Dispute rates and contingency fees: an analysis from the signaling model.
Pecorino, Paul
1. Introduction
Contingency lee contracts, under which the plaintiff pays her
lawyer a percentage of the judgment if she wins at trial and nothing if
she loses, are very common in the United States but are banned or
severely restricted in many other countries. (1) Their use in the United
States generates great controversy, and while their use is restricted in
some states, further calls for restrictions on contingency fee contracts
are often heard. (2) Although contingency fee contracts are quite
simple, their effects on the litigation process are complex and wide
ranging. Previous studies have considered the effect of contingency fees
on the frequency of litigation (Danzon 1983: Miceli and Segerson 1991)
and nuisance suits (Miceli 1993, 1994) and on various aspects of the
lawyer-client relationship (Miller 1987: Dana and Spier 1993; Rubinfeld
and Scotchmer 1993; Watts 1994: Hay 1996, 1997). In this article, we
focus on the effects of contingency fees on the selection of disputes
for trial and the overall dispute rate in the signaling model of
Reinganum and Wilde (1986). (3) Along with Bebchuk (1984), this is one
of the two canonical models of pretrial settlement. In addition, since
the solution to a model with two-sided informational asymmetries has a
strong signaling element (Daughety and Reinganum 1994), it is
particularly important to understand how contingency fees affect dispute
rates in the signaling model.
As in the standard literature on pretrial settlement (e.g., Bebchuk
1984; Reinganum and Wilde 1986), we assume that the plaintiff controls
all aspects of the case. (4) In the Reinganum and Wilde model, an
informed plaintiff makes a take-it-or-leave-it offer to an uninformed
defendant who rejects these offers with some probability in equilibrium.
In order to conduct a complete analysis of the contingency fee in a
signaling model, we also consider the case in which an informed
defendant makes a single offer to the uninformed plaintiff.
Reinganum and Wilde first develop a signaling model in which the
plaintiff's lawyer is paid via a fixed fee and then go on to
present (pp. 562-3) a very general solution to the model in the presence
of a contingency contract. We use the general framework of Reinganum and
Wilde to focus on specific forms for the contingent lee contracts. Our
contribution lies not in the derivations of the model solutions, as
these follow from the Reinganum and Wilde framework rather closely.
Instead, our contribution lies in the analysis of how these specific
contingency fee contracts affect pretrial settlement patterns. We
analyze the effects both on overall dispute rates and on the selection
of disputes for litigation. In section 2, we will further note the
relationship between our work and the earlier analysis provided by
Reinganum and Wilde.
We examine two types of contracts in this article, a bifurcated contingency fee and a unitary contingency fee. Under a unitary contract,
the same contingency payment is made by the client to her lawyer
regardless of whether there is an out-of-court settlement or a victory
at trial. (5) Under a bifurcated fee, the contingency percentage at
trial is generally higher than the percentage for cases that settle. (6)
While unitary fees appear to be more common, a significant use of
bifurcated fees has been noted in the literature. (7) In a model with
attorney moral hazard, Hay (1997) notes that bifurcated fees are
generally optimal from the perspective of the plaintiff. On the other
hand, Bebchuk and Guzman (1996) argue that a unitary fee can lead to a
larger net settlement for the plaintiff. Since both types of contracts
appear to be relevant empirically, we examine both in this article.
One robust finding from our article is that unitary fees lead to an
unambiguous increase in the incidence of trial relative to both the
fixed fee contract and the bifurcated contingency fee contract. Since
the plaintiff's lawyer is paid the same percentage fee whether
there is a plaintiff victory at trial or a pretrial settlement, the
joint cost of proceeding to trial for the plaintiff and defendant is
lower under this unitary contingency tee. It is well known that under a
unitary fee, the lawyer has an excessive incentive to settle relative to
the interests of the client. (8) By contrast, when the client controls
the case, she has an excessive incentive to bring the case to trial.
Under a bifurcated contingency contract, our results depend on the
nature of the signaling model. In the model where an informed plaintiff
makes the offer, the use of the contingency fee contract has an
ambiguous effect on the overall incidence of trial but does have a clear
effect on the selection of disputes for litigation. The use of a
bifurcated contingency fee contract tilts the rejection function so that
more low-stakes cases proceed to trial compared with a fixed fee. In
addition, there may be some presumption that the use of the bifurcated
fee raises the overall incidence of trial. In the model where an
informed defendant makes the offer, we find that for reasonable
parameter values, the use of the bifurcated fee contract unambiguously
reduces the incidence of trial.
In our article, we treat the terms of the contract between the
plaintiff and her lawyer as exogenous and compare settlement rates
across different contracts. This type of comparison is valid in a policy
context, where there are proposals to ban contingency fee contracts.
Such a ban would (exogenously) force plaintiffs to switch to fixed fee
contracts. An even deeper understanding of the effects of the
contingency fee on settlement will ultimately require a model that
derives these contracts as the solution to an optimization problem while
embedding the analysis in a model of settlement. The analysis of these
and other aspects of the lawyer-client relationship are beyond the scope
of this article.
2. A Signaling Model with an Informed Plaintiff
We present the derivation of the model solutions for the
convenience of the reader, but it should be noted that these derivations
either exactly follow the Reinganum and Wilde analysis (the fixed fee
case), are special cases of their solutions (the bifurcated fee), or
could be derived in a relatively straightforward way from their analysis
(the unitary fee). Our contribution is to focus on specific forms of the
contingency fee contract and to analyze how these contracts affect
dispute rates.
The Fixed Fee
We start with the fixed fee analysis of Reinganum and Wilde. In
this model, the plaintiff has private information concerning the
damages, J. The defendant knows that J is distributed by f(J), where
[??] and [bar.J] are the lower and upper supports of this distribution.
The probability p that the plaintiff will prevail in trial is common
knowledge as are [C.sub.p] and [C.sub.D], the attorney fees of the
plaintiff and defendant, respectively. It is assumed that p[J.bar] >
[C.sub.P] so that all plaintiffs have a credible threat to proceed to
trial. The informed plaintiff makes a single take-it-or-leave-it offer
to the defendant. The model is summarized as follows:
(i') Nature determines the plaintiff's type J. The
defendant does not observe J but knows the distribution f(J) from which
it is drawn.
