What determines public support for affirmative action?
Levin, Andrew T.
Despite widespread recognition of the value of diversity, efforts
to increase the number of minority professionals through race-sensitive
admissions policies have never been fully accepted. As the competition
to enter leading colleges and professional schools continued to
intensify, this opposition became more vocal ... The U.S. economy is
assigning more and more value to higher education as preparation for
success in the workplace. As a result, the incentive to finish college
is becoming stronger. This is surely one reason why the debate over who
gains admission to the most selective schools has become so heated.
--from The Shape of the River, by W. G. Bowen and D. Bok (1998, pp.
13, 69) [emphasis added]
1. Introduction
Affirmative action, which came into effect in the United States in
the late 1960s with the intent to eliminate racial, ethnic, and gender
differences in access to economic opportunity, has arguably been one of
the most contentious public policies implemented. (1) Although the civil
rights struggle of the 1960s shifted public opinion in favor of
affirmative action, opposition to such policies remained relatively high
throughout the late 1960s and the 1970s. The Supreme Court's ruling
on the 1978 Bakke v. the University of Ca1ifornia case, which prohibited the use of strict quotas but allowed the lawful consideration of race,
gender, and ethnicity in college admissions, settled the issue
temporarily--at least from a legal standpoint. In the 1990s, however,
stronger opposition to affirmative action and the subsequent elimination
in some states of such policies for college admissions, public
procurement, and employment helped bring affirmative action to the
forefront of the public policy forum once again. (2)
The three decades during which affirmative action policies were in
effect also canvas a period with potentially relevant changes in
academic trends and labor market outcomes: First, the disparity in the
scores of Black and White takers of the Scholastic Assessment Tests
narrowed fairly steadily between the mid-1970s and the late 1980s and
held relatively steady thereafter. (3) In contrast, the disparity
between Blacks and Whites with regard to job performance and labor
productivity remained persistently and significantly lower than
differences between Blacks and Whites with regard to average test scores
during the whole period. (4) Second, after rising in the 1960s and
declining in the 1970s, the returns to education, as well as other
components of skill, started to increase rapidly in the early 1980s. In
fact, the returns to education soared so impressively during the 1980s
and the early 1990s that in 1994 it stood at roughly 35% above its value
in 1963 (see Figure 1). Moreover, between the late 1970s and th e
mid-1980s, when the return to education, experience, and other
components of unobservable skill were rising, the increase in the
education premium outpaced that in the returns to experience and other
components of skill. (5)
For the most part, the debate about affirmative action revolves
around assessing whether the impact and success of affirmative action
policies to date justify their existence. But this debate also raises
intriguing questions from a political economy standpoint. Why has
political support for such policies begun to erode more rapidly in the
1990s? If indeed there are biases in screening, what role do they play
in the political economy of affirmative action? And, more specifically,
how are recent trends in public support for affirmative action linked to
increases in the education premium and reductions in the test score gap
in the last two decades?
In this paper, we present a political economy model of tax-financed
public education. In the model, investment in education is indivisible,
and as a result, demand for education can exceed its supply. Thus, a
screening mechanism--such as a standardized test--is required for
allocation. These tests can most accurately measure cognitive skills,
but labor productivity depends on these skills as well as other
immeasurable traits. In any given period, a majority vote determines the
supply of education as well as whether to enact affirmative action
policies. When voting, parents take into account not only the effect
affirmative action has on the odds of admission of their own offspring,
but also the social benefits of instituting these policies.
What are the potential social benefits of affirmative action? For
one, to the extent that the majority and the minority are more similar
in immeasurable traits than in measurable characteristics such that a
selection system bias exists, affirmative action policies help to
improve the efficiency of educational allocation. (6) Second, empirical
and anecdotal evidence indicates that greater social diversity in access
to education and employment generates aggregate economic benefits. (7)
It is also clear that such social diversity can be achieved only through
the maintenance of at least some degree of equal opportunity. In
racially, ethnically, or culturally diverse societies, the benefits of
diversity arise because greater representation of minorities in
government, business, and the professions helps to produce more
enlightened public policies and corporate choices. Moreover, for diverse
societies to remain peaceful and economically efficient, access to
economic opportunities and rewards need to be perceived to be open to
all members of a society. (8)
Our results indicate that for a given amount of spending on public
education, affirmative action policies may have two effects: First, they
lower the odds of admission to a public school for applicants from
majority households. Second, they alleviate the negative effect of the
selection system bias on the allocation of education. Because of both
these effects, changes in the returns to education as well as the
relative test score distributions of the majority and the minority
potentially affect the majority's political support for affirmative
action. In periods in which the education premium is relatively low, the
matching efficiency gains provided by affirmative action are relatively
high compared with the opportunity cost of not acquiring education, and
the majority supports affirmative action. In periods in which the
returns to education are high, the majority's support for
affirmative action declines as the opportunity cost of remaining
uneducated increases relative to the matching efficiency gains provid ed
by affirmative action policies. In contrast, changes in the test score
gap have offsetting effects on the majority: On the one hand, a higher
majority-minority test score gap suggests that the social benefits of
affirmative action would be large. On the other hand, the institution of
affirmative action policies would displace a number of the
majority's offspring from the ranks of the college educated. Thus,
in general, changes in the test score gap have ambiguous effects on the
majority's political desire to support affirmative action.
Nonetheless, for a sufficiently high test score gap, the social benefits
of affirmative action outweigh the majority's utility cost of
displacement from college such that they support affirmative action.
