Teaching price discrimination: some clarification.
Coates, Dennis
1. Introduction
Economics is useful and important as a tool for the study of
policy. Indeed, what interests students most are those topics with
direct policy relevance. We think it important that these topics be
covered with as little opportunity for confusion as possible, especially
in the Principles course, which may be the only exposure students get to
many of these issues. Treatment of price discrimination in both
Principles and Intermediate texts are often laden with misleading and
even incorrect information.
We have reviewed the discussions of price discrimination in several
Principles and Intermediate textbooks. Principles texts we have reviewed
include: Mansfield (1992), Baumol and Blinder (1994), Miller (1994),
Tresch (1994), Gwartney and Stroup (1995), Samuelson and Nordhans
(1995), Taylor (1995), Lipsey and Courant (1996), McConnell and Brue
(1996), and Parkin (1996). Intermediate texts we have reviewed include
Ekelund and Ault (1995), Mansfield (1997), Nicholson (1997), Hirshleifer
and Hirshleifer (1998), Landsberg (1998), Pindyck and Rubinfeld (1998),
Browning and Zupan (1999), and Perloff (1999). Across these texts, we
have found a wide variance in the approach and the issues raised.
In general, the discussions in Principles texts focus on either
theory or antitrust policy, but rarely link the two. Those that focus on
theory scarcely mention the regulatory issues and legislation. These
discussions usually are part of the chapter on monopoly. Most of these
texts indicate that a downward sloping demand curve and market
segmentation are required. Some mention that prohibition of resale is a
requirement. Most texts in this group define price discrimination as a
situation in which the same good is sold at different prices unrelated
to cost differences, but there are exceptions. Almost exclusively, the
graphical exposition demonstrates first-degree price discrimination, but
the examples of real-world price discrimination are of the third-degree
variety.
One major problem with these treatments is that the theoretical
presentation and the examples are inconsistent. A second problem is that
it is very hard to justify the examples as coming from monopolized
industries. For example, common textbook cases of price discrimination
are senior citizen discounts offered by restaurants, child prices for
movie theaters, and differential pricing for business and vacation
travelers on airlines. Few people would argue that restaurants,
theaters, or airlines are monopolies. Hence, texts suggest that price
discrimination is a pure monopoly phenomenon, then proceed to provide
examples in which monopoly is dubious at best and ludicrous at worst.
Those texts that focus on the antitrust issues summarize legislation pertaining to regulation of anticompetitive behaviors and
defenses that business can use if charged with illegal price
discrimination. Students reading from this group of texts get little
information on the conditions under which price discrimination may
occur, that there are several varieties of price discrimination, or the
likely effects of these pricing schemes on economic efficiency and
income distribution. In other words, students get little indication that
economic theory has anything to contribute in this policy area.
Similar problems with the treatment of price discrimination arise
in some Intermediate microeconomics texts. For example, Landsburg (1998,
p. 361) defines price discrimination as "the act of charging
different prices for identical items"; Nicholson (1997, p. 305)
defines price discrimination as "selling identical units of output
at different prices"; and both suggest that price discrimination is
exclusively a monopoly phenomenon. Pindyck and Rubinfeld (1998) make no
mention of cost differences in their treatment of price discrimination,
but Ekelund and Ault (1995) do. Mansfield (1997) notes that differences
in prices are not sufficient to show price discrimination but makes no
mention of efficiency effects. He also indicates that price
discrimination can occur whenever a firm has some market power, as do
Pindyck and Rubinfeld (1998), Browning and Zupan (1999), and Perloff
(1999). Hirshleifer and Hirshleifer (1998) discuss the importance of
market segmentation, using the example of differences in the prices of
Japanese cars sold in the United States and those sold in Japan. In the
context of a chapter on monopoly, as it is presented, the discussion is
likely to confuse students who are well aware of the existence of
multiple car manufacturers from both the United States and Japan.