(ii') The plaintiff hires a lawyer under a contract in which
she pays [C.sub.P] if the case proceeds to trial and 0 if the case
settles prior to trial.
(iii') The plaintiff makes a single take-it-or-leave-it offer
[O.sub.P] to the defendant.
(iv') If the defendant accepts the offer, the plaintiff
receives a payoff of [O.sub.P], while the defendant receives -[O.sub.P].
If the defendant rejects the offer, the case proceeds to trial.
(v') At trial, there is a finding for the plaintiff with
probability p, in which case she receives the payoff J - [C.sub.P] while
the defendant receives the payoff -(J + [C.sub.D]). With probability 1 -
p, the finding is for the defendant; in this case, the plaintiff
receives the payoff -[C.sub.P], and the defendant receives the payoff
-[C.sub.D].
There are potentially many equilibria in this signaling game, but
Reinganum and Wilde use refinement arguments to eliminate all but a
separating equilibrium in which the plaintiff's offer is perfectly
revealing of her type and the defendant plays a mixed strategy under
which he rejects the offer [O.sub.P] with the probability
[phi]([O.sub.P]). (9) In equilibrium, the rejection function must be
such that optimizing plaintiffs reveal their type through their offer.
Given the rejection function [phi]([O.sub.P]), the plaintiff will make
an offer in order to maximize his expected wealth [V.sub.P], which can
be written
(1) [V.sub.P] = [phi]([O.sub.P])[[p.sub.J] - [C.sub.P]] + (1 -
[phi]([O.sub.P]))[O.sub.P].
Maximization of Equation 1 by the plaintiff yields the following
first-order condition:
(2) [phi]'([O.sub.P])[pJ - [C.sub.P] - [O.sub.P]] + (1 -
[phi]([O.sub.P])) = 0.
The function B([O.sub.P]) describes the defendant's beliefs
about plaintiff's type as a function of his offer to the defendant.
In a perfect Bayesian equilibrium, these beliefs must reflect the
equilibrium actions of the plaintiff. Thus, beliefs are correct in
equilibrium: B([O.sub.P](J)) = J. Since the defendant pursues a mixed
strategy in equilibrium, the plaintiff's offer must make him
indifferent between acceptance and rejection. The equilibrium offer by a
type J plaintiff equals the defendant's expected payoff at trial
against this plaintiff:
(3) [O.sub.P] = pJ + [C.sub.D].
An out-of-equilibrium offer [O.sub.P] < [[O.sub.P].bar] =
p[J.bar] + [C.sub.D] is believed to be made by player type [J.bar] and
is accepted with probability 1. An out-of-equilibrium offer Op > p) +
Co is believed to be made by player type [bar.J] and is rejected with
probability 1. Analogous out-of-equilibrium beliefs and actions apply to
all the models we analyze in this article.
Using the boundary condition that [phi]([[O.sub.P].bar]) = 0, the
differential equation in Equation 2 may be solved to obtain (10)
[phi]([O.sub.P]) = 1 - [e.sup.-[psi]],
where [psi]([O.sub.P]) = ([O.sub.P] - [[O.sub.P].bar])/([C.sub.P] +
[C.sub.D]). In this case the equilibrium probability of settlement is 1
- [psi]([O.sub.P]), or [e.sup.[psi]]. Substitute the equilibrium offer
from Equation 3 to write the equilibrium probability of settlement under
the fixed fee as
(4) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII],
where the subscript F indicates that this is a model with a fixed
fee and the subscript P denotes that this is a game in which the
plaintiff makes the offer. In equilibrium, higher plaintiff types must
have their offers rejected more frequently in order to discourage lower
plaintiff types from "bluffing" by submitting an offer higher
than the one associated with their type. The mapping between higher
offers and an increased probability of rejection is exactly sufficient
to induce fully revealing offers. Note that the probability of
settlement is increasing in the joint costs of trial, [C.sub.P] +
[C.sub.D]. As seen in the following analysis, one important avenue by
which contingency tee contracts affect pretrial settlement is through
their effect on the joint cost of proceeding to trial.
The Bifurcated Contingency Fee
The introduction of a contingency fee into the model raises several
issues relating to the nature of the contingency contract and the agency
relationship between the lawyer and her client. We will make our
modeling choices in such a way as to be consistent with the assumptions
in the model with the fixed fee. As a result, we will analyze a
bifurcated contingency fee first. However, we later analyze the model
with a unitary contingency fee contract.
First, in Reinganum and Wilde, it is assumed that the client
controls all aspects of the case. We will maintain that assumption and
ignore any possible conflict between the lawyer and client. Second,
Reinganum and Wilde assume that legal costs are independent of the size
of the judgment and are incurred only at trial. Thus, we will assume
that the plaintiff's lawyer incurs the cost [C.sub.P] only when
cases reach trial and that the bifurcated contingency percentage,
denoted [[theta].sup.B], is paid only if the case reaches trial and the
plaintiff receives a positive award. It would not change the character
of the results to assume that some court costs are incurred prior to
trial and that the lawyer's contingency percentage is lower for
cases that settle than for cases that proceed to trial. (11) Thus, step
ii of the game described in the previous section is replaced by
(ii') The plaintiff hires a lawyer under a contract in which
she pays the lawyer [[theta].sup.B]J if the case reaches trial and there
is a finding for the plaintiff. The lawyer receives 0 if the case
settles prior to trial or if the plaintiff loses at trial.
Finally, we assume that at the time the lawyer accepts the
plaintiff's case, she can observe the distribution of types from
which the plaintiff is drawn but not the plaintiff's exact type.
(12) In order to keep expected attorney's fees equal to those paid
in the fixed fee model, we assume the contingency percentage
[[theta].sub.B] is set such that the lawyer earns [C.sub.P] on average
for all cases that proceed to trial. This average depends on the
distribution of plaintiff types and the equilibrium rejection function
derived in the following analysis. (13)
When a trial occurs, a plaintiff of type J expects to receive p(1 -
[[theta].sup.B])J. The plaintiff chooses an offer to maximize
(5) [V.sub.P] = [phi]([O.sub.P])[p(1 - [[theta].sup.B])J] + (1 -
[phi]([O.sub.P]))[O.sub.P],
where, as before, [phi]([O.sub.P]) is the rejection function. The
first-order condition from the maximization of Equation 5 is
(6) [phi]'([O.sub.P])[p(1 - [[theta].sub.B])J - [O.sub.P]] +
(1 - [phi]([O.sub.P])) = 0.
