Giving in dictator games: regard for others or regard by others?
Koch, Alexander K. ; Normann, Hans-Theo
1. Introduction
Experimental studies have challenged the notion that human behavior
can be well approximated with models assuming narrow self-interest.
Strong evidence for other-regarding behavior comes from dictator game experiments (Kahneman, Knetsch, and Thaler 1986; Forsythe et al. 1994).
One player (dictator) decides how to allocate an amount of money between
himself and a passive player (receiver). Narrow self-interest would call
for the dictator to keep the entire amount, leaving the receiver with
nothing. Forsythe et al. (1994) find that 70% of the dictators actually
do not grab the entire pie for themselves, leaving the receiver with on
average 24% of the total amount. Similar patterns have been documented
in many different dictator game settings (see, e.g., the survey of
Camerer 2003).
But what is the source of seemingly altruistic behavior? The two
fundamental views on this ancient question are pitted against each other
in Plato's (360 BC) Republic. Glaucon claims that "[...] a man
is just, not willingly or because he thinks that justice is any good to
him individually, but of necessity, for whenever any one thinks that he
can safely be unjust, there he is unjust." He illustrates this with
the tale of the shepherd Gyges, who finds a ring that enables him to
become invisible and act unjustly without anybody ever knowing. His
brother Adeimantus concurs, saying that otherwise "[...] we should
not have been on the watch to keep one another from doing wrong, but
every one would have been his own watchman" (Book II). In contrast,
Socrates claims that an individual who acts just for its own sake rather
than for its appearance is truly serving his own interest, justice being
concerned "[...] not with the ontward man, but with the inward [...]" (Book IV).
This paper looks into whether external forces--concerns for the
"outward man"--are needed to motivate dictator giving or
whether internal mechanisms--concerns for the "inward
man"--underly such behavior. It has been argued that giving in dictator games might arise from a desire of subjects to appear to be
acting in a socially appropriate way because their individual behavior
is observed by others. Hoffman et al. (1994, p. 349) suggest that
"fairness" may not be "'own' preference, but a
derivative of judgement by others." Because subjects' behavior
might also be influenced by expectations about the experimenter's
judgement. Hoffman et al. (1994), and Hoffman, McCabe, and Smith (1996)
run a double-blind treatment (DB1) to ensure that the experimenter
cannot personally attribute subjects' decisions. Incidence of
positive offers (36% of dictators) and average donations (9.2% of pie)
drop significantly relative to Forsythe et al. (1994). This vindicates
Glaucon and Adeimantus' view that external enforcement of norms is
important. Reducing observability of actions along the dimension of
increasing anonymity leads to less seemingly other-regarding behavior.
(1)
Nevertheless, 36% of the dictators in the DB1 experiment still
donate some money (mean gift 25% of the pie). Does this imply that these
subjects have pure other-regarding preferences? Hoffman et al. (1994, p.
371) argue that the DB1 results "may approach the appropriate
indicator of fairness as a pure preference phenomenon." However,
there is another dimension of observability. Giving by a dictator might
not be driven by true regard for the receiver's welfare but rather
stem from a desire to avoid that the receiver discovers the deed of
violating a social norm (rather than the perpetrator as an identifiable
individual). Then, even in completely anonymous settings, regard by
others would still serve as an external enforcement device of norms.
Recent bargaining experiments provide some evidence that an
important driving force in seemingly altruistic behavior is whether or
not the responder can observe a proposer's action. Introducing an
information asymmetry about the pie size to be divided by the proposer,
the typical finding is that subjects are concerned about being perceived
by others as abiding by social norms (even under intersubject anonymity)
but otherwise exploit their informational advantage in a selfish way.
(2) Guth, Huck, and Ockenfels (1996, p. 597) conclude that
"complying--at least superficially--with a (fairness) norm has some
intriusic value: you feel better when others do not know how greedy you
are."
Dana, Cain, and Dawes (2006) investigate the dimension of receiver
knowledge in a dictator game setting without introducing experimenter
anonymity. After dictators have made their allocation decision they are
given an exit option. If the option is chosen, the dictator gets $9 and
the receiver gets nothing but remains ignorant of the game. If the exit
option is not chosen, the receiver gets his part of the $10 pie, along
with the dictator's instructions (treatment 1) or without becoming
aware of the game (treatment 2). The pre-exit option pattern in
treatment 1 replicates the Forsythe et al. (1994) results: 70% of
dictators offer more than nothing, receivers get 25% of the pie on
average. The exit option is chosen by 33% of subjects, bringing down the
incidence of positive dictator offers actually carried out to 43%
(receivers in the experiment get 15% of the pie on average). This is
close to the levels in the Hoffman et al. (1994), and Hoffman, McCabe,
and Smith (1996) double-blind treatment (DB1) experiment (36% positive
offers, the average receiver share is 9.2% of the pie).