This article provides some suggestions for teaching price
discrimination and for providing examples that should avoid confusion
and give students a better understanding of the important issues. Our
discussion of price discrimination focuses on three areas: (i) the
definition of price discrimination, (ii) situations or conditions in
which price discrimination occurs, and (iii) the effects of price
discrimination.
2. Definition of Price Discrimination
Popular textbooks on industrial organization define price
discrimination as differences in the ratio of price to marginal cost across buyers or units of a good.(1) One form of price discrimination is
the practice of a firm charging multiple prices for the same good where
the difference in price is not attributable to a corresponding
difference in cost. This definition implies that different observed
prices for apparently identical goods need not be discriminatory.
Another form of price discrimination is the practice of a firm charging
the same price for all units of the same good when there are cost
variations in supply. This implies that observed identical prices for
apparently identical goods may be discriminatory. Cost differences, not
simply price differences, must be considered.
Lott and Roberts (1991) make this point forcefully by carefully
examining four commonly used "examples" of price
discrimination: the spreads in retail gasoline prices, the prices of
dinners at restaurants, the price of popcorn at movie theaters, and the
variation of airline ticket prices with time between ticket purchase and
flight date. They show that cost differences, particularly opportunity
cost differences, may explain the price differences. Their examples may
not necessarily be convincing, however, because one can reasonably
dispute whether the "goods,' sold at different prices are
really the same thing. For example, Lott and Roberts (1991) explain why
the price of dinner in a restaurant may be higher than the lunch time
price of the same food; the time spent at the table is longer for dinner
than for lunch, so the higher dinner price represents the greater
opportunity cost of tying up the table. Yet eating lunch, with its
particular set of accompanying services, is probably not a close
substitute for eating dinner, which may have a very different set of
accompanying services. The possibility that these two meals may be very
differently bundled presents a more complicated pricing situation, along
the lines of second-degree price discrimination. In this type of
situation, where marginal cost is difficult to determine, the usual
definitions of price-marginal cost ratios or differentials may be
insufficient to rule out the possibility of price discrimination.(2)
The more standard example of price discrimination at a restaurant
is that of senior citizen discounts. In this case, two diners at the
same table ordering exactly the same meal will face different prices if
one carries an American Association of Retired Persons card but the
other does not. Lott and Roberts' opportunity cost explanation for
different prices does not work for this example. Nonetheless, Lott and
Roberts (1991) have succeeded in showing that there may be subtle cost
differences that justify price differences in situations where one may
be tempted to claim the existence of price discrimination.
Even though price discrimination occurs when price-marginal cost
ratios differ across either units or buyers of a good, not all price
discrimination is the same. Different types of price discrimination have
been identified, each with different implications and distinct
characteristics. In fact, two distinct, but related, taxonomies of price
discrimination exist.(3) The most common taxonomy of price
discrimination identifies first-, second-, and third-degree price
discrimination.
First-degree price discrimination occurs when a different price is
charged for each and every unit offered for sale. The seller is able to
set price on each unit at the maximum that some buyer is willing and
able to pay.(4) The seller is in a position to make a
"take-it-or-leave-it" offer to the buyers of the good or to
bargain the buyer to his or her reservation price. Sellers are unlikely
to have this level of information in many situations. One famous, if
controversial, example of first-degree price discrimination is William
Niskanen's (1971) model of the relationship between bureaus and
Congress. Niskanen gives bureaucrats the ability and the desire to make
"take-it-or-leave-it" offers to Congress. Niskanen's
bureaucrats then capture all of the surplus in the form of budget
allocation associated with provision of public services.(5) Another
example of individual unit pricing would be a situation where the seller
deals individually with each buyer and can "size" him up and
price accordingly, such as in auto or insurance sales.
Second-degree price discrimination encompasses a variety of pricing
schemes through which the firm is able to induce consumers with high
valuations to pay higher prices than consumers with low valuations.