Two issues are noteworthy at the outset: First, although we
identify returns to education as an important determinant of affirmative
action policies, we do not claim that economic factors alone-- without
reliance on sociological or cultural ones--can explain changes in the
support for affirmative action. For example, one could argue that biases
in screening for education and employment have been significantly
reduced in the last three decades because of the Civil Rights Act and
therefore that scaling back affirmative action policies is warranted. We
do not take a position on this or any other similar argument. Rather,
our sole intent is to explore the effects, if any, of economic factors
on the determination and scope of affirmative action. Second, although
the sole focus of this paper is affirmative action in higher education,
it would be straightforward to extend this model to include affirmative
action in employment. As will become apparent below, equilibrium
affirmative action policies in education and em ployment should be
perfectly correlated when such policies in education are based on the
votes of a majority who take into account the private costs and benefits
of affirmative action. In that context, the full benefits of affirmative
action in education cannot accrue with continued biases in the labor
market.
2. Related Literature
By design, this paper brings together the existing literature on
public education and that on affirmative action. Fernandez and Rogerson
(1995) examine political support for tertiary education. They do not
consider the role of tests in the political economy outcomes but instead
focus on subsidies whose sizes are determined by majority vote.
Fernandez (1998) and Fernandez and Gali (1999) explore the role
borrowing constraints play in the performance of exams versus that of
markets as allocative mechanisms. In a model in which agents who differ
in their initial wealth and ability are assigned to various investment
opportunities or schools of various qualities, these authors show that
exams dominate markets in terms of aggregate output. For sufficiently
powerful (less-biased) exam technologies, exams are superior to markets
in terms of aggregate consumption as well. Glomm and Ravikumar (1992)
compare the income distribution and growth implications of public
education with those of private education. Their model is one in which
all agents in the economy demand educational services to various degrees
and the quality of educational services depends on the total resources
allocated to education. Glomm and Ravikumar find that private education,
which will be chosen by higher-income individuals, results in less
subsequent mobility but higher growth rates. In contrast, public
education, which will be preferred by lower-income groups, leads to
greater social mobility at the expense of long-run economic growth. As a
result, to the extent that the median voter is poorer than the mean
income voter, public education is chosen in a more unequal society.
Gradstein and Justman (1997) focus on why public education should be
more likely to be chosen over private education in a more democratic
society that is unequal. They demonstrate that because rational voters
internalize all possible positive externalities of an education system,
these voters do not necessarily choose one with more
redistribution--public education in particular-- over others that lead
to higher long-run economic growth.
There are relatively fewer theoretical studies on affirmative
action. Coate and Loury (1993a, b) develop models in which employers who
harbor negative stereotypes of certain groups are likely to assign
workers belonging to those groups to less rewarding jobs. They show that
since this lowers the expected return for these workers on investments
that make them more productive in more rewarding jobs, employers'
negative beliefs can be self-confirming even when all groups are ex ante
identical. Welch (1976) examines employment quotas in a setup in which
employers discriminate. He shows how quotas may create a shortage of
skilled minority workers. Thus, he argues that such quotas may lead
unskilled minority workers to be assigned to skilled jobs as a result of
firms' attempts to acquire the option of hiring additional skilled
majority workers. Lundberg (1991) analyzes the problem of enforcing
equal-opportunity laws when the regulators have imperfect information on
employer personnel policies and on the relationshi p between
workers' characteristics and their productiveness. She examines the
social costs and benefits of two alternative regulatory regimes: one
prohibiting the use of proxies for race, sex, or gender in the
determination of worker wages, and the other requiring wages to depend
on observed worker characteristics in the same way for each group. Chan
and Eyster (2000), as noted above, study the potential effects of
banning affirmative action on diversity and student quality. They find
that eliminating affirmative action policies will reduce diversity and
may also lower average student quality.
The remainder of this paper is organized as follows: In section 3,
we define the economy and individuals' preferences. In section 4,
we discuss the determination of affirmative action. We do this in two
steps: First, we utilize a simple version of the model in which the
share of resources devoted to education is fixed. Then, we relax this
assumption and examine the joint determination of affirmative action and
public education supply. In section 5, we conclude.
3. The Economy and Preferences
Consider an economy in which education is publicly provided. Let e
(e > 0) denote the cost of education per pupil and y denote aggregate
wealth in period 1. Then, the supply of educational services in the
second period, S, will be given by
S = [[tau].sup.*]y/about, (1)
where [[tau].sup.*] represents the equilibrium tax rate.
There is a single consumption good and a continuum of parents of
measure 1. The population comprises a majority, which accounts for p (a
fraction of more than half of the population), and a minority, 1 - p.
Parents live for two periods, and they get utility from their own
consumption and the expected consumption of their offspring. There is no
population growth, and each parent has one offspring who lives for one
period. (9) In the first period of life, parents consume. They also vote
on the share of resources to be allocated to public higher education and
whether to adopt affirmative action in the following period. In the
second period, these parents send their offspring to a public school if
they are admitted.
At birth, individuals are endowed with some innate ability, which
is lognormally distributed, with [a.sub.i] [equivalent to] log[A.sub.i]
~ N(0,1). (10) When voting on the share of resources to be allocated to
public higher education, parents do not know the ability endowments of
their children. (11) When the supply of public education, S, is less
than its demand, applicants are admitted to schools on the basis of
their measurable productive abilities. (12) Let [z.sub.i] ([z.sub.i]
[equivalent to] log [Z.sub.i]: [R.sup.2] [right arrow] R) represent the
log of labor productivity of parent i's offspring.
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] (2)
where [alpha] ([alpha] [greater than or equal to] [alpha]) denotes
the average productivity difference between the offspring of the
majority and the offspring of the minority. (13)
The available screening technology is imperfect. It can accurately
measure only a subset of the aggregate skills that determine labor
productivity. Moreover, the traits that the test technology can measure
are those for which minority children, on average, are at a particular
disadvantage. Let [I.sub.i] ([I.sub.i]: [R.sup.2] [right arrow] R)
denote the log of the labor productivity of parent i's offspring as
measured with the available proxy. Then,
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] (3)
where [beta] ([beTa] [greater than or equal to] [alpha]) denotes
the average difference between the test scores of the majority offspring
and minority offspring.