To make the defendant indifferent between acceptance and rejection,
the equilibrium offer must continue to satisfy Equation 3. Defendant
beliefs are again correct in equilibrium, so the offers described by
Equation 3 will be fully revealing of the plaintiff's type. A
rejection function that satisfies the diffemntial equation in Equation 6
is
(7) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Equation 7 is a special case of general solution presented by
Reinganum and Wilde (1986) in their Equation 10. (14) Since the
equilibrium offers satisfy Equation 3, Equation 7 implies an equilibrium
probability of settlement for a type J plaintiff under the bifurcated
lee equal to
(8) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
What we would like to do is compare the settlement function under
the bifurcated fee in Equation 8 to the settlement function under the
fixed tee in Equation 4. First note that under both settlement
functions, the weakest plaintiff type settles with probability 1:
[S.sub.BP]([J.bar]) = [S.sub.FP]([J.bar]) = 1. Next, taking the
derivative of these functions with respect to J and converting to a
percentage change (denoted by "^") we get the following:
(9) [[??].sub.FP] = -p/[C.sub.P] + [C.sub.D]
(10) [[??].sub.EP] = -p/[[theta].sub.B] [p.sub.J] + [C.sub.D].
Since the contingency fee percentage is based on an average of
plaintiff types, for low values of J it will be the case that
p[[theta].sup.B]J < [C.sub.P]. As a result, the settlement rate under
the bifurcated lee initially declines in percentage terms more sharply
than the settlement rate under the fixed fee. The rate of decline of
settlement under the fixed tee does not exceed the rate of decline under
the bifurcated fee until J > [C.sub.P]/p[[theta].sup.B]. For values
of J above this, the rate of settlement declines faster under the fixed
fee. At the point where J = [C.sub.P]/p[[theta].sup.B], the ratio of the
settlement rates [S.sub.FP]/[S.sub.BP] > 1 is maximized; that is, at
this point the incidence of trial under a bifurcated fee relative to the
fixed lee is the greatest. Thus, it is only possible for [S.sub.BP]
[greater than or equal to] [S.sub.FP] at some value of J such that J
> [C.sub.P]/p[[theta].sup.B]. For a given upper support of the
distribution [bar.J], there is no guarantee that there are any values of
J such that [S.sub.FP]/[S.sub.BP] < 1. However, if [bar.J] is
sufficiently large, the settlement functions will eventually cross so
that there will be values of J such that [S.sub.BP] > [S.sub.FP]. The
fact that the functions cannot cross until the expected contingency
payment exceeds the fixed fee (p[theta]J > [C.sub.P]) suggests but
does not prove that overall settlement rates will tend to be lower under
the bifurcated contingency fee.
This analysis is summarized as follows:
RESULT 1: (i) Under a bifurcated fee, low-damage plaintiffs (J <
[C.sub.p]/p[[theta].sup.B]) proceed to trial more frequently when
compared to the fixed fee.
(ii) For a sufficiently large J, [S.sub.BP] > [S.sub.FP], but
the crossing point must occur at a value of J such that J >
[C.sub.P]/p[[theta].sub.B].
PROOF: This follows immediately from the fact that
[S.sub.BP]([J.bar]) = [S.sub.FP]([J.bar]) = 1 and a comparison of
Equation 9 with Equation 10. QED
Under a contingency fee system, low plaintiff types face a lower
expected cost of pursuing trial than the same plaintiffs under a fixed
fee. This reduces the cost of having offers rejected for these
plaintiffs. Thus, as plaintiff type rises above [J.bar], the equilibrium
rejection rate initially has to rise at a faster rate compared with the
model with the fixed fee in order to induce the fully revealing offers
described by Equation 3. As a result, a bifurcated contingency fee
contract will produce more rejections (and more trials) among low-damage
plaintiffs.
As type J increases, the expected cost of trial rises for the
plaintiff, and the rate of increase in the rejection rate necessary for
truthful revelation of type decreases. When J >
[C.sub.P]/p[[theta].sub.B], the settlement rate under the contingency
tee declines at a slower rate than under the fixed lee. At a
sufficiently high value of J. the settlement rate under the bifurcated
lee will be higher than under the fixed fee. The previous analysis
suggests that less settlement will occur under the bifurcated fee, but
it is not totally conclusive on this point. Importantly, the bifurcated
contingency tee changes the selection of disputes since it causes more
low-stakes cases to reach trial than under the fixed fee.
It is relatively straightforward to write down the set of equations
that determine an equilibrium value of the contingency fee percentage
[[theta].sup.B], that is, the value that compensates (in an expected
value sense) the plaintiff's lawyer for the opportunity cost of her
time. However, these equations will not yield an analytical solution.
Therefore, we have omitted this analysis from the study. (15)
The Unitary Fee
While the use of bifurcated contracts is noted in the literature on
contingency tees, most contracts are unitary in the sense that the
contingency percentage is the same whether the case settles or the
plaintiff wins at trial. In this section we assume that the contingency
fee is paid whenever the plaintiff receives a payment, whether that be
at trial or through a pretrial settlement. Denote the unitary
contingency percentage as [[theta].sup.U].
Under this assumption, the plaintiff's objective function
(Equation 5) now becomes
(11) [V.sub.P] = [phi]([O.sub.P])[p(1 - [[theta].sup.U])J] + (1 -
[phi]([O.sub.P]))(1 - [[theta].sup.U])[O.sub.P].
This model is solved in a manner analogous to the earlier model.
The plaintiff chooses an offer to maximize Equation 11. The equilibrium
offer to the defendant continues to be described by Equation 3. The
first-order condition from the maximization of Equation 11 plus Equation
3 implies the following rejection function in equilibrium:
(12) [phi]([O.sub.P]) = 1 - [e.sup.-[psi]] where [psi]([O.sub.P]) =
p(J - [J.bar])/[C.sub.D].