Second-degree price discrimination schemes induce consumers to
self-select into groups based on their willingness to pay. Firms do not
have the consumers' valuation information in this case, as they do
under first-degree discrimination, nor do they have information that
would enable them to identify high- versus low-demand individuals as
under third-degree discrimination. For example, the firm might know that
there are two groups of buyers of its product. The first group will buy
a great deal of the good if the price for the marginal unit is low
enough; the second group will buy only a small amount of the good no
matter what the price. Unfortunately for the seller, he or she does not
know which group any specific buyer is in. One form of second-degree
price discrimination is the offer of quantity or volume discounts: the
price per unit falls after the purchase of some preset number of
units.(6) Another form of second-degree price discrimination is the
two-part tariff. Under a two-part tariff, consumers pay a lump sum fee
and a per-unit charge.(7) In each of these cases, buyers
"self-select" into the pricing arrangement best for them and
best for the seller, besides.
Other examples of second-degree price discrimination include tie-in
sales and quality choices. In these cases, the firm determines the
profit-maximizing prices of multiple products simultaneously. For
example, if a firm sells two products that are highly complementary,
then it will choose the prices on each to take advantage of that
complementarity. Alternatively, the firm might produce the same good in
different qualities. By carefully choosing the quality difference, the
firm can effectively segment the market into two groups, those whose
valuation is high and those whose valuation is low. The firm can then
charge a high price to the former and a lower price to the latter, even
after accounting for production and delivery cost differences. These may
be among the most frequent instances of price discrimination.
Third-degree price discrimination is based on characteristics of
the consumer or group of consumers. Firms recognize that some consumers
are more sensitive to price than are others. Moreover, firms can
separate consumers into either group through some easily or costlessly
identifiable trait of the consumer. For example, students may be
identified by asking for a student identification card; senior citizens
by presentation of an American Association of Retired Persons card or a
driver's license. Those whose demand for movies is insensitive to
price may show up to see first-run movies at their premiers; individuals
with more sensitive demand may wait until later to see the film in
low-cost venues or on video. Prices in each of these instances may well
differ for different consumers even after accounting for cost
differences.(8) Third-degree price discrimination is clearly "group
discrimination."
The distinctions drawn between price discrimination of the varying
degrees may seem arbitrary, but in fact these distinctions are important
for two reasons. First, they are based on different information
requirements for the seller. Second, the distinctions are important
because the different types of discrimination have different
implications for economic efficiency and income distribution. Principles
textbooks frequently describe and show efficiency implications of only
one type of discrimination (first degree) then follow with an example of
a different type (third degree), as in Gwartney and Stroup (1995),
Taylor (1995), Lipsey and Courant (1996), McConnell and Brue (1996), and
Parkin (1996). Students are then likely to come away with mistaken
impressions of the policy implications of price discrimination. We noted
earlier that a common textbook application of price discrimination is
the difference in prices charged to business travelers and vacation
travelers who use airline services. This is clearly an example of price
discrimination by consumer group (third degree), if it is price
discrimination at all.(9) The same texts, however, explain the
efficiency effects of (this third-degree) price discrimination only in
terms of first-degree (perfect) price discrimination. In addition to the
efficiency differences that result from output restrictions that may
occur across the different types of price discrimination, there are
various inefficiencies that may result because not all consumers pay the
same price for the product. Suppose consumer A can purchase additional
units of the product at a price discount compared to consumer B. If
B's willingness to pay for another unit is higher than that of A,
there exist gains to be had from A buying at the low price and selling
to B at a price below the price B faces but greater than the price A
pays. Because resale is not possible, this represents an additional
efficiency loss that occurs when consumers are separated into groups, as
in second- and third-degree price discrimination. If the differences
between the types of discrimination are not presented, then students may
easily be confused into believing that second- and third-degree price
discriminations are efficient.
We believe that a fruitful and less confusing approach is to give
greater emphasis to the conditions required for price discrimination to
be possible. Because the conditions vary slightly between types,
students can be shown how slight differences in the economic or business
environment have repercussions for economic efficiency and policy
implications. With this as motivation, we now turn to a discussion of
the conditions for price discrimination.