It is crucial at this juncture to explain what the specifications
in Equations 2 and 3 imply. With a screening technology that could
accurately measure all characteristics of lifetime productivity, there
would be no selection bias and the allocation of education would be
perfectly fair. For example, if labor. productivity depended only on
cognitive skills, differences in test scores would fully reflect
potential differences in productivity, and those with the highest
potential would be admitted to schools. However, given that available
tests most accurately measure some but not all of the traits that
detennine productivity, the relevant issue is whether there exist
screening biases that systematically leave members of certain cultural,
racial, or ethnic groups at a disadvantage. (15) Equations 2 and 3 are
designed to capture such biases, and the assumption [beta] [greater than
or equal to] [alpha] [greater than or equal to] 0 guarantees that the
formulation above is consistent with the empirical evidence.
We can verify that as [beta] [right arrow] [alpha], the available
test technology becomes a better predictor of labor productivity:
[lim.sub.[beta][right arrow][alpha]] corr([I.sup.i], [z.sup.i]) =
[lim.sub.[beta][right arrow][alpha]] = (1 + (1 - p)[alpha][beta]/[square
root of (1 + p(1 - p)[[alpha].sup.2])] [square root of (1 + p(1 -
p)[[beta].sup.2])]) = 1 (4)
Let [I.sup.*] denote the threshold score required for admission to
a public school that is consistent with the equilibrium tax rate
[[tau].sup.*]. If the measured ability level of parent i's
offspring is greater than or equal to [I.sup.*], then i's offspring
is admitted to a public school and earns [lambda](E)[Z.sub.i][w.sup.e]
in the second period, where [lambda] denotes a labor productivity
parameter, E denotes the aggregate efficiency units of educated labor,
and [w.sup.e] denotes the wage rate per efficiency unit of educated
labor. Otherwise, i's offspring remains uneducated and earns
[lambda](E)[Z.sub.i][w.sup.u], where [w.sup.u] is the wage rate per
efficiency unit of uneducated labor. We assume that [lambda] satisfies
the standard Inada conditions, that is, [lambda]'(E) > 0,
[lambda]"(E) < 0, [lim.sub.E[right arrow]0] [lambda]' =
[infinity] and [lim.sub.E[right arrow][infinity] [lambda]] = 0.
Let [a.sub.p], and [a.sub.1-p], respectively, denote the relevant
thresholds of admission for the children of the majority and the
children of the minority that are consistent with [I.sup.*] Equation 3
implies that when no affirmative action policies are in effect, the same
cutoff test score applies to all test takers. As a result [a.sub.p] =
[I.sup.N] < [a.sub.1-p] = [I.sup.N] + [beta]. That is, the threshold
ability necessary to gain admission for children of the majority is
strictly less than that for children of the minority. Thus, when
affirmative action is not adopted, the cutoff exam score required for
admission, [I.sup.N], is given by
S = 1 - [psi]([I.sup.N]), (5)
where [psi]([I.sup.N]), [psi]([I.sup.N]) [equivalent to]
p[PHI]([I.sup.N]) + (1 - p)[PHI]([I.sup.N] + [beta]), denotes the
population c.d.f. and [PHI](*) denotes the log ability c.d.f.
When voters choose to enact affirmative action policies, however,
we assume that higher-education admissions are carried out via a quota
system (or some weak variant of it) under which the minority and the
majority are admitted to schools on the basis of their representation in
the population. In that case, [a.sub.p] = [a.sub.1-p] = [I.sup.A], and
the threshold ability necessary to gain admission for majority children
is equal to that for minority children. That is, [I.sup.A] is such that
S = 1 - [PHI]([I.sup.A]). (6)
Parent i's utility from his or her own consumption in period 1
and his or her offspring's consumption in period 2 has a log-linear
form:
[u.sub.i] - [theta] ln([c.sub.i,1]) + (1 -
[theta])E[ln([c.sub.i,2])]; 0 < [theta] < 1, (7)
where [c.sub.i,1] and [c.sub.i,2] denote parent i's
consumption in period 1 and the consumption of i's offspring in
period 2, respectively.
Given that the higher-education system is public and parents do not
know their offspring's abilities when voting, the following
constraints apply to maximizing Equation 7:
[c.sub.i,1] [less than or equal to] (1 - [[tau].sub.i])[y.sub.i],
E[ln([c.sub.i,2])] = [[integral].sup.ai.sub.-[infinity]]
ln[exp([a.sub.i])[lambda](E)[w.sup.u]][phi](a) da +
[[integral].sup.[infinity].sub.ai]
ln[exp([a.sub.i])[lambda](E)[w.sup.e]][phi](a) da (8)
= ln [lambda](E) = [PHI]([a.sub.i]) ln([W.sup.u]) + [1 -
[PHI]([a.sub.i])]ln([w.sup.e]),
where [phi](*) denotes the probability density function (p.d.f.) of
the log-innate abilities, [y.sub.i] represents individual i's
initial endowment, [[tau].sub.i] is i's preferred tax rate, and
[a.sub.i], equals [a.sub.p], for majority voters and [a.sub.1-p] for
minority voters.
4. Affirmative Action and Education Supply
Affirmative Action with Fixed Education Supply
In what follows, we present the simplest version of the model laid
out above. Accordingly, the supply of education is fixed at S (i.e., the
equilibrium tax rate, [[tau].sup.*] is predetermined at [tau]). The only
decision that voters need to make is whether to enact affirmative action
policies in the following period. As Equations 5 and 6 indicate, S = S
[right arrow] [I.sup.A] > [I.sup.N].
