Controversy: is economics a moral science? A response to Ricardo F. Crespo.
Boettke, Peter J.
That political economy in its finest moments is a value-relevant
discipline can hardly be disputed. The question is whether knowledge
gleaned in the disciplines of economics and political economy can be
both value-relevant and value-neutral. Adam Smith holds a claim to our
intellectual attention to this day precisely because his work, as
Kenneth Boulding so aptly put it, is part of our "extended
present." (1) We need Smith, because Smith still speaks to us in an
enabling manner about basic issues of social organization. But
Smith's analysis of economic interdependence is something that
stands independent of our judgment of his vision of "the system of
natural liberty." Vision and analysis cannot be so neatly
compartmentalized, but they can nevertheless be usefully distinguished
from one another. (2)
The post-positivist critique of objective knowledge found in
writers such as Michael Polanyi, (3) Thomas Kuhn, (4) and Stephen
Toulmin (5) does not inevitably slide into the post-modernist critique
of scientific knowledge in general. There might be strong
epistemological arguments against the idea that scientific procedures
can produce a "mirror of nature," but that need not imply a
slip into epistemological relativism. Algorithms and methods do not
necessarily make for good science; good scientists make for good
science. (6) But beyond admonishments to behave morally, the task of
scientific discourse can be aided by certain argumentative steps. (7)
Despite the critique of modernist epistemology, there are, in other
words, pragmatic steps we can take in argumentation that improve the
chances for interpersonal assessment. These steps amount to accepting
the ends of one's intellectual adversary and restricting analysis
to an immanent critique of their system.
Crespo does not tackle the issue of whether economics is a moral
science by way of post-modernist philosophy, but instead through the
lens of Aristotelian philosophy. His basic claim is that economics as a
practical science must of necessity address the ends toward which
individuals strive. I do not have much problem with what is stated about
the Aristotelian stance, especially with regard to expecting from a
discipline only that "amount of precision which belongs to its
subject matter," and I do have many problems with positivistic notions of economic science as they have developed in this century. So,
why do I resist Crespo's formulation? Because I think in his
critique of economic analysis Crespo undermines precisely the most
important role that economics as a science can play in developing a
value-relevant political economy. Economics can provide us with as close
to value-neutral knowledge as we can hope to gain, and this knowledge,
in turn, provides the basis for our rational discussion of alternative
visions of the good.
The practice of political economy as a value-relevant discipline is
an interdisciplinary research program in politics, philosophy, and
economics. Hyper-specialization of the disciplines has pulled these
fields increasingly further apart, but for political economy to be
properly practiced these disciplines can neither be allowed to collapse
into one another through overzealous intellectual imperialism nor
completely separated in the vain quest for specialization. Instead, we
must respect each discipline for its unique contribution to human
knowledge, yet draw on the multi-disciplinary insights that reside in
the section of overlap--an overlap of questions, of data, of both the
object and subject of study in political economy. The unique
contribution that economics has to offer to this project is a style of
reasoning about means and ends, and a determination of the effectiveness
of selected means to obtaining selected ends.
I will raise four separate points to argue for the role of
economics as value-neutral. Before I proceed, however, I would like to
make a few qualifying statements. First, to say that economics can
provide value-neutral knowledge does not mean that any particular
economist can be value-neutral. We are human beings and in the very
nature of choosing we strive for various ends by employing available
means. This is as true for the scientist as it is for the stock-broker
or your parish priest. Value-judgments are part of our human condition
and there is no way to escape them, and either we admit to them or we
sneak them in through the backdoor. The best we can do is to either
openly debate and defend value-judgments, or find certain procedures in
our argumentative strategy that attempt to improve interpersonal
assessment of how we obtained our judgments. Second, when economists use
the term efficiency there is no necessary judgment involved in the term.
It could, in fact, be used as a term of value-judgment if we impart
normative weight to ends (such as wealth-maximizing), but there is no
necessary reason to take this step. All efficiency refers to is the
relationship between means chosen and desired ends. Both the sinner and
the saint want to be efficient in this sense. The criticism of
economics, that it tries to substitute efficiency as the ultimate moral
judgment, is, in this sense, simply misplaced. Efficiency, for example,
does not mean wealth-maximization. Of course, some economists (perhaps
many) may be guilty of misapplication, but economics need not be so
tarred.
I can grant many (perhaps most) of Crespo's arguments and
still hold out a pragmatic defense of value-neutral economics, for it is
only a value-neutral economics that enables economists and social
thinkers to practice a value-relevant political economy.
Radical Subjectivism
Modern economic theory stresses the subjective nature of
value-judgments by choosing individuals within social processes. It is
individuals that choose which ends to pursue with the means available to
them. As has been stressed by Israel Kirzner (8) (and before him by
Ludwig von Mises), it is precisely the radical subjectivism of economics
that assures that the discipline has any way to approximate
"objective knowledge." The content of ends is not the domain
of economics; the logical analysis of the effectiveness of selected
means to achieve given ends is the domain of economics. Economics cannot
determine, for example, whether profits are deserved. But what economics
can do is inform one of the consequences of various answers to that
question.