In sum, eliminating only one of the two dimensions of external
enforcement of norms, regard by the receivers (Dana, Cain, and Dawes
2006) or regard by the experimenter (the Hoffman et al. [1994], and
Hoffman, McCabe, and Smith [1996] double-blind procedure), appears to
affect subject behavior to a similar extent. Our contribution is to test
for the importance of receiver knowledge in the absence of the second
dimension of external enforcement of norms. The experiment therefore
eliminates reputational and other strategic considerations with a design
that guarantees experimenter anonymity and precludes any possibility of
future interaction between dictators and receivers. Paraphrasing
Adeimantus, we ask to what extent individuals are effective in policing
themselves in completely anonymous situations. Or put differently, does
it matter for an individual in a completely anonymous setting that those
affected by his or her actions are able to assess whether these actions
conform to established social norms or not?
The treatments vary the information that receivers have. The A ware Receiver (AR) treatment provides receivers with the dictator game
instructions. Common knowledge of the game enables receivers to become
aware of being treated kindly or unkindly by the dictators. Such
knowledge by receivers is crucial for external enforcement to be
effective. In contrast, it is irrelevant for dictator behavior if pure
other-regarding preferences (or any other internal mechanisms) are at
work. Therefore, we compare behavior with that in the Unaware Receiver
(UR) treatment, which provides no information to receivers about the
source of dictator offers. In fact, receivers do not even know that they
participate in an experiment. In all treatments, we control for
experimenter anonymity by implementing the Hoffman et al. (1994), and
Hoffman, McCabe, and Smith (1996) procedure. To remove any possibility
for future interaction between dictators and receivers, receivers are
randomly selected from UK phone directories to receive the
dictators' offers via mail.
Related to our experiment is a study of social distance in dictator
games by Johannesson and Persson (2000). They compare a standard Hoffman
et al. (1994, 1996) double-blind treatment, in which both dictators and
receivers are students, with one in which the receivers are randomly
drawn from the Swedish population. In this latter treatment,
dictators' offers are mailed out together with the instructions.
Johannesson and Persson (2000) find no significant differences between
their treatments. In contrast to our study, receivers always receive the
instructions together with the dictators' offers--unless the offer
is zero (in which case, in their experiment, nothing is mailed out).
Moreover, dictators choose from a different set of possible allocations.
(3)
2. Experimental Design and Procedures
All experimental treatments follow the standard Hoffman et al.
(1994), and Hoffman, McCabe, and Smith (1996) procedure to guarantee
experimenter anonymity, and instructions are kept as close as possible
to the original ones (see Appendix). In the AR treatment, each receiver
gets the instructions for the experiment along with the dictator's
offer. This corresponds to the standard dictator game setting and serves
as a control treatment. In the UR treatment, each receiver gets only the
dictator's offer without any indication where it came from. The
receiver is even unaware of taking part in an experiment.
It is crucial for our experiment to exclude any possibility for
future interaction between dictator subjects and receivers and thereby
guarantee that the differential information treatments are credible.
Therefore, instead of using laboratory subjects, receivers are randomly
selected from UK phone directories to get by post an envelope containing
the dictator's offer.
Each session has 15 subjects who receive a show-up fee of 5 [pounds
sterling] upon arrival and take a seat in separate cubicles in the
experimental lab, where a set of instructions is provided. Subjects are
asked to remain quiet during the session, instructions are read out
loud, and any questions are answered. Then subjects draw a ballot to
determine the monitor, who verifies that the instructions are carried
out to the letter and receives an additional 10 [pounds sterling] for
this. (4) The monitor randomly distributes 14 unmarked envelopes and
retires to the back of the lab with the experimenters. Twelve envelopes
contain ten 1 [pounds sterling] coins and ten metal discs of
corresponding size and weight, two envelopes contain only 20 metal
discs. (5) Subjects tear open these envelopes and then decide how much
money to place in the return envelope provided in their cubicle. They
are instructed to return a total of 10 coins/metal discs, seal the
envelope, and place the remaining 10 coins/discs in an identical
envelope marked "Take this envelope with you." (6) Subjects
leave in an order that guarantees each individual privacy for his or her
decision. When leaving, subjects place the return envelope in a box next
to the exit and take the other envelope with them. After all subjects
leave, the monitor opens the return envelopes, records their contents,
removes the discs, and places only the coins returned (if any) in a
preaddressed envelope. Finally, the monitor and experimenter go to the
nearest mailbox and post the 14 letters.