Equation 12 can be derived in a relatively straightforward way from
Equation 9 in the Reinganum and Wilde article. (16) The equilibrium
probability, of settlement under the unitary fee is
(13) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
A comparison of Equations 13 and 4 reveals that for all J >
[J.bar] we have [S.sub.FP] > [S.sub.UP]. Take the derivative of
Equation 13 with respect to J and convert to a percent change to obtain
(14) [S.sub.UP] = - P/[C.sub.D]
This leads to the following result:
RESULT 2: A unitary contingency tee increases the incidence of
trial relative to both (i) a fixed fee contract and (ii) the bifurcated
contingency fee contract.
PROOF: Part (i) follows directly from a comparison of Equation 13
to Equation 4. For part (ii), note that at J = [J.bar], [S.sup.UP] =
[S.sub.BP] = 1. A comparison of Equations 14 and 10 shows that Sup
declines at a faster rate than [S.sub.BP] for all Y. Thus, for all J
> [J.bar], [S.sub.BP] > [S.sub.UP].
Note further that since the fixed fee [C.sub.P] in Equation 4 and
the expected contingency payments at trial p[[theta].sup.B]J in Equation
8 should be sizable, the increase in the incidence of trial may be quite
large. Since she now pays her lawyer regardless of whether the case
proceeds to trial, the cost of proceeding to trial is lower for the
plaintiff. For plaintiffs of type J to be discouraged from making an
offer associated with type J + [DELTA] J, the rate of rejection must
rise more steeply than in either of the two earlier models. As a result,
for all J > [J.bar], the probability of acceptance is lower when a
unitary contingency fee contract is used.
Fee Shifting
Both Donohue (1991) and Smith (1992) have analyzed the interactions
between contingency fees and fee shifting in models along the lines of
Shavell (1982) in which trials result when exogenous beliefs of the
parties to the dispute diverge sufficiently. Both authors analyze fee
shifting under the assumption that the defendant pays the
plaintiff's lawyer [[theta].sup.B]J in the event that the plaintiff
is victorious at trial. (17) We will follow this assumption but note
some issues that it raises as well. We will also assume that the
plaintiff rather than her attorney pays the defendant's attorney
lees [C.sub.D] in the event the defendant wins at trial. (18) Fee
shifting under which the loser at trial pays the legal fees of the
victorious party is sometimes referred to as the English Rule.
We will analyze only the case of the bifurcated fee, but the
analysis of the unitary fee yields similar conclusions. The general
nature of the equilibrium is as described previously. As before, the
plaintiff's offer must make the defendant indifferent between
acceptance and rejection. Thus, the offer must reflect the probability
of shifted fees as follows:
(15) [O.sub.P] = p(J + [C.sub.D] + [[theta].sup.B]J).
In equilibrium, a type J plaintiff will make the offer described in
Equation 15. Thus, offers are fully revealing in equilibrium. The
plaintiff's expected wealth may now be written
(16) [V.sub.P] = [phi]([O.sub.P])[pJ - (1 - p)[C.sub.D]] + (1
[phi]([O.sub.P]))[O.sub.P],
where, as before, [phi]([O.sub.P]) is the probability the offer
[O.sub.P], is rejected by the defendant. Equation 16 reflects a
bifurcated fee under which the plaintiff's lawyer is paid in the
event of a plaintiff victory at trial but not in the event of a pretrial
settlement. The plaintiff chooses [O.sub.P] to maximize Equation 16,
taking the rejection function as given. Proceeding as before, the
first-order condition to Equation 16 is solved by a differential
equation of the form
(17) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
Substitute Equation 15 into Equation 17 to see that the settlement
rate with lee shifting (i.e., the English Rule) is
(18) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
A comparison of Equation 18 with Equation 8 implies the following:
RESULT 3: For a given value of the bifurcated contingency fee,
[[theta].sup.B], fee shifting under which the loser at trial pays the
winner's court costs unambiguously increases the incidence of
trial.
PROOF: For a given value of the contingency lee [[theta].sup.B],
Equation 18 < Equation 8 for each plaintiff type J > [J.bar].
Reinganum and Wilde show that lee shifting does not affect
settlement in the model with the fixed fee. (19) The reason is that
adjacent plaintiff types shift the same expected fee p[C.sub.P] to the
defendant. To understand why fee shifting affects settlement rates when
contingency tees are used, consider two adjacent plaintiff types J and J
+ [DELTA]J. Type ,I expects to shift p[[theta].sup.B]J and type J +
[DELTA]J expects to shift p[[theta].sup.B](J + [DELTA]J). This
difference in the expected value of shifted tees is reflected in the
offer the plaintiff submits to the defendant. This increases the
incentive of a plaintiff to "bluff" by submitting a higher
offer than is associated with her type. Thus, with fee shifting, the
rejection rate must rise more steeply in order to induce revealing
otters as described by Equation 15.
To the extent that a lower dispute rate is considered a policy
goal, this analysis suggests that the introduction of the English Rule
may be undesirable in a system that makes extensive use of contingency
fees (or vice versa). It is straightforward to show that the use of fee
shifting also raises the incidence of trial when a unitary contingency
fee contract is used. (20)
There are several issues raised by the interaction of contingency
fees and fee shifting that may affect how such a system would be
implemented in practice. First, under a bifurcated fee, the plaintiff
pays her lawyer a small contingency in the event the case settles but
never pays her own lawyer at trial. (If she wins at trial, the defendant
pays her lawyer.) Thus, the plaintiff has the incentive to negotiate a
contingency percentage at trial that is the highest allowable by law so
as to maximize the work incentives of her lawyer. (21) It is important,
therefore, that shifted tees be reasonable and perhaps limited to the
expenditures by the opposing party at trial. (22)
Second, under a bifurcated tee, the contingency percentage at trial
[[theta].sup.B] embeds within it the probability the plaintiff will lose
at trial. Suppose the plaintiff wins with probability 0.5, the expected
judgment is $100,000, and a lawyer working under a fixed fee would earn
$16,666.67 if the case went to trial. The corresponding contingency
payment to this lawyer would be [[theta].sup.B] = 1/3. Thus, if the
entire contingency payment is shifted when the plaintiff wins, the
defendant pays $33,333.33 compared with $16,666.67 under a fixed tee.