Thus, contra Crespo, the knowledge that economics provides can be
separated from ethical questions. Moreover, it is precisely because
economics can provide value-neutral knowledge of the logical
consequences of different ethical systems that is an essential input to
a value-relevant discipline of political economy. To put it another way,
if the choice is between utility and justice, then, of course, we can
agree that justice should trump. But, in the world, the choice is rarely
so clear-cut. Instead, we are usually confronted with a choice between
different concepts of justice, and when confronted with this choice,
utility trumps justice. (9) Knowledge of the consequences of alternative
social arrangements is vital to making the choice among those
arrangements. If we deny that this knowledge is obtainable in any manner
that allows for interpersonal assessment, then we deny from the moral
science of political economy the ability to adjudicate between different
conceptions of social organization. On the other hand, if we restrict
our analytical attention to the relationship between means and ends, and
thus treat ends as given, then we can obtain the necessary critical
information that eventually makes value-relevant statements move beyond
mere opinions reflecting the political and social preferences of the
analyst.
Ideology and the Devil's Test
The world is a rather tricky place, and utopia is not a viable
option. In fact, perhaps, the most important role that economics plays
is in providing negative knowledge. By examining the logic of means-ends
efficiency economics places parameters around people's utopias.
Wishing it so, in short, cannot make it so. To put it bluntly, chickens
do not fly into people's mouths. Scarce resources must be allocated
among competing ends in a way that minimizes waste by directing
resources to their most effective use in satisfying the demands of
others. Every day, however, policies are introduced that attempt to
direct resources in a manner different from what would have been chosen
voluntarily. (10) In some instances, these policies might improve upon
the situation, but in others the policy choice actually worsens the
situation. How can we establish this fact? If economics is a value-laden
discipline from the very beginning, does it not depend on the
perspective of the analyst whether a policy is deemed good or bad?
Again, the solution does not require an epistemological defense of
objectivity. All that is needed is the more humble defense of an
argumentative strategy that allows people to rationally discuss
alternative policies.
The analyst does not debate the ends but rather restricts the
analysis to the logic of means-ends. If the ends the advocate seeks are
undermined by the means chosen, then even the advocate would have to
admit that the chosen policy is inappropriate. That the analysis of
means-ends is independent of the ideological vision of the analyst can
be checked by what could be called the "devil test." (11) If
both an angel and the Devil could agree with the means-ends analysis,
then the analysis itself provides an independent or
"objective" ground upon which to debate.
In economics, mistakes are often made by analysts--even assuming
they employ solid economic logic--because the "holding other things
constant" clause is forgotten, or the magnitude of the consequence
is not dutifully noted. The minimum wage controversy, for example,
highlights the problem. Blanket statements like "Minimum Wage Laws
Cause Unemployment" claim too much. A proper statement must
establish the context of application. A minimum wage law set above the
market clearing wage rate will cause some disemployment effect. The
extent of the disemployment effect, and the manner in which that effect
will be felt depends on the extent of the deviation from the market
clearing wage, and the margin of decision for employers in adjusting to
the change in the legal wage rate. What can be established fairly
clearly is the tendency and direction of the effect. Wage rates set
above the market clearing level by law will result in disproportionately
harming lower wage workers--i.e., the least well-off workers. If the end
of the policy is to aid the least well-off, then the means chosen
(raising the legal wage rate that must be paid to employees) will be
ineffective for that task. If, on the other hand, the intended result
was to harm the least well-off (the Devil's work), then
establishing legal minimum wages would be an effective policy. Both the
angel and the Devil can agree with the analysis, but place different
weight on the normative use to which the analysis can be deployed. The
analysis itself, however, is value-neutral. To deny that would, I fear,
result in denying economic logic and as such would drain economics of
its critical edge.
Critical Appraisal and Policy Advocacy
There is a strict line that must be drawn between the critical
appraisal of alternative public policies and advocacy of any policy.
Critical appraisal can be "objective;" advocacy requires
value-judgments. If we advocate free-trade, then it is appropriate for
us to defend the "goodness" of free-trade and be explicit
about the ends we desire. On the other hand, if we are restricting our
analysis to the examination of proposed protectionist legislation, then
the economist can surely critically assess the effectiveness of the
proposed policy for achieving the ends (usually stated as improving the
economic health of the country). Of course, this means that if someone
were to argue that the majority of consumers should pay more for their
products to benefit a few producers and this is the goal toward which
the proposed protectionist legislation is aimed, then the economist as
economist has little to say. Most policy advocates, however, are not so
brazen in their disregard for the economic interests of consumers.