The 14 receivers in the UR treatment are unaware of being part of
an experiment and do not know that some other person decided to allocate
from a total of 10 [pounds sterling] to him or her the amount found in
the envelope. In contrast, in the AR treatment, receivers become aware
of the fact that somebody else has decided to be kind to them or has
acted selfishly. Therefore, if dictator giving is (partially) motivated by external enforcement of social norms, there should be a higher
fraction of people giving money and a higher average share of the pie
for receivers under the AR treatment than under the UR treatment.
Otherwise, if dictator giving is purely driven by internal mechanisms,
there should be no behavioral differences between the AR and UR
treatments.
All experiments were conducted in the Experimental Lab of Royal
Holloway College, University of London, in March and May 2005. We ran
three sessions for each treatment to generate 36 independent dictator
observations per treatment (since in each session, two dictator subjects
received no money to distribute), recruiting subjects from all
discipline areas of the university (of the 42 nonmonitor subjects, eight
in AR and six in UR had economics majors or minors, respectively).
[FIGURE 1 OMITTED]
3. Results
In the AR treatment, the number of people who kept the entire
endowment was 21 (58%), and receivers got 10.3% of the pie on average.
In the UR treatment, the number of people who kept the entire endowment
was 23 (64%), and the average share for the receivers was 9.4%. These
results are virtually identical and a chi-square test, on the basis of
the proportion of people who give zero and the proportion of people who
give a positive amount, unsurprisingly, yields no significant
differences between treatments ([chi square] = 0.23, d.f. = 1, p >
0.5).
Figure 1 shows the cumulative distribution of dictators'
choices. Again, AR and UR are rather similar and a Kolmogorov-Smirnov
test finds no significant differences between distributions (Z = 0.281,
p = 0.86). These results reject the hypothesis that external enforcement
matters.
Figure 1 also reveals that there are no obvious differences between
our treatments and the results in Hoffman et al. (1994), and Hoffman,
McCabe, and Smith (1996). In DB1, 23 subjects (64%) kept the whole money
endowment and 9.2% was given to receivers on average. Both of our
treatments are very similar to these results, and differences are not
statistically significant. We conclude for the control treatment part of
the experiment that our AR double-blind procedure replicates the DB1
results and therefore is also consistent with Johannesson and
Persson's (2000) results.
The result that the UR and AR treatments do not differ provides
evidence that social norms can be effectively sustained by internal
mechanisms. More than one third of the dictators gave positive amounts,
and these subjects offered 25% of the pie on average. Moreover, in the
UR treatment, three of the 36 subjects gave 40% or 50% of their
endowment. This replicates both the Hoffman et al. (1994), and Hoffman,
McCabe, and Smith (1996) DB1 (3/36) treatments and our AR (4/36)
treatments. Because this frequency does not change across our
treatments, it suggests that such dictators might have truly
other-regarding preferences. Suppose subjects felt that fairness norms
call for dictators to give 50%. In the AR treatment, receivers can
immediately verify compliance with such a norm. In contrast, in the UR
treatment, receivers are completely unaware of the pie size and thus
have no obvious reference point against which to judge the offer. Hence,
an external motivation for not violating this norm has no bite. If
dictators still give half of the endowment, we can presume that this
decision is consistent with their true preferences.
We finally discuss whether our procedures might have biased the
results. We kept very closely to the Hoffman et al. (1994), and Hoffman,
McCabe, and Smith (1996) design and instructions. In our experiments,
there was no evidence that dictators gave money as a result of an error.