The utility of a representative majority parent when there is no
affirmative action, [u.sup.N.sub.p], is given by
[u.sup.N.sub.p] = [theta] ln[(1 - [tau])[y.sub.p]] + (1 -
[theta]){ln [lambda][E([I.sup.N])] + [PHI]([I.sup.N]) ln([w.sup.u]) + [1
- [PHI]([I.sup.N])] ln([w.sup.e])}. (9)
The utility of a representative majority parent when there is
affirmative action, [u.sup.A.sub.p], is given by
[u.sup.A.sub.p] = [theta] ln[(1 - [tau])[y.sub.p]] + (1 -
[theta]){ln [lambda][E([I.sup.A])] + [PHI]([I.sup.A]) ln([w.sup.u]) + [1
- [PHI]([I.sup.A])] ln([w.sup.e])}. (10)
If [u.sup.A.sub.p] [less than or equal to] [u.sup.N.sub.p], the
social benefit of affirmative action policies does not outweigh their
costs to the majority (which accrue in the form of reduced odds of
gaining entry to a college), and the majority votes against affirmative
action. However, if [u.sup.A.sub.p] > [u.sup.N.sub.p], the benefit to
the majority outweighs the costs, and the majority votes to adopt
affirmative action. The likelihood that the utility of the majority with
affirmative action will exceed that without it depends on how large the
education premium, [w.sup.e]/[w.sup.u], is. This is more formally stated
in the following proposition.
PROPOSITION 1. Ceteris paribus, an increase in the education
premium, [w.sup.e]/[w.sup.u], reduces the likelihood that the majority
will support affirmative action. That is, for [beta] = [beta] and
[alpha] = [alpha], where [beta] > [alpha], [there exists]
([w.sup.e]/[w.sup.u]) such that [for all] [w.sup.e]/[w.sup.u] [greater
than or equal to] ([w.sup.e]/[w.sup.u]), [u.sup.A.sub.p] [less than or
equal to] [u.sup.N.sub.p], and [for all] [w.sup.e]/[w.sub.u] <
([w.sup.e]/[w.sup.u]), [u.sup.A.sub.p] > [u.sup.N.sub.p].
PROOF. Let F [equivalent to] [u.sup.A.sub.p] - [u.sup.N.sub.p] =
ln{[lambda][E([I.sup.A])]/[lambda][E([I.sup.N])]} -
ln([w.sup.e]/[w.sup.u][[PHI]([I.sup.A]) - [PHI]([I.sup.N]). Given that
[I.sup.A] > [I.sup.N],
E([I.sup.A]) = p [[integral].sup.[infinity].sub.[I.sup.A]]
exp(a)[phi](a) da + (1 - p) [[integral].sup.[infinity].sub.[I.sup.A]]
exp(a - [alpha])[phi](a) da, (11)
and
E([I.sup.N]) = p [[integral].sup.[infinity].sub.[I.sup.N]]
exp(a)[phi](a) da + (1 - p) [[integral]sup.[infinity].sub.[I.sup.N] +
[betal]] exp(a - [alpha])[phi](a) da, (12)
[beta] > [alpha] [right arrow] E([I.sup.A]) > E([I.sup.N]).
Thus, In {[lambda][E([I.sup.A])/[lambda][E([I.sup.N])]} > 0.
Moreover, for any given pair ([beta], [alpha]), [there exists]
([w.sup.e]/[w.sup.u]) such that F = 0. It follows immediately from
[partial]F/[partial]([w.sup.e]/[w.sup.u]) < 0 that [for all]
[w.sup.e]/[w.sup.u] [greater than or equal to] ([w.sup.e]/[w.sup.u]),
[u.sup.A.sub.p] [less than or equal to] [u.sup.N.sub.p], and [for all]
[w.sup.e]/[w.sup.u] < ([w.sup.e]/[w.sup.u]), [u.sup.A.sub.p] >
[u.sup.N.sub.p]. QED.
In the proof of the above proposition, the second term on the RHS of F represents the marginal cost of affirmative action to the majority
voter, whereas the first term on the rhs of F represents its marginal
benefit. The latter accrues through the positive externality of
attaining a more efficient educational allocation, and the former is
related positively to the marginal decline in the expected income of the
majority's offspring,([w.sup.e]/[w.sup.u])[[PHI]([I.sup.A]) -
[PHI]([I.sup.N])]. That, in turn, is related to the education premium,
[w.sup.e]/[w.sup.u]. Thus, when there is an increase in the education
premium, the net marginal benefit of majority voters' children
being admitted to a college increases relative to that of affirmative
action and raises the likelihood that majority voters will strike down
affirmative action.
The extent to which the adoption of affirmative action displaces
the majority offspring from college admissions also affects the expected
income of the majority's offspring through the term
[PHI]([I.sup.A]) - [PHI]([I.sup.M]). When the screening bias, [beta], is
relatively small, fewer majority offspring are displaced when
affirmative action is put in effect. Moreover, ceteris paribus, this
manifests itself in a relatively unchanged admission score being
required for the majority offspring under affirmative action, [I.sup.A].
This makes the private cost of affirmative action relatively low for the
majority. Nonetheless, the positive externality of attaining a more
efficient educational allocation is also smaller when [beta] is
relatively small. As a result, we cannot establish whether the
likelihood that affirmative action will be supported by majority voters
is lower when screening biases are relatively small. Only when the
screening biases are rather large can we conclude that the positive
social externalit y of affirmative action outweighs the private costs to
the majority voters. The next proposition formalizes this discussion.
PROPOSITION 2. For [for all] [beta] > [alpha] [greater than or
equal to] 0, the effect of higher test score biases, [beta], on the
majority's support for affirmative action is ambiguous. For [for
all] [alpha] [greater than or equal to] 0, the likelihood that the
majority will support affirmative action approaches unity as [beta]
[right arrow] [infinity].