3. Conditions for Price Discrimination
For a firm to practice price discrimination, three conditions are
necessary. First, the firm must not be a price taker, it must have some
market power.(10) Even the slightest market power implies that the firm
faces a negatively sloped demand curve for its product. Consequently,
price discrimination can occur under both oligopoly and monopolistic
competition, as well as pure monopoly. The downward sloping demand curve
for the firms's product means that there is consumer surplus
arising from the transactions. Price discrimination is the firm's
attempt to capture some of this surplus for itself.
Price discrimination also requires that the firm can control the
sale of its product. If arbitrage is possible, the law of one price
holds; that is, those who face the low price can purchase the product
and sell it at a profit to those facing the higher price, Resale may be
prevented by the nature of the commodity or via licensing agreements,
copyrights' or other legal impediments to resale. If a seller
charges a higher per-unit price to large buyers than to small buyers,
the firm must prevent multiple purchases at a low price by a single
buyer, say, by imposing quantity limitations. Services such as haircuts,
physical examinations, or legal advice, are likely examples of goods for
which price discrimination is possible because of the obvious difficulty
in reselling them or in making multiple purchases.
A third requirement often cited for price discrimination is that
consumers have different price elasticities of demand for the good or
service. The extent to which the firm knows or correctly infers the
demand behavior of buyers largely determines which degree of price
discrimination is possible. For example, if the firm knows each and
every individual buyer's demand curve perfectly, then the firm can
set price on each unit to entice that buyer with the highest willingness
to pay into a purchase. This is clearly first-degree price
discrimination. If the firm knows only of the existence of buyers with
high willingness to pay and buyers with low willingness to pay, then it
can offer quantity discounts or use tie-in sales to capture some of the
consumer surplus created by the transactions. These are instances of
second-degree price discrimination or nonlinear pricing. Finally, if the
firm knows that elasticity is related to some identifiable group
characteristic, then it can use third-degree price discrimination to
induce the price-insensitive buyers to pay a high price and
price-sensitive buyers to pay a low price for the good. This is
third-degree price discrimination.
The informational requirements for the three types of price
discrimination vary. Under first-degree price discrimination a great
deal of information must be known about individual buyers. Second-degree
price discrimination relaxes that assumption substantially, allowing
firms only to know that some buyers have high willingness and others low
willingness to pay. By pricing specific quantifies of the good
differentially or by attaching some other condition to the purchase of
the good (tie-ins, for example), second-degree price discrimination
induces the individuals to reveal to which class they belong. At the
same time, second-degree price discrimination does not require the
seller to have sufficient information prior to the transaction to guess
which people belong in which category. Under third-degree discrimination
the seller does have that kind of information; to wit, the seller can
identify those with unresponsive demand based on some readily observable characteristic, such as some sociodemographic trait. This characteristic
separates this "group" for differential pricing.
Understanding the differential informational requirements, one can
then examine how the differences influence economic efficiency, income
distribution, and policy implications. We turn now to efficiency and
distribution considerations.
4. Effects of Price Discrimination
Price discrimination affects efficiency and distribution, but the
specific effects depend on the type of price discrimination practiced by
the firm. Moreover, because the type of discrimination that is possible
depends on the availability of information, the efficiency and
distribution under price discrimination is linked to this availability
of information. Regardless of the type of price discrimination, however,
it is profitable for a firm to engage in this practice. This
profitability arises from the seller extracting consumer surplus from
the buyers that it could not get if it did not have market power and
control over sale or resale and if buyers' price elasticities were
identical.