Typically, no questions were asked, and even fine points in the
instructions appeared to have been understood by all. For example,
without exception, subjects returned a total of 10 coins/metal discs in
their envelope, as instructed. Moreover, we took extreme care in
avoiding credibility of design issues (Frohlich, Oppenheimer, and Moore
2001) by selecting the monitor publicly (see footnote 4) and ensuring
complete privacy of decisions through the use of separated cubicles and
padded envelopes. A caveat, however, is the possibility of a residual
influence on dictator behavior in the UR treatment because the anonymous
offers are observed by the monitor and the experimenter. (7)
4. Discussion and Conclusion
Recent experiments on dictator and ultimatum games have
demonstrated a substantial effect of anonymity and incomplete
information on subjects' behavior. This has rekindled the question
of whether we follow social norms because we truly care for others or
because we are worried about the regard by others.
The experiment reported in this paper addresses the issue of
whether giving in completely anonymous dictator games is internally
motivated or whether external pressure helps enforce social norms. To
this end, we remove a crucial element of observability of the
dictators' actions; receivers do not learn about the experimental
instructions and, in fact, do not even know they participate in an
experiment. Moreover, we guarantee credibility of the one-shot nature of
the game and the informational treatments by eliminating, through an
anonymous mail-out scheme, any possibility for future interaction
between dictators and receivers.
In both treatments, roughly one third of the dictator subjects give
positive amounts, leaving the receivers with around 10% of the pie (as
in the Hoffman et al. [1994], and Hoffman, McCabe, and Smith [1996] DB1
experiment). Once complete anonymity is assured, it does not matter for
dictator behavior whether receivers are aware of being treated kindly or
unkindly.
This puts into perspective recent bargaining experiments, which
show that subjects tend to exploit information asymmetries to engage in
more selfish behavior when this does not become apparent to other
subjects. The fact that information about the game provided to receivers
has no impact in our completely anonymous setting suggests that those
dictators who give are not driven by external pressure but are
internally motivated to do so. These internal mechanisms include pure
regard for others (as stipulated in models of other-regarding
preferences), a warm glow of decision making (Andreoni 1989), a desire
to maintain a positive self impression (Murnighan, Oesch, and Pillutla
2001), or a desire to avoid feelings of guilt. The latter point has been
succinctly framed by Kandel and Lazear (1992, p. 806) in the context of
sustaining work norms via peer pressure: (8) "Guilt is internal
pressure, whereas shame is external pressure. In the context of the
firm, the important issue is observability. A worker feels shame when
others can observe his actions. Without observability, only guilt can be
an effective form of pressure."
Our experimental results suggest that perceptions by receivers in a
dictator game do not matter when there is complete anonymity. This
complements the experiments by Hoffman et al. (1994), and Hoffman,
McCabe, and Smith (1996), and Dana, Cain, and Dawes (2006), who show
that eliminating only one of the two dimensions of external enforcement
of norms, regard by the receivers or regard by the experimenter, reduces
the incidence of dictator giving by roughly half. Overall, these
experiments and our results suggest that about half of dictator giving
observed in standard experiments with exogenously given pie size (9) is
internally motivated, and the other half is driven by external factors
such as experimenter observability or regard by receivers.
From this we conclude that social behavior can be partially
explained by models based on preferences that are purely internal (as
captured, e.g., by other-regarding preferences). However, a significant
part of such behavior appears to be driven by the influence of external
enforcement of social norms. This underscores the importance of recent
theoretical work on modeling games in which players' utilities
depend on the beliefs held by others in the form of "psychological
payoffs" (e.g., Geanakoplos, Pearce, and Stacchetti 1989;
Battigalli and Dufwenberg 2005; Dillenberger and Sadowski 2006).
Appendix: Instructions
You have been asked to participate in an economics experiment. For
your participation today we have paid you 5 [pounds sterling] in cash.
You may earn an additional amount of money in cash.
We ask you to remain silent during the entire experiment; if you
have any questions, please raise your hand.
In this experiment each of you will be paired with a person whose
address was randomly selected from the BT phone directories for the UK.
You will not be told who that person is either during or after the
experiment, and he or she will not be told who you are.
You will notice that there are other people in the same room with
you who are also participating in this experiment. You will not be
paired with any of these people.
One of the persons in this room will be chosen to be the monitor
for today's experiment. The monitor will be paid 10 [pounds
sterling] in addition to the 5 [pounds sterling] already paid. The
monitor will be in charge of the envelopes explained below. In addition,
the monitor will verify that the instructions have been followed as they
appear here.
The experiment is conducted as follows: Fourteen unmarked envelopes
have been placed in a box. Twelve of these envelopes contain 10 1
[pounds sterling] pound coins and 10 metal discs. The remaining two
envelopes contain 20 metal discs. The monitor will hand each person in
the room one of these sealed filled envelopes. The person will then open
the envelope privately inside the cubicle. Only the person who was given
the envelope will know what the envelope contains.
