a crisis of
any economic system centered upon income-from-wages.
Fourth, the previous point merges with a related notion. When Block
defends the inequalities that arise in a marketplace, he draws upon
classic free-market thinking: That the productivity of a market economy
will raise all boats, and that inequality, rather than being an evil, is
a hallmark of the freedom the market embodies. These premises have
certainly been true, and I have held to them myself. But in the context
of a radical new future, they take on a different character, and are
compounded of faith and myopia. How can we be confident that the
near-utopian technology will raise all boats, when the result of that
technology is that literally billions of people will be left to compete
to perform the few things that remain labor-intensive? (1) Now, with
respect to the second premise, have we forgotten that classical
liberalism was once, for good reason, the enemy of aristocracy and
hierarchical society? There are cultural prerequisites to a free society
that were once understood by classical liberals but have been lost sight
of under the narrower theoretical systems held to today. It is
predictable that vast inequality--even though market-originated--will
lead to a hardening of classes and a transformation away from the open
culture of a society that values individual freedom. We take the
"inequality is the hallmark of freedom" idea too far when we
make it an apologia for impending hierarchy.
I realize that I am looking farther ahead than most people want to
think. Right now, the premises I am criticizing continue to apply pretty
well, because, despite all the daily announcements of new scientific and
medical discoveries, we are just at the beginning of the new age. I do
not blame people for wanting to stay with those well-known premises,
since my concerns seem speculative and futuristic. But a new world is
coming upon us at a hitherto unheard-of pace, and I urge that those who
are not convinced keep their eyes and minds open.
One great potential difficulty will be that, armed with an
ideological support for inequality, classical liberals will not be able
to spot a disastrous situation when they see one. Historically speaking,
most societies, such as Brazil with its squalid urban slums, seem to
take any amount of inequality in stride. In doing so, they are not
adequately sensitive to the effects of social hierarchy upon the
institutions, principles, and way-of-life of a free society.
Nor are such societies sufficiently sensitive to the moral issues.
An inequality borne out of differences in ability, effort, character,
market discernment, and the like, is a morally justifiable inequality.
But, as Henry George pointed out a century ago, some wealth accrues to
individuals without any relationship either to merit or to a productive
meeting of consumers' needs. George made this point with regard to
the increase in land values that comes from increasing population near
the land. During the past century, most classical liberals, including
myself until recently, have not become followers of George (who was in
all other ways a devout free-market thinker) because it has seemed
better to let the market work without qualification than to make an
admission that Socialists could use to their own advantage. Now,
however, with the rapid advance of computerization, robotics, materials
sciences, and biotechnology, Henry George's observation becomes
even more pertinent. Those in the year 2030, for example, who make a
fortune as computer experts will make only a part of that income from
their own effort; instead, they will have inherited from the
civilization in which they live the work of countless geniuses who will
have preceded them, and much of their income will be due to those
previous successes. How appropriate will it be then to say that
"any amount of inequality is all right, because it arises out of
the successful peoples' success in the market"? Will future
classical liberals be able to say that with a clear conscience if
billions of people are faring quite badly?
And why will those billions be faring badly? Will it be because of
their own inertia, laziness, or lack of effort? Perhaps with some it
will be; but with vast numbers it will be despite every desire to work
hard and to participate in the economic system.
What is at issue more than anything else is the methodology by
which classical liberals reason about a free society. Do they see
society as a whole and seek ways to accomplish individual freedom,
limited government, and the fulfillment of advanced civilization? This
can be called a systems theory of a free society. Or do they settle upon
a few axioms or insights and deduce from them a complete system that is
so fully explanatory that they allow no new axioms or insights to enter?
This is a closed or self-contained system, which is the sort of thing
ideologues love so well. The trouble with it is, however, that no axioms
can include everything that human beings need in an advanced and free
society. "There is more in heaven and earth, Horatio, than is
dreamt of in your philosophy."
This is not to say that we should not use a principled approach,
both with regard to understanding and to behavior. There is great value,
even intellectual necessity, in principles. This is largely negated,
however, if they congeal into closed systems that "explain
everything" and admit of no new facts or further considerations.