Moreover, by treating the desired ends, not as a subject of debate
but as given, and by restricting analysis to the relationship of the
selected means in obtaining the stated ends, the economic analyst can
provide "objective knowledge" or something approximating such
knowledge. Many policy disputes, and especially those debates that call
upon economics most urgently, are not about ends but about means to
obtain rather broad ends--"provide for the least advantage;"
"improve opportunities;" "social justice;"
"allow people to live peaceful and fruitful lives." The
examination of means to given ends can establish that policies generate
consequences that are perverse with regard to the ends sought--the least
well-off are disproportionally harmed; opportunities are restricted;
social inequities grow worse; and social conflict and poverty ensue. In
taking this critical stance with regard to the position of the advocate,
the knowledge provided by economic analysis enables us to explore the
limits and potential of political and social organization. Endorsing a
concept of the "good life" necessarily entails value-judgments
but the tool of weighing the different concepts of the good by examining
consequences need not entail any importation of values--except the value
that achieving what one sets out to accomplish is worthwhile.
Pre- and Post-Constitutional Levels of Analysis
James Buchanan has made the useful distinction in his work between
pre- and post-constitutional levels of analysis. (12) At the
pre-constitutional level, the discussion revolves around different
notions of what might constitute good rules of the game. At the
post-constitutional level, the rules are treated as given and the
question then becomes, which strategies players will play given the
established rules? Political economy consists of oscillating between the
pre- and post-constitutional levels of analysis. The rules of the game
determine the types of strategies that individuals will choose.
Choice among the rules is a normative enterprise, whereas choice of
strategies is not. The choice of strategy follows a simple formula--what
is the best play given the rules and the play of others. The choice
among rules, however, entails determining what is considered a good game
and whether a game is challenging yet fair, and so forth. The point I
want to stress for present purposes is that, in deciding on the rules,
it is also important to consider the consequences this has on the choice
of strategy. A game that has interesting rules in theory but is
undermined by opportunistic strategies is not a very robust game, no
matter how convinced we are of its righteousness. Thus, the ability to
engage in a positive analysis of the consequences of alternative rules
of the game on the way in which the game will be played is essential for
our ability to engage in a productive normative discourse about what
rules we should choose to live by.
Conclusion
Economics, as I said earlier, puts parameters on people's
utopias. But it also provides insight into what might be workable
utopias. Economics without history, politics, culture, and morality runs
the risk of becoming a barren technical enterprise. But political
economy, without a firm basis in logic and evidence, runs the risk of
being mere opinion and wishful thinking. The disciplines of economics
and political economy can be likened to engineering science and worldly
philosophy. The great minds of political economy--independent of
ideological perspective--have found a way to weave together both the
technical and the philosophical aspects of these disciplines without
becoming mutually exclusive of the other. Crespo's argument for
economics as a moral science correctly challenges economists who believe
that the "engineering aspects" of the discipline are enough to
provide advice on policies. His argument also challenges those who think
that economics as a discipline is best practiced in an ideological
vacuum. But I sense that the argument goes too far when he suggests that
economics cannot provide value-neutral knowledge. My contention is that
political economy as a value-relevant discipline has a legitimate claim
on our intellectual attention only to the degree that it is grounded in
the value-neutral logic of economic analysis--an analysis that while it
cannot determine ultimate values may nevertheless inform us of the
consequences of alternative social and political arrangements
established to serve those values.
Peter J. Boettke
Associate Professor of Economics
George Mason University
Notes
(1) "After Samuelson, Who Needs Adam Smith?" History of
Political Economy 3 (Fall 1971): 225-37.
(2) See Peter Boettke, "Analysis and Vision in Economic
Discourse," Journal of the History of Economic Thought 14 (Spring
1992): 84-95.
(3) Personal Knowledge (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1958).
(4) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1962).
(5) The Uses of Argument (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1958); and Human Understanding (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1972).
(6) See D. N. McCloskey, The Rhetoric of Economics (Madison:
University of Wisconsin Press, 1985), 37.
(7) Peter Boettke, "Why Are There No Austrian
Socialists?" Journal of the History of Economic Thought 17 (Spring
1995): 35-56.
(8) "Value Freedom," in Elgar Companion to Austrian
Economics, ed. Peter Boettke (Aldershot, UK: Edward Elgar Publishing,
1994): 313-19.
(9) I owe this formulation of the problem to David Schmidtz.
(10) Of course, the introduction of terms like voluntary and
coercion introduce moral distinctions into the language of economic
analysis. I do not want to object to this aspect of Crespo's
argument, nor to the theory-laden aspect of all social thought. However,
I believe that by taking a pragmatic turn in our defense of
value-neutrality we follow certain argumentative procedures that advance
our ability to understand the limits and potential of social
organization. If we deny that the economic way of thinking can make this
step, then we must waive the knowledge that economics can provide in our
attempt to advance the moral science of political economy.
(11) I owe this terminology to Fr. James Sadowsky.
(12) "The Constitution of Economic Policy," American
Economic Review 77 (June 1987): 748-50.