Each person in this room will find inside the cubicle two empty
padded envelopes, one of which is unmarked and the other is marked
"Take this envelope with you." Each person must decide how
many coins (if any) and how many discs to put into the unmarked padded
envelope. The number of coins plus the number of discs must add up to
10. The person then puts the remaining coins and discs into the envelope
marked "Take this envelope with you."
Examples:
1. Put 2 [pounds sterling] and 8 discs into the unmarked padded
envelope, put the remaining 8 [pounds sterling] and 2 discs into the
other padded envelope.
2. Put 9 [pounds sterling] and 1 disc into the unmarked padded
envelope, put the remaining 1 [pounds sterling] and 9 discs into the
other padded envelope.
These are examples only, the actual decision is up to each person.
If the envelope handed out by the monitor has 20 discs, put l0
discs into the unmarked padded envelope and the other 10 into the other
padded envelope.
This is done in private and we ask that you tell no one of your
decision. Notice that each unmarked padded envelope returned will look
exactly the same. Also note that no one else, including the
experimenter, will know the personal decisions of the people in this
room.
Once you have made your decision you will seal your unmarked padded
envelope. When called upon, leave the cubicle, place it in the box
marked "return envelopes" and then leave the room taking along
with you the envelope marked "Take this envelope with you."
After all 14 unmarked padded envelopes have been returned, the
monitor will be given another box. This box is marked
"addresses" and contains 14 envelopes with a stamp. Each of
these envelopes has the address of a person randomly selected from the
BT phone directories for the UK. This person does not know anything
about the experiment. In fact, this person does not even know that he or
she is participating in an experiment. He or she will simply receive the
envelope without any explanation and without any indication where the
envelope comes from. The person will be sent a copy of these
instructions but no further explanation. [AR treatment] There will be no
return address and your identity will remain anonymous.
The monitor will then choose one envelope from the box with
"return envelopes" and record its content. The monitor will
put the money from this envelope into the envelope from the box
"addresses" and seal it. Each addressed envelope will contain
only the amount of money found in the return envelope (that is, 0
[pounds sterling] to 10 [pounds sterling]), without any explanation [UR
treatment] and a copy of these instructions [AR treatment]. The monitor
will continue until all the envelopes have been opened. The monitor will
then take the 14 sealed envelopes and together with the experimenter, go
to the closest mailbox and mail the envelopes. The experiment is then
over.
For today's experiment, you will not have to sign a receipt
for the money you received.
We thank Dirk Engelmann, Armin Falk, Ernst Fehr, Uri Gneezy and two
anonymous referees for comments.
Received February 2007; accepted May 2007.
References
Andreoni, James. 1989. Giving with impure altruism: Applications to
charity and Ricardian equivalence. Journal of Political Economy
97:1447-58.
Battigalli, Pierpaolo, and Martin Dufwenberg. 2005. Dynamic
psychological games. Bocconi University IGIER Working Paper No. 287.
Berg, Joyce, John Dickhaut, and Kevin McCabe. 1995. Trust,
reciprocity, and social history. Games and Economic Behavior 10:122-42.
Bohnet, Iris, and Bruno S. Frey. 1999a. Social distance and
other-regarding behavior in dictator games: Comment. American Economic
Review 89:335-9.
Bohnet, Iris, and Bruno S. Frey. 1999b. The sound of silence in
prisoner's dilemma and dictator games. Journal of Economic Behavior
and Organization 38:43-57.
Bolton, Gary E., Rami Zwick, and Elena Katok. 1998. Dictator game
giving: Rules of fairness versus acts of kindness. International Journal
of Game Theory 27:269-99.
Burnham, Terence C. 2003. Engineering altruism: A theoretical and
experimental investigation of anonymity and gift giving. Journal of
Economic Behavior and Organization 50:133-44.
Camerer, Colin F. 2003. Behavioral Game Theory." Experiments
in Strategic Interaction. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Cason, Timothy N., and Vai-Lam Mui. 1997. A laboratory study of
group polarization in the team dictator game. Economic Journal
107:1465-83.
Cason, Timothy N., and Vai-Lam Mui. 1998. Social influence in the
sequential dictator game. Journal of Mathematical Psychology 42:248-65.