The efficiency effects depend on the type of price discrimination
practiced by the firm, and this depends on what the firm knows, or can
learn, about the buyers' price elasticities. When a firm practices
first-degree price discrimination, it is profitable to expand output to
the point where price equals marginal cost. The firm, recall, knows the
maximum willingness to pay of every individual buyer. Consequently, it
offers a unit for sale only if the most anyone will pay for it is at
least the marginal cost of producing that unit. On every unit for which
the maximum willingness to pay exceeds marginal cost, the firm captures
the entire difference as its own. On the last unit offered for sale, the
firm makes no profit because marginal cost equals price. But marginal
cost equal to price is precisely the condition for maximizing net social
gain from this market (that is, in partial equilibrium). In other words,
when the firm has full and perfect information about consumer demands,
then price discrimination improves efficiency. This added efficiency
comes at the cost of transferring all the gains from trade from
consumers to the firm.
Under third-degree price discrimination, the firm knows that
identifiable groups have different price elasticities of demand. The
firm does not know, however, the maximum willingness to pay of each
member within each group. Therefore, the firm must select a single price
for each group. Because each group faces a given price, and assuming the
group's demand curve is downward sloping, the group members will
derive consumer surplus from the purchase of this good that the firm
cannot extract. Additionally, because the firm must select a single
price for each group, it will select the price by equating marginal
revenue to marginal cost. But because marginal revenue is less than
price, there is allocative inefficiency. Relative to first-degree price
discrimination then, third-degree price discrimination is less efficient
but leaves consumers with some consumer surplus.
The exact efficiency effects under third-degree price
discrimination depend on the shapes of the cost and demand curves. With
straight-line demand curves and constant costs, as are typically found
in Principles books, output does not increase over the level of the
nondiscriminating firm.(11) Rather, relative to the nondiscriminating
firm, the profit maximizing output is simply redistributed among
consumers. In this situation, any deadweight loss that had existed with
no discrimination still exists, by which we mean that the gap between
marginal willingness to pay for one more unit and marginal cost of
producing one more unit is the same. There is, however, an additional
welfare cost caused by the allocation of the good from those whose
willingness to pay is higher to those whose willingness to pay is lower.
In other words, in this case, third-degree price discrimination is not
only less efficient than first-degree price discrimination, it is also
less efficient than no price discrimination (Schmalensee, 1981; Varian,
1985). However, social welfare may increase under third-degree price
discrimination, over nondiscrimination, if output increases. Note that
output increasing is a necessary condition for welfare to increase, not
a sufficient condition. The intuition of this is straightforward.
Inefficiency arises under nondiscrimination because price exceeds
marginal cost - output is too low. If output rises under discrimination,
then the inefficiency arising from producing too little output is
reduced. At the same time, however, price discrimination puts a wedge
between the marginal valuations of different consumers, which means that
there are uncaptured gains from trade - an efficiency loss. Whether the
gain in efficiency from increased output is sufficient to offset the
loss in efficiency from the wedge between marginal valuations depends on
the precise shapes of the cost and demand curves.
Table 1. Price Discrimination - Numerical Example
Marginal Marginal
Quantity Revenue 1 Price 1 Revenue 2 Price 2
1 24.5 24.75 46 48
2 24 24.5 42 46
3 23.5 24.25 38 44
4 23 24 34 42
5 22.5 23.75 30 40
6 22 23.5 26 38
7 21.5 23.25 22 36
8 21 23 18 34
9 20.5 22.75 14 32
10 20 22.5 10 30
11 19.5 22.25 6 28
12 19 22 2 26
13 18.5 21.75 -2 24
14 18 21.5 -6 22
15 17.5 21.25 -10 20
16 17 21 -14 18
17 16.5 20.75 -18 16
18 16 20.5 -22 14
19 15.5 20.25 -26 12
20 15 20 -30 10
Demand in market 1: [Q.sub.1] = 100 - 4[P.sub.1]. Demand in market
2: [Q.sub.2] = 25 - 0.5[P.sub.2].