The defendant is, in an expected value sense, paying the
plaintiff's lawyer for the state of the world in which the
plaintiff loses. Thus, under a bifurcated contingency fee, a fee
shifting rule that shifts the entire contingency payment is strongly
proplaintiff.
On the other hand, if a unitary contingency fee is used, it will
overpay the lawyer for cases that settle and underpay (in an expected
value sense) the lawyer for cases that proceed to trial. Since the
overwhelming majority of cases settle, a unitary fee shifted at trial to
the defendant may be a very significant underestimate of the true cost
of the plaintiff's lawyer (most of which is paid out in the state
of the world in which the case settles).
Since shifting [theta]J appears problematic under either
contingency fee contract, it might be more desirable to shift fees based
on the number of hours put in on the case by the lawyer using prevailing
hourly rates to value this time.
3. A Signaling Model Where the Defendant Has Private Information
To fully understand how contingency fees affect the outcome of a
signaling game, it is important to analyze the alternative information
structure under which an informed defendant makes a single offer to an
uninformed plaintiff. To make our results comparable to section 2, we
will assume that the defendant knows the value of the judgment J in the
event that the plaintiff prevails at trial. (23) We will examine both
the bifurcated and the unitary contingency fee in the context of this
model. The derivation of the model solutions follows the previous
analysis very closely. (24)
For comparison, we first consider the following game in which the
fee is fixed:
(i') Nature determines the defendant's type J. The
plaintiff does not observe J but knows the distribution f(J) from which
it is drawn, where [bar.J] and [J.bar] are the upper and lower supports
off (J).
(ii') The plaintiff hires a lawyer under a fixed fee contract
that pays her lawyer [C.sub.P] if the case proceeds to trial and 0 if
the case settles prior to trial.
(iii') The defendant makes a single take-it-or-leave-it offer
[O.sub.D] to the defendant.
(iv') If the plaintiff accepts the offer, she receives a
payoff of [O.sub.D], and the defendant receives a payoff of -[O.sub.D].
If the offer is rejected, the case proceeds to trial.
(v') At trial, there is a finding for the plaintiff with
probability p, in which case she receives the payoff J - [C.sub.P],
while the defendant receives the payoff -(J + [C.sub.D]). With
probability 1 - p, the finding is for the defendant; in this case, the
plaintiff receives a payoff of -[C.sub.P], and the defendant receives
the payoff -[C.sub.D].
Again, we assume that [C.sub.P] < p[J.bar], so that the
plaintiff will proceed to trial even against the defendant with the
strongest case.
The defendant will make an offer [O.sub.D] to maximize
(19) [V.sub.D] = [empty set]([O.sub.D])[-pJ - [C.sub.D]] + (1 -
[empty set])([O.sub.P]))(-[O.sub.D]),
where [empty set]([O.sub.D]) is the probability the plaintiff
rejects an offer [O.sub.D].
Since plaintiffs pursue a mixed strategy in equilibrium, they must
be indifferent between accepting and rejecting an otter. As a result,
defendants of type p make an offer that satisfies
(20) [O.sub.D] = pJ - [C.sub.P].
Proceeding as before, the first-order condition from Equation 19
combined with Equation 20 and the boundary condition [empty
set]([[bar.O].sub.p]) = 1 together imply the following rejection
function in equilibrium:
[empty set]([O.sub.D]) = 1 - [e.sup.[psi]],
where [psi]([O.sub.D]) = ([[bar.O].sub.D] - [O.sub.D])/([C.sub.P] +
[C.sub.D]). Use Equation 20 to find an equilibrium probability of
settlement equal to
(21) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
where the subscript FD denotes a fixed fee model in which the
defendant makes the offer. Defendants with stronger cases (lower values
of J) have their offers rejected more in equilibrium so as to discourage
"bluffing" by defendants with weaker cases. The defendant with
the weakest case, [bar.J]. has his offer accepted with probability 1.
Take the derivative of Equation 21 with respect to .I and convert to
percentage terms to find
(22) [S.sub.FD] = P/[C.sub.p] + [C.sub.D].
The positive sign on [S.sub.FD] implies that the settlement rate
falls as J falls below [bar.J].
Contingency Fees
The previous game will be modified so that the plaintiff's
lawyer is paid based on a bifurcated contingency fee contract. Steps
ii' and v' replace those in the game developed in the previous
section.
(ii') The plaintiff hires a lawyer under a bifurcated
contingency fee contract that pays her lawyer [[theta].sup.B]J if the
case proceeds to trial and 0 if the case settles prior to trial.
(v') At trial, there is a finding for the plaintiff with
probability p, in which case she receives the payoff J(1 -
[[theta].sup.B]), while the defendant receives the payoff -(J +
[C.sub.D]). With probability 1 - p, the finding is for the defendant: in
this case, the plaintiff receives a payoff of 0, and the defendant
receives the payoff -[C.sub.D].
In this game, the defendant's optimization problem remains
unchanged from Equation 19. However, the offer that leaves the plaintiff
indifferent between acceptance and rejection becomes
(23) [O.sub.D] = p(l - [[theta].sup.B])J.
This offer reflects the contingency percentage [[theta].sup.B] paid
at trial in the event of a plaintiff victory. Again, solving the
first-order condition from the maximization of Equation 19 while making
use of Equation 23 yields the following equilibrium probability of
settlement under a bifurcated contingency fee:
(24) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
Taking the derivative of Equation 24 with respect to J and
convening to percent change yields
(25) [S.sub.BD] = (1 -[[theta].sup.B])p/[[theta].sup.B]pJ +
[C.sub.D]
This analysis leads to the following:
RESULT 4: In the model where the informed defendant makes the
offer, a bifurcated fee will result in a higher settlement rate than the
fixed fee for all values of J < [bar.J] if
(26) (1 - [[theta].sup.B])[C.sub.P] < [[theta].sub.B](pJ +
[C.sub.D] [for all]J.
PROOF: At [bar.J] we have [S.sub.BD] = [S.sub.FD] = I. If the
previously stated condition holds, then a comparison of Equation 25 with
Equation 22 shows that as p falls, the rate of decrease in the
settlement rate under the fixed fee always exceeds the rate of decrease
under the bifurcated contingency fee.
Even if the condition in Equation 26 does not hold, it is still
quite possible that the contingency fee will result in greater
settlement overall, though the settlement functions will cross at some
point.