Fifth, Block ends by suggesting--all within the bounds of the
civility that both our friendship and fruitful intellectual discussion
require--that I am "flirting with socialism." Indeed, I am, at
least as to one important feature of socialism. Let us be clear about
that. Several years ago, I wrote an essay for The Freeman pointing out
how fraudulent it was for Louis Kelso to claim to be advancing
capitalism while he advocated what was clearly socialism. I want no part
of such a fraud. What I favor for the future is a non-market
distribution of property (shares in the economy by way of shares in
index mutual funds) to everybody in a given society, whether they have
done anything to "earn" them or not. Being non-market, and
involving, in part, compulsion through taxation, we can easily identify
it, by itself, as a Socialist means. What I am saying is that it will be
a necessary means if we are to keep both the global and local market
economy going, are to prevent revolution that can destroy everything we
value, and are to formulate a theory (and practice) of a free society
based both upon sound thinking and a tenable moral foundation. In this,
I think I am on sounder ground precisely as a classical liberal than
those who would label me a Socialist. Time and events will tell who is
right.
Concern over the future of society in an age of computers is new to
those of us on the right. When not long ago I wrote a book (which
remains unpublished) about all of this, I did not expect that many, if
any, of my friends would start by agreeing with me. I suspect that more
and more will come to agree as time goes on.
Sixth, Block takes issue with my prediction of "catastrophe in
the less-developed economies." He argues rightly that the plight of
people living in the Third World stems from excessive government
(although we should add innumerable cultural and ideational factors that
join in holding them down). What he misses is that I am looking ahead to
the future as a time when there will be virtually no demand for the
products of such societies' enormous pool of unskilled labor. That
will not itself be a product of too much government.
Seventh, as I have discussed these subjects with well-read
conservatives and libertarians, they have joined Block in knocking
Jeremy Rifkin as both a Socialist and a Luddite. I have no reason to
defend Rifkin in general (he can very well do that for himself); it is
enough for me to say that his books The End of Work and The Biotech
Century are among the more provocative and insightful in recent memory.
My attitude is that it is time for thinkers who are not Socialist and
who have no anti-technology tendencies to begin considering the
impending future seriously. Nothing very meaningful can be said about
the world today without a reasoned futurism.
Conclusion
Certainly my own views should not be confused with a Luddite
rejection of technology (and I do not suggest that Block pins that on
me). I see the new technologies as offering incredible hope. Humanity
would be extremely foolish to block these new technologies and the
productivity they portend. We will only realize those benefits, however,
if we address appropriately the social problems that will arise
concomitantly with those technologies. By "appropriately," I
mean in ways that are consistent with a free and advanced society.
Let me conclude by thanking the Journal of Markets & Morality
for making its pages available to a very serious discussion, and by
thanking Walter Block for being my partner in this exchange.
Notes
(1.) At one point, Block observes how it would have seemed at the
beginning of the Industrial Revolution that all work would soon be
displaced; and from this he infers that my concern over displacement and
inequality resulting from today's new technology are equally
unrealistic. Let us consider that proposition. Following the Industrial
Revolution, people migrated from farming into industrial pursuits, so
that, as Block rightly points out, only two percent of Americans are
engaged in agriculture. In the twentieth century, people have migrated
out of industrial work and into service industries. According to
Block's expectation, service work can continue to occupy unlimited
numbers, serving as a permanent sop. Now, however, we see that great
fields of service work are becoming non-labor-intensive, as virtually
all "middle-men" professions are beginning to be displaced by
"disintermediation" (i.e., consumers are beginning to go
directly to providers through the Internet and otherwise, cutting out
stock brokers, real estate agents, retail clerks, wholesalers, college
professors, and countless others). With voice-recognition computers and
robotic lawn-mowers (just announced the same day this is written), the
new technology offers to require little, if any, human effort. Even in
the skilled areas, the technology is becoming increasingly
user-friendly, so that less and less skill is being needed for it. All
of this is a process that is new to the economic equation, and all that
Block has to answer it with is an article of faith. Past experience has
borne out that faith. Will the new realities do the same?
Dwight D. Murphey
Professor of Business Law
Wichita State University