Table 1 provides a numerical example that clarifies the efficiency
and distributional differences between first- and third-degree price
discrimination, a nondiscriminating monopolist, and competition. The
alternative outcomes are illustrated in Figure 1.(12) Assume that the
marginal cost is constant at $20. In a perfectly competitive market,
output is 35 units and price is $20 per unit - equal in value to
marginal cost - each firm earns zero economic profit, and consumer
surplus is $275. Consumers of type 1 get $50 of the consumer surplus,
consumers of type 2 get $225. The nondiscriminating monopoly model would
find a market price of $24, a total quantity of 17.5 units, and profit
of $70. Consumer surplus is reduced to about $172.70, with consumers of
type 1 getting $2.40 and consumers of type 2 getting $170.30. In this
single-price monopoly case, the sum of profit and consumer surplus is
$242.70, so the dead weight loss is $32.30.
The first-degree price discriminator would sell the first 12 units
produced to buyers in market 2, where buyers are willing to pay more
than are buyers from market 1. The firm sells in market 2 at prices
starting at $48 for the first unit and declining to $26 for the 12th
unit, before selling even the first unit in market 1. This is so because
the price at which each of these first 12 units can sell in market 2 is
higher than the price the monopolist can get for even the first unit in
market 1. Indeed, for the first-degree discriminator, who prices each
unit individually, the market demand curve is the marginal revenue
curve. The seller is thus able to extract all of the consumer surplus on
each unit sold and earn a total profit of $275. The total sold by the
first-degree discriminator is 35:20 to market 1 and 15 to market 2. Note
that the price of the last unit sold in each market equals the marginal
cost, [P.sub.1] = [P.sub.2] = MC = $20. Hence, the first-degree
discriminator sells the efficient (competitive) quantity. Moreover, the
price charged on the last unit sold is at or above the maximum any
individual is willing to pay for another unit, so there are no
uncaptured gains from trade between consumers. The firm captures all of
the consumer surplus.
The third-degree price discriminator will sell a total of 17.5
units, just as in the nondiscriminating monopoly model. Because
production is the same level as in the nondiscriminating monopoly, there
is no reallocation of resources into the production of this good, as
occurs with first-degree price discrimination, so allocative
inefficiency continues. The third-degree discriminator divides this 17.5
units of output across the two markets, selling 10 units in market 1 at
a price of $22.50/unit and 7.5 units in market 2 at a price of $35/unit,
for a total profit of $137.50. This profit is less than could be made if
the seller was a perfect price discriminator, but more than can be
earned with no price discrimination at all. Consumer surplus is $68.75,
with type 1 consumers getting $12.50 and type 2 consumers $56.25. The
total of consumer surplus and profit in this case is $206.25. Note that
the dead weight loss (= $68.75) has risen relative to the single-price
monopoly situation. In addition, there exist uncaptured gains from trade
as buyers from market 2 would gladly pay buyers from market 1 more than
$22.50 to acquire another unit of the good. Because the firm controls
sale of the product, such exchanges do not occur.(13) For this reason,
greater inefficiency occurs in the third-degree case than under the
nondiscriminating monopoly model, despite the fact that the same
quantity of the good is sold in both situations. If the cost and demand
curves result in an expansion of output beyond that offered in the pure
monopoly model, as might occur if marginal cost is upward sloping,
efficiency may or may not be increased, depending on the gains from
increased output compared to the losses from reallocation of output from
low-valued to high-valued consumers (Schmalensee 1981; Varian 1985).(14)
The efficiency of second-degree price discrimination, relative to
nondiscrimination, depends on whether output increases and on the losses
incurred from introducing different marginal valuations across
consumers. This efficiency will also depend on what type of
second-degree discrimination is possible. Consider two examples. In the
first example, firms allow consumers to select between different
two-part tariff schemes. In the second example, firms use quantity
discounts.