Furthermore, for a reasonable set of parameter values, the
condition in Equation 26 will hold for all values of J. For example,
when [C.sub.P] = [C.sub.D] and [[theta].sup.B] = 1/3, the condition in
Equation 26 collapses to [C.sub.P] < pJ. Earlier we imposed [C.sub.P]
< p[J.bar] to guarantee that the plaintiff had a credible threat to
proceed to trial against all defendant types. Thus, for these parameter
values, Equation 26 holds for all defendant types, and there is an
unambiguous reduction in the incidence of trial relative to the model
where the fixed fee is utilized. By contrast, in the model where the
informed plaintiff makes the offer, there is an ambiguous effect on the
settlement rate and, if anything, a presumption of an overall increase
in disputes.
The denominator in Equation 25 is analogous to that in Equation 10,
and the mechanism described in section 2 operates in this model as well.
In particular, the plaintiff has a weak case when J takes on a low
value. This group of plaintiffs has a low expected payment to their
lawyer if the case proceeds to trial. Thus, the joint cost of trial is
lower for the plaintiff and defendant than it is for plaintiffs with
stronger cases (i.e., those matched against defendants with higher
values of J). Thus, plaintiffs with weak cases proceed to trial more
often relative to a fixed fee. As noted previously, this mechanism gives
an ambiguous prediction as to how the incidence of trial will change as
we move from a fixed fee regime to a bifurcated contingency fee.
However, in this version of the model, there is an additional
mechanism not present in the earlier model. This mechanism is reflected
by the 1 - [[theta].sup.B] term in the numerator of Equation 25, which
has no analog in Equation 10. The contingency fee pushes the offers of
adjacent defendant types closer together relative to the fixed fee.
Under a fixed fee, two adjacent defendant types will make the offers pJ
- [C.sub.D] and p(J - [DELTA]J) - [C.sub.D]. Under a bifurcated
contingency fee, the same two defendant types will offer p(1 -
[[theta].sup.B])J and p(1 - [[theta].sup.B])(J - [DELTA]J). Because the
offers are closer together under the bifurcated contingency fee, there
is less incentive for the defendant to "bluff" by submitting
an offer lower than the offer indicated by Equation 23. As a result,
compared to the fixed fee, the rejection function need not rise as
steeply as the defendant's offer falls.
Now briefly consider the use of a unitary contingency fee. The
defendant's objective function Equation 19 remains unaffected, but
a larger offer is necessary to make the plaintiff indifferent between
acceptance and rejection. In equilibrium, the defendant's offer
must satisfy
(27) [O.sub.D] = [p.sub.J].
Since the plaintiff pays her lawyer, regardless of whether the case
settles, the equilibrium offer to the plaintiff must rise to the
expected judgment she would receive at trial. Solving the model as
before using Equation 27 yields an equilibrium probability of settlement
of
(28) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII.]
Taking the derivative with respect to J and converting to percent
changes yields
(29) [[??].sub.UD] = p/[C.sub.D]. Ct)
Equations 28 and 29 lead to the following result:
RESULT 5: A unitary contingency lee unambiguously reduces
settlement rates relative to (i) a fixed fee and (ii) a bifurcated lee.
PROOF: Result (i) follows from a direct comparison of Equation 28
to Equation 21. For result (ii), note that at [bar.J], [S.sub.UD] =
[S.sub.BD] = 1. A comparison of Equation 29 with Equation 25 shows that
as J falls, the rate of decrease in the settlement rate under the
unitary fee always exceeds the rate of decrease under the bifurcated
contingency fee.
Since the defendant cannot extract any of the plaintiff's
expected trial costs with his offer, the cost of having an offer
rejected by the plaintiff is lower than in the case of either the fixed
fee or the bifurcated fee. As a result, the rejection rate needs to rise
more quickly as the defendant's offer falls in order to induce the
revealing offers indicated by Equation 27.
With the unitary contingency fee, the offer to the plaintiff rises
as reflected by a comparison of Equation 27 with Equations 20 and 23.
This increase in the offer reflects the insights of Bebchuk and Guzman
(1996), who argue that this represents an advantage of a (unitary)
contingency fee contract relative to an hourly fee arrangement. (25) The
increased dispute rate under a unitary contingency fee contract may
offset this advantage, as the contingency percentage will have to rise
to reflect the increased hours put in by lawyers on the additional cases
that reach trial.
The predicted increase in the incidence of trial under the unitary
contingency fee is quite robust. It occurs in the signaling model
regardless of whether it is the plaintiff or the defendant who is
modeled as the informed party. In addition, this result would clearly
generalize to a screening model along the lines of Bebchuk (1984).
Fee Shifting
In this section we analyze fee shifting with a bifurcated fee using
a modeling approach similar to that presented in section 2.
Specifically, the defendant pays the plaintiff's lawyer
[[theta].sup.B] J in the event that the plaintiff is victorious at
trial, and the plaintiff pays the defendant's attorney fees
[C.sub.D] in the event the defendant wins at trial.
In equilibrium, the defendant's offer must make the plaintiff
indifferent between acceptance and rejection. Thus, the offer must
satisfy
(3) [O.sub.D] = [p.sub.J] - (1 - p)[C.sub.D],
which reflects the probability (1 - p) that the defendant's
court costs will be shifted to the plaintiff. The defendant's
expected wealth is now
(31) [V.sub.D] = [phi]([O.sub.D])[-p(J + [[theta] J + [C.sub.D])] +
(1 - [phi]([O.sub.D]))(-[O.sub.D]),
where, as before, [phi]([O.sub.D]) is the probability the
defendant's offer is rejected by the plaintiff. The defendant
chooses [O.sub.D] to maximize Equation 31, taking the rejection function
as given. Proceeding as before, the first-order condition is solved by a
differential equation of the form
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII.]
Substitute from Equation 30 to see that the settlement rate with
fee shifting is
(32) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII.]
A comparison of Equation 32 with Equation 24 yields the following:
RESULT 6: For a given value of the bifurcated contingency fee,
[[theta].sup.B], fee shifting under which the loser at trial pays the
winner's court costs unambiguously increases the incidence of
trial.
PROOF: For a given value of the contingency fee [[theta].sup.B],
Equation 32 < Equation 24 for each plaintiff type J < [??].