PROOF. F [equivalent to] [u.sup.A.sub.p] - [u.sup.N.sub.p] = In
{[lambda][E([I.sup.A])]/[lambda][E([I.sup.N])]} - In
([w.sup.e]/[w.sup.u])[[PHI]([I.sup.A]) - [PHI]([I.sup.N])]. Using
Equation 5 and invoking the implicit function theorem, it is
straightforward to show that [for all] [I.sup.N] > 0,
[partial][I.sup.N]/[partial][beta] = (1 - p)[phi]([I.sup.N] +
[beta])/[psi]([I.sup.N]) < 0. (13)
Thus, [for all] [I.sup.N] > 0,
[partial][PHI]([I.sup.N])/[partial][beta] =
[partial][PHI]([I.sup.N])/[partial][I.sup.N]
[partial][I.sup.N]/[partial][beta] = (1 - p)[phi]([N.sup.N] +
[beta])[phi]([I.sup.N])/[psi]([I.sup.N]) < 0. (14)
Moreover, using Equation 6, we can also establish that [for all]
[I.sup.A] > 0, [partial][I.sup.A]/[partial][beta] =
[partial][PHI]([I.sup.A])/[partial][beta] = 0. Thus,
[partial][[PHI]([I.sup.A]) - [PHI]([I.sup.N])]/[partial][beta] =
-[partial][PHI]([I.sup.N])/[partial][beta] > 0. In addition, using
Equations 11 and 12, we also establish
[partial]In{[lambda][E([I.sup.A])]/[lambda][E([I.sup.N])}/[partial][b eta] = (1 - p) exp([I.sup.N] + [beta] - [alpha])[phi]([I.sup.N] +
[beta])[lambda]'[E([I.sup.N])]/[lambda][E([I.sup.N])] > 0. (15)
Thus, [for all] [beta] > [alpha] [greater than or equal to] 0,
[partial]F/[partial][beta] = (1 - p)exp([I.sup.N] + [beta])
{exp([I.sup.N] + [beta] -
[alpha])[lambda][E([I.sup.N])]/[lambda][E([I.sup.N])] - ln
([w.sup.e]/[w.sup.u]) [phi]([I.sup.N])/[psi]([I.sup.N])} >/< 0,
(16)
where [psi]([I.sup.N]) [equivalent to] p[phi]([I.sup.N]) + (1 -
p)[phi]([I.sup.N] + [beta]). For a sufficiently large [beta], the term
in brackets in Equation 16 becomes strictly positive, since when [beta]
[right arrow] [infinity], [phi]([I.sup.N] + [beta]) [right arrow] 0
(which implies in ([w.sup.e]/[w.sup.u])[[phi]([I.sup.N])/[psi]([I.sup.N])] [right arrow] in([w.sup.e]/[w.sup.u])/p) and exp([I.sup.N] + [beta] -
[alpha]) [right arrow] [infinity] (which implies exp([I.sup.N] + [beta]
- [alpha])[lambda]'E([I.sup.N])/[lambda]E([I.sup.N]) [right arrow]
[infinity]). This suggests that [for all] [alpha] [greater than or equal
to] 0, [there exists] large enough values of [beta] s.t.
[partial]([u.sup.A.sub.p] - [u.sup.N.sub.p])/[partial][beta] > 0.
QED.
Our second proposition implies that while the efficiency gains
associated with the adoption of affirmative action policies are highest
when screening biases are relatively large, its effect on the admissions
criteria--and therefore on the offspring's admission odds--is also
large. The implication of this is that smaller screening biases not only
reduce the social benefit of affirmative action but also lower the cost
to the majority because, at the margin, they displace fewer majority
children from the ranks of the educated. Thus, we cannot generally and
unambiguously establish what effect changes in the majority-minority
test score gap might have on political support for affirmative action.
As Proposition 2 shows, however, we can establish that the displacement
effect diminishes as the test score bias gets large, whereas the social
benefit of affirmative action increases. Hence, despite the generally
ambiguous effect of the test score gap on support for affirmative
action, we find that the public will favor a ffirmative action policies
with sufficiently high test score biases. What remains unclear is what
happens to that support when the test score gap declines.
Affirmative Action and Endogenous Education Supply
We now endogenize the share of resources devoted to education to
demonstrate that such an extension preserves the results outlined above.
In deciding on the optimal share of resources devoted to higher public
education, parents maximize Equation 7 with respect to the tax rate
[tau]. It is straightforward to show that majority parents prefer a tax
rate [[tau].sup.*] that satisfies the following first-order condition
[partial][u.sub.p]/[partial][I.sup.*] = - [theta]/1 - [[tau].sup.*]
[partial][[tau].sup.*]/[partial][I.sup.*] - (1 - [theta]) ln
([w.sup.e]/[w.sup.u]) [phi]([a.sub.p]) + (1 - [theta])
[lambda]'(E)/[lambda](E) [partial]E/[partial][I.sup.*] = 0, (17)
where
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] (18)
and where
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] (19)
with
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] (20)
The first term in Equation 17 denotes the marginal cost of lowering
the admissions threshold and increasing the supply of public education,
and the second and third terms represent the marginal benefit of doing
so. While the first benefit term depends on the education premium,
[w.sup.e]/[w.sup.u], and accrues only when the offspring gains admission
to a public school, the second arises due to the productivity gains
associated with a more educated labor force. Moreover, the former
depends positively on the p.d.f. of the ability of parent i's
offspring at that threshold, [phi]([a.sub.i]), but the cost of raising
supply is related to the p.d.f. of abilities for the whole population.