Cherry, Todd L., Peter Frykblom, and Jason F. Shogren. 2002.
Hardnose the dictator. American Economic Review 92:1218-21.
Croson, Rachel T. A. 1996. Information in ultimatum games. Journal
of Economic Behavior and Organization 30:192-211.
Dana, Jason, Daylian Cain, and Robyn Dawes. 2006. What you
don't know won't hurt me: Costly (but quiet) exit in a
dictator game. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes
100:193-201.
Dillenberger, David, and Philipp Sadowski. 2006. Ashamed to be
selfish. Unpublished paper, Princeton University.
Eckel, Catherine C., and Philip J. Grossman. 1996. Altruism in
anonymous dictator games. Games and Economic Behavior 16:181-91.
Engelmann, Dirk, and Urs Fischbacher. 2003. Indirect reciprocity
and strategic reputation building in an experimental helping game.
CERGE-EI working paper No. 215.
Forsythe, Robert, Joel L. Horowitz, N. E. Savin, and Martin Sefton.
1994. Fairness in simple bargaining experiments. Games and Economic
Behavior 6:347-69.
Frohlich, Norman, Joe Oppenheimer, and J. Bernard Moore. 2001. Some
doubts about measuring self-interest using dictator experiments: The
costs of anonymity. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization
46:271-90.
Geanakoplos, John, David Pearce, and Ennio Stacchetti. 1989.
Psychological games and sequential rationality. Games and Economic
Behavior 1:60-79.
Gehm, Theodore L., and Klaus R. Scherer. 1988. Relating situation
evaluation to emotion differentiation: Nonmetric analysis of
cross-cultural questionnaire data. In Facets of Emotion." Recent
Research, edited by Klaus R. Scherer. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbanm, pp. 61-77.
Guth, Werner, and Steffen Huck. 1997. From ultimatum bargaining to
dictatorship--An experimental study of four games varying in the degree
of veto power. Metroeconomica 48:262-79.
Guth, Werner, Steffen Huck, and Peter Ockenfels. 1996. Two-level
ultimatum bargaining with incomplete information: An experimental study.
Economic Journal 106:593-604.
Haley, Kevin J., and Daniel M. T. Fessler. 2005. Nobody's
watching? Subtle cues affect generosity in an anonymous economic game.
Evolution and Human Behavior 26:245-56.
Harbaugh, William T. 1998. The prestige motive for making
charitable transfers. American Economic Review 88:277-82.
Hoffman, Elizabeth, Kevin McCabe, and Vernon L. Smith. 1996. Social
distance and other regarding behavior in dictator games. American
Economic Review 86:653-60.
Hoffman, Elizabeth, Kevin McCabe, Keith Shachat, and Vernon Smith.
1994. Preferences, property rights, and anonymity in bargaining games.
Games and Economic Behavior 7:346-80.
Johannesson, Magnus, and Bjorn Persson. 2000. Non-reciprocal
altruism in dictator games. Economics Letters 69:137-42.
Kagel, John H., Chung Kim, and Donald Moser. 1996. Fairness in
ultimatum games with asymmetric information and asymmetric payoffs.
Games and Economic Behavior 13:100-10.
Kahneman, Daniel, Jack L. Knetsch, and Richard H. Thaler. 1986.
Fairness and the assumptions of economics. Journal of Business
59:S285-S300.
Kandel, Eugene, and Edward P. Lazear. 1992. Peer pressure and
partnerships. Journal of Political Economy 100:801-17.
Kritikos, Alexander, and Friedel Bolle. 2002. Utility versus
income-based altruism--In favor of Gary Becker. EuropaUniversitat
Viadrina Discussion Paper No. 180.
Lewis, Helen Block. 1971. Shame and guilt in neurosis. New York:
International Universities Press.
Mitzkewitz, Michael, and Rosemarie Nagel. 1993. Experimental
results on ultimatum games with incomplete information. International
Journal of Game Theory 22:171-98.
Murnighan, J. Keith, John M. Oesch, and Madan Pillutla. 2001.
Player types and self-impression management in dictatorship games: Two
experiments. Games and Economic Behavior 37:388-414.
Oxoby, Robert J., and John Spraggon. 2008. Mine and yours: Property
rights in dictator games. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization
65:703-13.
Pillutla, Madan M., and J. Keith Murnighan. 1995. Being fair or
appearing fair: Strategic behavior in ultimatum bargaining. Academy of
Management Journal 38:1408-26.