The first example is similar to memberships in warehouse shopping
clubs. The consumer can join with one of two different types of
membership. Under the less expensive membership, posted prices are not
discounted, whereas under the more expensive membership, posted prices
are discounted at 10%. By selecting a membership, consumers reveal
information about their demand - information that the firm would not
have had otherwise. The membership fees transfer consumer surplus to the
firm. The differential pricing induces inefficiency by creating a gap
between the marginal valuations of different consumers. Under this
scheme, it seems probable that sales are increased. Output will increase
if the undiscounted prices are not too much higher and the discounted
prices are sufficiently lower than the nondiscriminatory prices. But if
the prices faced by those holding low-valued memberships are not lower
than the nondiscriminatory prices, which may still be available at other
nonwarehouse stores, then it is unclear why anyone would buy these
memberships. Therefore, it seems likely that price under either
membership plan will be lower than under nondiscrimination and that
output will increase. However, output is not likely to rise to the
competitive level. If the discounted prices equal marginal cost, then
the firm sells to the holders of high-priced memberships the same
quantity they would purchase under competition. But the holders of the
low-priced memberships face a price higher than marginal cost, so they
will purchase fewer units than under competition. Sales fall short of
the competitive level. In other words, this type of second-degree price
discrimination may be more efficient than nondiscrimination but is
certainly less efficient than either competition or first-degree
discrimination. This type of discrimination also enables firms to
capture a large measure of the consumer surplus - certainly more than
under nondiscrimination, although whether more than under third-degree
discrimination is not generally determinable.
The second example of second-degree price discrimination is the
case of quantity discounts. The second-degree price discriminator could
set the higher price at the monopoly price and the lower price at the
competitive price. Net social welfare rises because output rises
relative to the pure monopoly situation, although it still falls short
of the competitive output, unless those facing the higher price would
not have purchased any additional units at the lower price. At the same
time, because not all consumers pay the same price for the product,
there remain uncaptured gains from trade - an efficiency loss. Moreover,
it is uncertain whether the lost welfare from these misallocations of
the good away from high-value consumers to low-value consumers is
greater than or less than the welfare loss from the simple monopoly
case. However, under this scheme the firm is unable to capture consumer
surplus that consumers derive from purchases at these prices, unlike the
two-part tariff example. This type of second-degree price discrimination
is, therefore, more akin to third- than to first-degree price
discrimination.
Generally then, the efficiency and distributional effects of
second-degree price discrimination, relative to the pure monopoly
situation, depend on a number of factors. First, the shapes of the cost
and demand curves are important. Steeply rising marginal cost, for
example, implies smaller dead weight loss in the pure monopoly
situation, all other things constant, than in the constant marginal cost
case. In this case, the difference between the pure monopoly price and
the competitive price is small, so the gap between the willingness of
high-value and of low-value consumers to pay is likely to be small.
Therefore, price differentials would tend to cause relatively little
inefficiency, arising from the lack of resale possibilities. The
increased net benefit from increasing output would, therefore, tend to
raise overall efficiency.
Second, the effects will vary with the specific second-degree price
discrimination strategy the seller employs. Which strategy is
appropriate will depend on the nature of the good and the number and
closeness of substitutes for it. For example, in the two-part tariff
case, the consumer generally has few opportunities to decide to purchase
the good, and there are few close substitutes. The permanent seat
license (PSL) pricing scheme used by professional sports teams is a good
example. Few cities have multiple franchises in any given sport, so
there are few substitutes. Season ticket purchases are rare, made only
once every year in the absence of PSLs and only once a lifetime with
PSLs. Given the lack of substitutes, lumpiness of the good, and
infrequent purchases, the firm can use the two-part tariff scheme. Not
too many years ago, long distance telephone service would have been a
similar example. Consumers generally selected a long distance carrier
once. Now, the competition among long distance services can have
consumers changing carriers frequently, with the fee portion of the
two-part tariff approaching zero for most customers.(15) In effect, the
two-part tariff works well when the choice the consumer faces is between
being able to purchase the good and not being able to purchase it and
there are no close substitutes for the good.
Quantity discounts as a pricing scheme works well when there are
close substitutes for the good and consumers make repeated purchases.