(16) In Equation 18, the latter term is given by the mixture density
function [psi]([I.sup.*]). [psi]([I.sup.*]) is higher under affirmative
action, which implies that the marginal cost of lowering the test-score
threshold is also higher when affirmative action is in effect. Put
differently, when the ratio of the majority voters' off spring
density to population density is small (as is the case when affirmative
action policies are in place), the net marginal benefit is low, since a
larger share of the benefit of lowering the admissions threshold accrues
to minority children. Equation 19 implies that when affirmative action
policies are not in effect, a disproportionate number of educated
workers come from majority households. Equation 20 indicates that the
aggregate efficiency units of educated labor, E, depend negatively on
the cutoff score [I.sup.*].
Figures 2 and 3 show the log ability densities for the children of
the two groups, [phi]([a.sub.i]), as well as the mixture p.d.f. for the
whole population, [psi]([a.sub.i]). Figure 2 depicts the ease of no
affirmative action when [beta] = 3. Note how at relatively high cutoff
levels of the threshold indicator, [I.sup.i], the mixture density
function lies below the density function of log abilities for the
offspring of the majority voters. In contrast, at lower threshold levels the density of log abilities for majority offspring is below that for
the population. Figure 3 shows the same variables for [beta] = 1. When
screening biases are smaller, the ratio of the majority's offspring
density to the population density is also smaller, which reflects the
increase in the odds of admission to public schools of the children of
the minority at the expense of those of the majority.
In the limiting case in which [alpha], [beta] [right arrow] 0, the
ratio of the densities approach 1. In that case, neither screening
biases, [beta], nor the fraction of the minority voters, 1 - p, has an
influence on the equilibrium share of resources devoted to public
education supply.
In order to highlight the role screening biases play in the
majority's optimal choice of public education supply, let us now
focus on the case in which affirmative action policies are not in
effect. Then, the share of resources devoted to public education supply
is an increasing function of the screening bias [beta]. More formally,
let G [equivalent to] [partial][u.sub.p]/[partial][I.sup.N] = 0. Using
the implicit function theorem, it is straightforward to show that
[partial][[tau].sup.N]/[partial][beta] =
-[G.sub.[beta]]/[G.sub.[tau]]
= -p[phi]([I.sup.N] + [beta])/[G.sub.[tau]] [theta]/1-[[tau].sup.N]
e/y [2([I.sup.N] + [beta]) + 1/1-[[tau].sup.N] c/y [psi]([I.sup.N])] +
1-[theta]/[G.sub.[tau]] [[lambda]'(E)/[lambda](E)
[[partial].sup.2]E/[partial] [([I.sup.N]).sup.2] +
[lambda]"(E)[lambda](E) -
[lambda]'[(E).sup.2]/[lambda][(E).sup.2]
[partial]E/[partial][I.sup.N]] [partial][I.sup.N]/[partial][beta]. (21)
The first term in Equation 21 shows the effect of a larger [beta]
on the majority offspring's admission odds and on the majority
voters' marginal cost: By assumption, [[tau].sup.N] is an interior
solution to the maximization problem of a majority parent when
affirmative action is not in effect. Thus, [G.sub.[tau]] is strictly
negative. The term 2([I.sup.N] + [beta]) represents how a given supply
of educational services benefits majority voters at the threshold [I.sup.N]. This effect arises because screening biases shift down the
relative position of the minority applicants in the [I.sup.i] map and
raise the majority voters' odds of admission when [I.sup.N] +
[beta] > 0. A sufficient but not necessary condition for this effect
to be positive is that resources allocated to public education are
restrictive enough that the threshold score [I.sup.N] is nonnegative.
The term [1/(1 - [[tau].sup.N])](e/y)[psi]([I.sup.N]) represents the
effect on utility of a lower fraction of children born to minority
voters qualifyi ng for admission at a given threshold [I.sup.N]. This
effect arises because when biases are larger, fewer resources need to be
devoted to public education supply, as a lower fraction of minority
parents' offspring qualify for admission. This effect is
unconditionally positive. The marginal utility and disutility of taxes
are depicted in Figure 4. (17) Consistent with the above analysis, the
utility of resources devoted to public education for majority voters
peaks at lower threshold levels and higher tax rates when screening
biases are larger.
The second term in Equation 21 denotes the marginal effect of
screening biases on the productivity variable [lambda]. Given that a
larger [beta] implies a less efficient allocation of education, this
term too is unambiguously positive. Consequently, when [I.sup.N] +
[beta] > 0, [[partial][tau].sup.N]/[partial][beta] > 0. The
corollary is that when affirmative action policies are in effect,
majority voters will choose to allocate a smaller share of total
resources to the supply of education. That is, [for all] [beta] >
[alpha] [greater than or equal to] 0, [[tau].sup.A] < [[tau].sup.N]
[right arrow] [I.sup.A] > [I.sup.N].
Turning once again to the determination of affirmative action, the
majority will vote to enact such policies if and only if >
[u.sup.A.sub.P] > [u.sup.N.sub.P] Modifying the function F defined in
the proof of Proposition 1, we get
F = 1n{1 - [[tau].sup.A])/(1 - [[tau].sup.N])} +
1n{[lambda][E([I.sup.A])]/[lambda] [E([I.sup.N])]} -
1n([w.sup.e]/[w.sup.u])[[PHI]([I.sup.A]) - [PHI]([I.sup.N])], (22)
where [[tau].sup.*] = d[1 - [PSI]([1.sup.*])]/y, * = N, A. From
Equation 22, analogs of Propositions 1 and 2 follow.
5. Conclusion
This paper presents a political economy model of affirmative action
for higher education. In the model, there are positive social
externalities associated with admitting applicants to public schools
according to their ability, and the demand for education exceeds supply
because of indivisibility in educational investment. Therefore, a
screening mechanism, which may potentially be biased against minorities,
is required to choose the student body. The results indicate that the
returns to education affect the support for affirmative action policies.