As in the model where the plaintiff makes the offer, fee shifting
unambiguously increases dispute rates when it is combined with an
existing contingency fee arrangement. (26) The robustness of this result
across information structures lends some insight into why American-style
contingency fees contracts have been banned in Britain. They also
suggest that some care be taken to address the interaction between
contingency fees and fee shifting if fee shifting is to be introduced
into the United States on a widespread basis.
4. Conclusion
The effects of a contingency fee on settlement depends both on the
nature of the contingency fee contract and on the way in which the
informational asymmetry is modeled. One robust result is that under a
unitary contingency fee, the incidence of trial is unambiguously higher
compared with either a fixed fee or a bifurcated contingency fee. When
the informed plaintiff makes the offer, a bifurcated fee changes the
selection of disputes for litigation but has an ambiguous effect on the
overall incidence of trial. In particular, under such a fee structure,
more low-stakes cases will proceed to trial than under the fixed fee
contract. When an informed defendant makes the offer, there is a
presumption that a bifurcated contingency fee reduces the incidence of
trial relative to the fixed fee.
Fee shifting may have important interactions with contingency fees.
In particular, when fee shifting is introduced into a model with a
bifurcated contingency fee, we find (for a given value of the
contingency fee) an unambiguous increase in the incidence of trial. By
contrast, when the lawyer is compensated with a fixed fee, Reinganum and
Wilde show that fee shitting has no effect on the incidence of trial.
The analysis in this study assumes that the plaintiff controls all
aspects of the case. We view the results of this study as complementary,
to the results of earlier work that analyzed contingency fees under the
assumption that the plaintiff's lawyer effectively controlled the
settlement decision.
(1) See Gravelle (1998) and Rubinfeld and Scotchmer 11998). See
Helland and Tabarrok (2003) for a recent empirical analysis of the
effects of contingency tees.
(2) In addition, there was considerable debate in Britain in the
early 1990s over whether the use of contingency tees should be allowed.
While there were some changes in British law, U.S.-style contingency
fees are still banned them. Lawyers are now allowed to enter in
conditional fee arrangements, Under these arrangements, no fee is paid
by the plaintiff if she loses, and a markup over the usual lawyer tees
is paid if she wins. See Gravelle (1998).
(3) For more on the selection of disputes for trial see Priest and
Klein (1984) and Shavell (1996), among others.
(4) This is the approach taken by Miceli (1994), who develops a
model with nuisance suits. See also Gravelle and Waterson (1993). who
develop a model in which the lawyer controls the case and maximizes a
weighted average of her income and her client's income. In both of
these articles, the uninformed party makes an offer to the informed
party. In our study, the informed party makes the offer: that is, ours
is a signaling model. Reinganum and Wilde (1986) analyze contingency
fees in the signaling model. Their work is discussed extensively in the
following text.
(5) Daughety and Reinganum (2003) develop both a signaling model
and a screening model in which the plaintiff pays her lawyer via
contingency lee. As in our section 3, they consider a model with an
informed defendant (see pp. 141-7). The locus of their study is
split-award statutes under which punitive damage awards are split
between the plaintiff and the state. They do not analyze the effect of
contingency fees on settlement. In addition, they consider the unitary
tee but not the bifurcated fee introduced later in this article.
(6) We are following Hay's (1997) terminology to describe
these fee structures.
(7) Based on survey data, Hensler et al. (1991, p. 136) find that
87% of plaintiffs hired lawyers on contingency, with 67% using a fixed
contingency fee and 20%, using a varied fee that would include the type
of bifurcated lee analyzed in this study. See also Miller (1987, p.
201).
(8) See Miller (1987). Polinsky and Rubinfeld (2002) argue that
this traditional result may not hold once the lawyer's incentive to
under provide effort at trial is taken into account. Polinsky and
Rubinfeld (2003) propose a mechanism that aligns the interest of the
client and the lawyer under a contingency fee. See also Santore and
Viard (2001).
(9) The concept they use is "universally divine
equilibrium." See Banks and Sobel (1987). Using this refinement,
all pooling and semipooling equilibria can be eliminated. See Reinganum
and Wilde (1986, p. 566).
(10) For a discussion on why this is the correct boundary
condition, see Reinganum and Wilde (1986, p. 565). An analogous
condition applies in all the models analyzed in this article.
(11) This is the assumption made by Miceli (1994, p. 215). See also
Hay (1997).
(12) This is the assumption made by Miceli and Segerson (1991, p.
383).
(13) As noted in section 1, we are treating the form of the
contract between the plaintiff and her lawyer as exogenous. An alert
reader may be concerned that plaintiffs with strong cases should (in the
context of our setup) prefer fixed lee contracts because for these
plaintiffs the expected contingency payment is large. This issue can be
addressed by changing the tinting of the model. In particular, we can
assume that the plaintiff learns her exact type through consultations
with her lawyer that take place after a contract has been entered into.
(14) To see this, set [beta] = 1, [alpha] = 1 - [[theta].sub.B],
and [C.sub.P] = 0 in their equation 9.
(15) The equations which determine the endogenous value of
[[theta].sup.B] are provided in the working paper version of this
article (Farmer and Pecorino 2003).
(16) Set [c.sub.p] = 0 and [alpha] = [beta] = 1 - [0.sup.u] in
their equation 9. Solve the resulting dilferential equation to obtain
our Equation 12.
(17) In contrast, Reinganum and Wilde (1986, pp. 562-3) assume that
only the noncontingent portion of court costs are subject to shifting.
They show that allocation of court costs can affect the probability of
trial if this interacts with a contingency fee arrangement under which
the plaintiff does not retain all the pretrial settlement.
(18) Smith and Donohue analyze both cases.
(19) But see note 17.
(20) Fee shifting has been shown to increase total expenditures at
trial (Braeutigam, Owen, and Panzar 1984). An increase in expenditure
should lead to a reduced incidence of trial. This presumption must be
weighed against the results we present here that suggest the opposite
effect.
(21) See the discussion in Smith (1992, pp. 2167-71).
