Absence of Envy Does Not Imply Fairness: Reply.
Holcombe, Randall G.
Randall G. Holcombe [*]
1. Introduction
I titled my reply using the title of my original paper rather than
the title of Berliant, Thomson, and Dunz's comment, "On the
Fairness Literature," because my 1997 paper dealt only with the
issue in its title, not with the fairness literature in general. What I
intended to show was only that the statement in the title is true:
Absence of envy does not imply fairness. I want to do two things in this
reply: first, consider the claim I made in the title of my original
paper in light of the comment of Berliant, Thomson, and Dunz, and
second, respond to the issues they raised in their comment. I will be
brief in supporting my original claim, because Berliant, Thomson, and
Dunz do not dispute it. Nowhere do they argue that any part of my paper
is incorrect, but rather, they say, "Holcombe's exclusive
focus on the no-envy solution is not warranted." Thus, we appear to
be in agreement that my original paper demonstrated that the absence of
envy does not imply fairness, as its title claimed, and that my original
pap er focused exclusively on the no-envy criterion. We agree on
something else too. In my original paper, I quoted Berliant, Thomson,
and Dunz (1992, p. 202), and in their comment, they also quoted
themselves as having said, "There now exists in economics a
well-developed literature devoted to the formulation and the analysis of
equity concepts. The concept that has played the central role is that of
an envy-free allocation." Thus, we also agree that the concept of
an envy-free allocation is the central concept in this literature.
I did not write my original paper as a comment on Berliant,
Thomson, and Dunz (1992), or any other specific paper, or on the
fairness literature in general; rather, I hoped to make an independent
contribution to this literature with a clear and convincing
demonstration that the absence of envy does not imply fairness, even in
the most straightforward case. The reason I cited Berliant, Thomson, and
Dunz was to show that some of the most frequent contributors to this
literature [1] believe that the concept I focused exclusively on is, in
fact, the central concept in the fairness literature. Academic writing
often focuses on very narrow concepts to get a better idea of their
properties and implications, and my exclusive focus on the concept that
Berliant, Thomson, and Dunz call the central concept in the fairness
literature does not seem inappropriate, especially when that narrow
focus demonstrates that the central concept in the fairness literature
is neither necessary nor sufficient to ensure fairness. [2]
2. Limitations of the Fairness Literature
Berliant, Thomson, and Dunz say I raise four criticisms of the
fairness literature, but in fact I make only one, and I prefer to
consider it an observation, not a criticism. Also, as I noted in my 1997
paper, many other contributors to the literature have made the same
observation. Consider the criticisms they list.
First, they list as a criticism my observation that an allocation
may be envy-free but not fair. Defending the fairness literature against
my observation, they note that the literature has examined many other
criteria, and I am happy to acknowledge that this is the case. However,
my paper dealt only with the no-envy criterion. My paper was not an
attack on the fairness literature but rather was limited to an analysis
of what Berliant, Thomson, and Dunz call the central concept of that
literature.
Second, they say I criticize the literature because "some
agents may deserve more than others, and envy might well be justified
then." Here again, we agree that this is true, but I did not intend
it as a criticism of the fairness literature. Rather, I noted that
others in the literature have already analyzed situations in which some
might deserve more than others, and in such cases, fair outcomes may not
be envy-free. For that reason, the analysis in Holcombe (1997) takes
place in a purely distributional framework where nobody deserves more
than anybody else, so this issue is irrelevant to my analysis. My point
was that even in a situation where nobody is more deserving than anybody
else, an envy-free outcome still can be shown to be unfair. I brought up
the issue of merit not as a criticism of the fairness literature, but
rather to point out that it is not relevant to my 1997 analysis of
envy-free outcomes.
Third, they say I criticize the literature because "random
devices may appear fair, but once implemented they are not." Again,
we agree on this, and I was not criticizing the literature because of
it. My original example does not rely on random devices, and I brought
this up in my 1997 paper only to show that one cannot escape from my
conclusion by appealing to the possibility of adding random devices to
the mechanism in my paper. As I noted in my 1997 paper, some authors
have employed random devices to try to avoid just the problem that paper
addresses, so I believed it was worth discussing--not as a criticism of
the literature but to show that it is irrelevant to the problem at hand.
Fourth, they say I criticize the literature by saying, "The
fairness of the process that leads to the final allocations should not
be ignored." I agree with that statement, and that was my main
point in Holcombe (1983). I do not view this as a criticism of the
literature, which has recognized this point, but rather brought it up
because the reason Holcombe (1997) concludes that absence of envy does
not imply fairness is that the process for producing an envy-free
outcome can be biased to favor some individuals over others. This is
relevant because the freedom-from-envy criterion is an evaluation of an
outcome and does not take into account the process that produces an
envy-free outcome. The point is relevant, but I did not raise it as a
criticism of the literature. My only goal in my original paper was to
demonstrate that the absence of envy does not imply fairness.
3. Conclusion
Berliant, Thomson, and Dunz are critical of the narrow focus of my
1997 paper, but in closing, it is worth repeating those things on which
we appear to agree so it is clear where any differences between us
begin. We all agree that absence of envy does not imply fairness; my
original paper focused exclusively on the no-envy criterion; and the
no-envy criterion plays the central role in the fairness literature. My
1997 paper was not intended as a comment on Berliant, Thomson, and Dunz
(1992), but I see how they could have taken it as such. The title of
their paper says it is about "fair division," but on pages
203-4, they say, "We now present our main equity notion.... a
partition is envy-free if no agent would prefer someone else's
parcel to his own. This concept is the central one in the economics
literature." Nowhere after this equity notion is presented to the
reader does their paper ever mention fairness, not even in the
conclusion. Thus, I would argue that their paper is about envy-free
division, not fai r division, and that the two are not the same.
In my 1997 paper, I cited a number of contributions to the
literature that discussed problems with equating fairness and freedom
from envy, and I am happy to acknowledge that there is a broader
literature on the subject. At the same time, I believe that sometimes
the freedom-from-envy concept has been inappropriately relied on as an
indicator of fairness in that literature. Thus, I will close by
re-emphasizing the only point I intended to make in my original paper,
and a point on which both my critics and I appear to agree: Absence of
envy does not imply fairness.
(*.) Department of Economics, Florida State University,
Tallahassee, FL 32306, USA; E-mail holcombe@garnet.acns.fsu.edu.
(1.) By my count, Berliant, Thomson, or Dunz are authors or
coauthors of 18 of the 63 references they cite in their comment on the
fairness literature, or about 29% of the total.
(2.) Could Berliant, Thomson, and Dunz (1992) be vulnerable to the
same criticism they level at me? Their 1992 paper analyzes only two
equity criteria: no envy and egalitarian equivalence. Although this is
twice the number of equity criteria I examine, one still might argue
that in light of the voluminous literature cited in their comment, their
exclusive focus on only these two criteria is unwarranted. My point is
that any one paper always has a narrower focus than a body of literature
consisting of hundreds of articles and books.
References
Berliant, Marcus, William Thomson, and Karl Dunz. 1992. On the fair
division of a heterogeneous commodity. Journal of Mathematical Economics 21:201-16.
Holcombe, Randall G. 1983. Applied fairness theory: Comment.
American Economic Review 73:1153-6.
Holcombe, Randall G. 1997. Absence of envy does not imply fairness.
Southern Economic Journal 63:797-802.