In periods in which the education premium is relatively low, the
matching efficiency gains provided by affirmative action are relatively
high compared with the opportunity cost of not acquiring education, and
the majority supports broader affirmative action. In contrast, in
periods in which the returns to education are high, the majority's
support for affirmative action declines as the opportunity cost of not
getting educated increases relative to the matching effici ency gains
provided by affirmative action policies. Unlike the role of the
education premium in determining the political outcome, a higher test
score bias has a generally ambiguous effect on political support for
affirmative action. Nonetheless, the social benefits of affirmative
action are large enough to sustain political support for affirmative
action when the test score gap is sufficiently large.
Appendix: Some Gallup Survey Results on Affirmative Action (18)
* Question: (Would you be more likely or less likely to vote for a
candidate who took the following positions or would it not affect your
opinion either way?) ... Favored affirmative-action plans that guarantee
minorities and women access to education and jobs.
Responses:
More likely: 63%
Less likely: 19%
No effect: 14%
Don't know: 4%
Population: National adult
Population size: 1009
Interview method: Telephone
Survey date: January-February 1982.
* Question: Do you generally favor or oppose affirmative-action
programs for women and minorities?
Responses:
Favor: 55%
Oppose: 34%
No opinion: 11%
Population: National adult
Population size: 1220
Interview method: Telephone
Survey date: March 1995.
* Question: When affirmative-action programs were first adopted
almost thirty years ago, do you think they were needed to help women and
racial minorities overcome discrimination, or were they not needed
thirty years ago?
Responses:
Needed: 86%
Not needed: 12%
No opinion: 2%
Population: National adult
Population size: 1003
Interview method: Telephone
Survey date: February 1995.
* Question: (As I read you each of the following issue positions,
please tell me if you would be more likely or less likely to vote for a
presidential candidate taking this position--or if it would not make
much difference.)... What if the candidate favored strengthening
affirmative-action laws for women and minorities?
Responses:
More likely: 51%
Less likely: 26%
Not much difference: 18%
Don't know/refused: 5%
Population: National adult
Population size: 1421
Interview method: Telephone
Survey dote: January 1992.
* Question: Do you favor or oppose strengthening affirmative-action
laws for women and minorities?
Responses:
Favor: 49%
Oppose: 43%
Don't know/refused: 9%
Population: National adult
Population size: 1022
Interview method: Telephone
Survey date: September 1994.
[FIGURE 1 OMITTED]
[FIGURE 2 OMITTED]
[FIGURE 3 OMITTED]
[FIGURE 4 OMITTED]
Received December 2000; accepted March 2002.
(1.) The Civil Rights Act, which prohibits discrimination on the
basis of race, gender, or ethnicity, was enacted in 1964. Executive
orders 11246 and 11375, which set the currently applicable standards of
affirmative action policies in federal procurement, employment, and
education, were signed in 1965 and 1967, respectively.
(2.) In 1995, the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Fifth Court
approved eliminating the consideration of race for admissions to public
colleges in Texas. In 1996, a majority of California voters cast their
ballots in favor of Proposition 209, which called for ending the
consideration of race, ethnicity, or gender in admissions to public
colleges and universities in California.
According to Gallup polls, opposition to affirmative action
policies in education stood at a much higher level in the mid1990s than
in the early 1980s--the earliest period for which the opinion polls
exist. In 1982, 63% of the representative subsample of the U.S. adult
population responded that they would be more likely to vote for a
presidential candidate who favored affirmative action in education and
employment for women and minorities. In contrast, only 55% of the
respondents to a national poll in 1995 said that they generally favored
affirmative action programs. At least an striking, 86% of those surveyed
in 1995 thought that affirmative action programs were needed when they
were first adopted in the late 1960s. (For more details, see the
Appendix.)
(3.) Bowen and Bok (1998) document that the score gap for both the
verbal and the math sections of the test declined by approximately 25%
between 1975-1976 and 1989 and that it held steady or even widened
modestly in recent years.
(4.) The standard deviation for test scores averages around 1. but
that of job performance does not exceed 0.4.
Jencks (1998) points out that this difference is indicative of a
"selection system bias" in higher-education screening. Such a
bias occurs because while available screening tests measure mostly--if
not purely--cognitive skills, test scores explain only 10-20% of the
variation in job performance. Moreover, Blacks are far less
disadvantaged in noncognitive determinants of productivity than in
cognitive ones.
(5.) See Juhn, Murphy. and Pierce (1993), Murphy (1997), and Autor,
Katz, and Krueger (1998).
(6.) Chan and Eyster (2000) show, for example, that banning
affirmative action always reduces diversity and, in some cases, may also
reduce average student quality. Moreover, Holzer and Neumark (1999) find
no evidence of weaker job performance among most minority groups,
although they find that the educational qualifications of minorities
hired under affirmative action are lower.
(7.) Some indirect empirical evidence is provided by numerous
studies on the long-run adverse economic consequences of income
inequality. See, for example, Galor and Zeira (1993) and Persson and
Tabellini (1994).
(8.) See Bowen and Bok (1998, pp. 11-12).
(9.) This assumption is clearly nonessential. Whether the offspring
live for one period or two periods is irrelevant, since, in this
context, we do not focus on the dynamics of public education finance and
affirmative action.
10.) We employ the lognormal probability density function (p.d.f.)
for expositional convenience only. In fact, the results we present below
are not dependent on the exact specification of the p.d.f. To the extent
that the simple trade-off between the private costs and the social gains
of affirmative action exist for decisive voters, our results would--at
least qualitatively--go through.