(22) Such a limitation is likely to affect high type J plaintiffs
but not low types. As long as there are some low plaintiff types for
which such a limitation is not binding, the rejection rate under fee
shifting will exceed the rejection rate without tee shifting for all
plaintiff types J > [J.bar]. However, for the range of plaintiff
types for which the cap on shifted fees is binding, Equation 18 will
provide an underestimate of the settlement rate.
(23) An example (suggested to us by an anonymous referee) would be
a chemical company acting as a defendant that knows more about the
expected damages it has inflicted on the plaintiffs than the plaintiffs
do. Assuming instead that the defendant is better informed about p. the
probability the plaintiff prevails at trial will not affect any of our
results.
(24) See note 5.
(25) See also Rickman (1999).
(26) But see note 20.
References
Banks, Jeffery S., and Joel Sobel. 1987. Equilibrium selection in
signaling games. Econometrica 55:647-61.
Bebchuk, Lucian Arye. 1984. Litigation and settlement under
imperfect information. RAND Journal of Economics 15:404-15.
Bebchuk, Lucian Arye, and Andrew T. Guzman. 1996. How would you
like to pay for that? The strategic effects of fee arrangements on
settlement terms. Harvard Negotiation Law Review 1:53-63.
Braeutigam, Ronald, Bruce Owen, and John Panzar. 1984. An economic
analysis of alternative lee shifting systems. Law and Contemporary
Problems 47:173-85.
Dana, James D., Jr., and Kathryn E. Spier. 1993. Expertise and
contingent fees: The role of asymmetric reformation in attorney
compensation. Journal of Law. Economics, and Organization 9:349 67.
Danzon, Patricia M. 1983. Contingency fees for personal injury
litigation. Bell Journal of Economies 14:213-24.
Daughety, Andrew F., and Jennifer F. Reinganum. 1994. Settlement
negotiations with two-sided asymmetric information: Model duality,
information distribution, and efficiency. International Review of Law
and Economics 14:283-98.
Daughety, Andrew F., and Jennifer F. Reinganum. 2003. Found money?
Split award statutes and settlement of punitive damages cases. American Law and Economics Review 5:134-64.
Donohue, John J. 1991. The effects of fee shifting on the
settlement rate: Theoretical observations on costs, conflicts and
contingency fees. Law and Contemporary Problems 54:195 226.
Farmer, Amy, and Paul Pecorino. 2003. Dispute rates and contingency
fees: An analysis from the signaling model. University of Alabama Working Paper No. 03-11-01.
Gravelle, Hugh, 1998. Conditional fees in Britain. In Palgrave dictionary of economies and the law 1. edited by Peter K. Newell. New
York: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 382-7.
Gravelle, Hugh, and Michael Waterson. 1993. No win, no fee: Some
economics of contingent legal fees. Economic Journal 103:1205-20.
Hay, Bruce L. 1996. Contingency lees and agency costs. Journal of
Legal Studies 25:503-33.
Hay, Bruce L. 1997. Optimal contingent fees in a world of
settlement. Journal of Legal Studies 26:259-78.
Helland, Eric, and Alexander Tabarrok. 2003. Contingency fees,
settlement delay and low-quality litigation: Empirical evidence from two
datasets. Journal of Law. Economics and Organization 19:517-42.
Hensler, Deborah R.. Susan Marquis, Allan F. Abrahamse, and D.
Hensler. 1991. Compensation for accidental injuries in the United
States. Santa Monica, CA: Rand.
Miceli, Thomas J. 1993. Optimal deterrence of nuisance suits by
repeat defendants. International Review of Law and Economics 13:135-44.
Miceli, Thomas J. 1994. Do contingent fees promote excessive
litigation? Journal of Legal Studies 23:211 24.
Miceli, Thomas J., and Kathleen Segerson. 1991. Contingent fees for
lawyers: The impact on litigation and accident prevention. Journal of
Legal Studies 20:381-99.
Miller, Geoffrey P. 1987. Some agency problems in settlement.
Journal of Legal Studies 18:157-79.
Polinsky, A. Mitchell, and Daniel Rubinfeld. 2002. A note on
settlements under the contingent fee method of compensating lawyers.
International Review of Law and Economics 22:193-216.
Polinsky, A. Mitchell, and Daniel Rubinfeld. 2003. Aligning the
interests of lawyers and clients. American Law and Economics Review
5:165-88.
Priest, George L., and Benjamin Klein. 1984. The selection of
disputes for litigation. Journal of Legal Studies 13:1-55.
Reinganum, Jennifer F., and Louis L. Wilde. 1986. Settlement,
litigation, and the allocation of litigation costs. RAND Journal of
Economics 17:557-66.
Rickman, Neil. 1999. Contingent fees and litigation settlement.
International Review of Law and Economics 19:295-317.
Rubinfeld, Daniel L., and Suzanne Scotchmer. 1993. Contingent fees
for attorneys: An economic analysis. RAND Journal of Economics
24:343-56.
Rubinfeld, Daniel L., and Suzanne Scotchmer. 1998. Contingent lees.
In Palgrave dictionary of economics and the law 1, edited by Peter K.
Newell. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 415-9.
Santore, Rudy, and Alan D. Viard. 2001. Legal fee restrictions,
moral hazard, and attorney rents. Journal of Law and Economics
44:549-72.
Shavell, Steven. 1982. Suit, settlement and trial: A theoretical
analysis under alternative methods tot the allocation of legal costs.
Journal of Legal Studies 11:55-81.
Shavell, Steven. 1996. Any frequency of plaintiff victory at trial
is possible. Journal of Legal Studies 25:493-501.
Smith, Bradley L. 1992. Three attorney lee-shifting rules and
contingency fees: Their impact on settlement incentives. Michigan Law
Review, 90:2154-87.
Watts, Alison. 1994. Bargaining through an expert attorney. Journal
of Law, Economics, and Organization 10:168-86.
Amy Farmer * and Paul Pecorino ([dagger])
* Department of Economics, University of Arkansas. Fayetteville, AR
72701, USA: Email: afanner@walton.uark.edu.
([dagger]) Department of Economics, Finance and Legal Studies,
University of Alabama. Box 870224, Tuscaloosa. AL 35487, USA: E-mail
ppecorin@cba.ua.edu: corresponding author. We would like to thank
Richard Boylan. Akram Temimi, and two anonymous referees for providing
helpful comments on this article.
Received August 2003: accepted May 2004.