Plato. 360 BC. Republic. Translated by Benjamin Jowett. 1901. New
York: P. F. Collier & Son.
Rapoport, Amnon, and James A. Sundali. 1996. Ultimatums in
two-person bargaining with one-sided uncertainty: Offer games.
International Journal of Game Theory 25:475-94.
Rapoport, Amnon, James A. Sundali, and Darryl A. Seale. 1996.
Ultimatums in two-person bargaining with one-sided uncertainty: Demand
games. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 30:173-96.
Ruffle, Bradley J. 1998. More is better, but fair is fair: Tipping
in dictator and ultimatum games. Games and Economic Behavior 23:247-65.
Straub, Paul G., and J. Keith Murnighan. 1995. An experimental
investigation of ultimatum games: Information, fairness, expectations,
and lowest acceptable offers. Journal of Economic Behavior and
Organization 27:345-64.
Tangney, June Price, and Ronda L. Dearing. 2002. Shame and guilt.
New York: Guilford Press.
(1) Dictator giving tends to increase when adding an additional
observer (Cason and Mui 1997, 1998) or visual cues in the form of
stylized eyes that suggest being observed (Haley and Fessler 2005) and
weakening anonymity across subjects (e.g., Bohnet and Frey 1999a, b;
Frohlich, Oppenheimer, and Moore 2001; Burnham 2003). Similarly,
information that the receiver is deserving of aid increases
dictators' offers (Eckel and Grossman 1996). However, Bolton,
Zwick, and Katok (1998) find no significant experimenter anonymity
effect.
(2) See Mitzkewitz and Nagel (1993); Pillutla and Murnighan (1995);
Straub and Murnighan (1995); Croson (1996); Guth, Huck, and Ockenfels
(1996); Kagel, Kim, and Moser (1996); Rapoport and Sundali (1996);
Rapoport, Sundali, and Seale (1996); Guth and Huck (1997); and Kritikos
and Bolle (2002). Further evidence against intrinsic benefits from
giving is that charities often receive donations just sufficient to
enter a publicized higher prestige donor category (Harbaugh 1998),
possibly because of concerns for direct or indirect reciprocity
(Engelmann and Fischbacher 2003).
(3) Dictators could choose to give 0, 20, 40, 60, 80, or 100
Swedish kroners, excluding the possibility of an equal split.
(4) We use such a ballot to convince subjects that we did not place
a stooge among them who is then selected as monitor.
(5) This guarantees that even if all subjects provided with coins
return no money, the individual subjects' decisions will not become
known (Hoffman et al. 1994; Hoffman, McCabe, and Smith 1996).
(6) Both envelopes are padded so that it is impossible to tell
apart by looking at them an envelope filled with 10 coins/discs even
from an unfilled one.
(7) To completely eliminate any possible external motivations, the
experimenter would have to discreetly observe an unaware dictator. This
presents an obstacle that cannot be overcome: Someone must enforce the
rules of the game, and that someone is always a source of regard by
others. We are grateful to an anonymous referee for pointing this out.
(8) These concepts of guilt and shame are borrowed from sociology
and have also been used by psychologists (e.g., Gehm and Scherer 1988,
p. 74). It should be noted though that they contrast with Lewis'
(1971) reconceptualization of these terms, which psychologists often
follow (e.g., Tanguey and Dearing 2002).
(9) An entitlement effect comes into play when adding
"earned" income to a dictator game setting. If the pie is
earned by own effort of the dictator, offers to receivers are typically
almost all zero (Cherry, Frykblom, and Shogren 2002; Oxoby and Spraggon
2008). If the pie is earned by the effort of the receiver and then
allocated by the dictator, the setting corresponds to a trust game
(Berg, Dickhaut, and McCabe 1995). Dictator giving then appears to be
driven by reciprocity: the bigger the pie, the bigger the proportion
allocated to the receiver--often more than half (Ruffle 1998; Oxoby and
Spraggon 2008).
Alexander K. Koch * and Hans-Theo Normann ([dagger])
* Royal Holloway, University of London, and IZA (Institute for the
Study of Labor), Royal Holloway College, University of London,
Department of Economics, Egham TW20 0EX, UK; E-mail
Alexander.Koch@rhul.ac.uk; corresponding author.
([dagger]) Royal Holloway College, University of London, Department
of Economics, Egham TW20 0EX, UK; E-mail Hans.Normann@rhul.ac.uk.