(11.) The results of our model are based on the premise that by the
time parents vote on the supply of public higher education, there exists
some uncertainty about the innate academic ability of the voters'
offspring. While we employ a stricter version of this notion by assuming
that at the time of voting parents have no information on their
children's academic potential, the results below would hold under
alternative specifications where there is some degree of uncertainty at
the time of the vote.
(12.) Note that in our simple framework, the demand for education
equals 1, as the second-period wage earnings for educated labor are
higher than those for uneducated labor for all ability levels. Note also
that for the sake of simplicity, we abstract from any cost associated
with screening.
(13.) We allow for the possibility that there is a positive
productivity gap between the majority and the minority on the grounds
that there exist accumulable factors, such as social capital and
connections, that influence labor productivity. As some argue, there can
be historical precedents to suggest that biases in social practices and
policies have led to gaps between the minority and the majority in the
accumulation of such factors. That noted, whether [alpha] is strictly
positive or not is inconsequential for the results below.
(14.) In our view, a more comprehensive version of Equation 3 ought
to include a measurement error term. Although we abstract from it in the
version provided here, the qualitative nature of our results is robust
to a specification of Equation 3 that includes such an error term.
(15.) Jencks (1998) identifies five such potential biases in
testing and concludes that two of those--labeling and selection system
biases--significantly harm minorities. He shows how choosing students at
least in part on the basis of test technologies that measure cognitive
skills leads to biases even if the technology exhibits no systematic
prediction errors. The reason is that available tests measure those
traits for which differences across groups tend to be larger than those
for other unmeasured determinants of productivity (see footnote 4).
According to Jencks's definitions, labeling bias arises when a test
claims to measure one thing but actually measures something else.
Selection system bias occurs when (i) labor productivity depends only
partly on cognitive skills, (ii) it is easy to measure cognitive skills
relative to other skills that affect performance, and (iii) the racial
disparity in cognitive skills is larger than that in other unmeasured
traits that influence performance.
(16.) Note that the concavity of voter's utility function
manifests itself in a precautionary supply of public education. This
effect is implicit in both the second and the third terms of Equation
17. In the former it is reflected in ln([w.sup.e]/[w.sup.u]), and in the
latter it is reflected in [lambda]'(E)/[lambda](E).
(17.) To simplify the exposition. Figure 4 has been drawn under the
assumption that there are no externalities of educated labor on the
level of technology.
(18.) The margin of error on all listed surveys is [+ or -]3%.
References
Autor, David, Lawrence Katz, and Alan Krueger. 1998. Computing inequality: Have computers changed the labor market? Quarterly Journal
of Economics 113:1169-214.
Bowen, William G., and Derek Bok. 1998. The shape of the river.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Chan, Jimmy, and Erik Eyster. 2000. Does banning affirmative action
harm college student quality? Unpublished paper, Johns Hopkins
University.
Coate, Steven, and Glenn Loury. 1993a. Antidiscrimination
enforcement and the problem of patronization. American Economic Review
83:92-8.
Coate, Steven, and Glenn Loury. 1993b. Will affirmative-action
policies eliminate negative stereotypes? American Economic Review
83:1220-40.
Fernandez, Raquel. 1998. Education and borrowing constraints: Tests
vs. prices. Unpublished paper, New York University.
Femander, Raquel, and Jordi Gali. 1999. To each according to ...?
Markets, tournaments, and the matching problem with borrowing
constraints. Review of Economic Studies 66:199-824.
Fernandez, Raquel, and Richard Rogerson. 1995. On the political
economy of education subsidies. Review of Economic Studies 62:249-62.
Galor, Oded, and Joseph Zeira. 1993. income distribution and
macroeconomics. Review of Economic Studies 60:35-52.
Glomin, Gerhard, and B. Ravikumar. 1992. Public versus private
investment in human capital: Endogenous growth and income inequality.
Journal of Political Economy 100:818-34.
Gradstein, Mark, and Moshe Justman, 1997. Democratic choice of an
education system: Implications for growth and income distribution.
Journal of Economic Growth 2:169-83.
Hoizer, Harry, and David Neumark. 1999. Are affirmative action
hires less qualified? Evidence from employer-employee data on new hires.
Journal of Labor Economics 17:534-69.
Jencks, Christopher. 1998. Racial bias in testing. in The
Black-White test score gap, edited by C. Jencks and M. Phillips.
Washington, DC: Brookings institution Press, pp. 55-85.
Juhn, Chinhui, Kevin M. Murphy, and Brooks Pierce. 1993. Wage
inequality and the rise in returns 10 skill. Journal of Political
Economy 101:410-42.
Lundberg, Shelly J. 1991. The enforcement of equal opportunity laws
under imperfect information: Affirmative action and alternatives.
Quarterly Journal of Economics 106:309-26.
Murphy, Kevin M. 1997. Skills and earnings inequality: The supply
side. AEI Seminar Series on Understanding Economic Inequality. Working
Paper No. 7375.
Persson. Torsten, and Guido Tabellini. 1994. Is inequality harmful
for growth? American Economic Review 84:600-621.
Murat F. Iyigun *
Welch, Finis. 1976. Employment quotas for minorities. Journal of
Political Economy 84:S105-39.
* Department of Economics, University of Colorado, Campus Box 256,
Boulder, CO 80309-0256, USA; E-mail murat.iyigun@colorado.edu;
corresponding author.
Andrew T. Levin +
+ Board of Governors of the Federal Reserve System, 20th and C
Streets, Washington, DC 20551, USA; E-mail levina@frb.gov.
For useful suggestions we thank two anonymous referees and seminar
participants at Brown University and the Federal Reserve Board. All
remaining errors are our own. This paper represents the views of the
authors and should not be interpreted as reflecting those of the Board
of Governors of the Federal Reserve System or other members of its
staff.