Frequent flyer plans are a good example. There are several airlines from
which to choose, and those who travel by plane often do so several times
a year. The consumer has several opportunities to choose, or not choose,
any given airline. Quantity discounts provide the consumer an added
incentive to choose the same airline each time.
5. Concluding remarks
We began this paper with a criticism of the style and approach of
teaching price discrimination found in Principles texts. In this
section, we propose a method for presenting price discrimination that
would spark student interest in the application of economic theory to
policy and, at the same time, create the least confusion possible.
(i) Price discrimination can be defined in a more general way as a
variation in the price-cost ratio, or differentials, across units or
across groups of buyers. The advantages of this definition are, first,
that it is more accurate and, second, that it encompasses alternative
forms that price discrimination may take. This definition thus
incorporates examples of multiple pricing when costs do not differ (such
as selling the identical vehicle to two different buyers at two
different prices), and single pricing when costs do differ (such as
shipping the same good to two different buyers at different locations
and cost but at the same delivered price).
(ii) Provide information about the three necessary conditions for
price discrimination to occur.
(iii) Explain that there are three types of price discrimination
and that the type of discrimination that occurs depends upon the level
of information held by firms.
(iv) Emphasize that the different types of price discrimination
have different implications for economic efficiency. One way to do this
is through a numerical example in the form of a table or diagram, as
presented here. In addition, use of the diagram or table emphasizes the
important differences between the competitive outcome, the monopoly
outcome, and the outcomes of the different types (degrees) of price
discrimination. Moreover, the numerical example can be used to discuss
the inefficiency of third-degree discrimination that arises when buyers
pay different prices for the marginal unit purchased.
(v) Address issues of distribution, particularly since the
price-discriminating firm gains profit by acquiring surplus from
consumers. This also can be illustrated through a numerical example, as
we have shown here.
(vi) Discuss the practical difficulties of identifying price
discrimination. Students should be made aware of the importance of price
differences that are not explained by cost differences, the role of
opportunity cost, and the important issues of market definition.
Price discrimination is complex. Often, in the attempt to simplify,
the.explanation actually provides misleading or incorrect information.
We believe, however, that price discrimination can be presented at the
introductory and intermediate levels in a way that is correct, yet
simpler and less confusing than we currently observe, so that students
are not faced with misleading information.
It is clearly inappropriate to attribute the practice of
differential pricing to monopoly; price discrimination may arise in any
market in which firms are not price takers and they therefore have even
a small amount of market power. Situations of multiple pricing may
reflect any number of economic situations other than price
discrimination, such as problems in market definition, the existence of
opportunity costs not accounted for explicitly by the firm, a situation
of competitive behavior indicating the absence of market power, or the
presence of an alternative market imperfection, such as asymmetric
information.
The treatment of price discrimination is less misleading if it is
presented as both a theoretical issue and a policy issue. The
theoretical issue is concerned with the behavior that leads to the
efficiency and distributional effects of price discrimination. This
requires distinguishing between the two basic types (price
discrimination by unit and by consumer group) and clearly stating the
conditions required in each case, so that students know what the
practice is and when it can occur. The policy issue involves both
antitrust and regulatory policy. Either or both can be examined to help
students understand the meaning of social efficiency and the distinction
between efficiency and distribution.
Examples of price discrimination are pedagogically helpful.
Students like them and they have most likely had some experience with
many of them. Providing examples classified according to price
discrimination by unit (first and second degree), and price
discrimination by consumer group (third degree) would be consistent with
presentation of theory as we outline above, and clearer to students.
Many students do not fully understand the concept of efficiency as
social efficiency. Often students believe that if a firm increases
profit it is doing better, so it must be efficient. This is the case if
a firm is able to lower its cost and thereby increase its profit; it is
not necessarily the case when profit is increased by other
circumstances. Witness the increase in a firm's profit with a
collusive agreement that replaces interfirm competition, or with
third-degree price discrimination with no corresponding increase in
output. Although this profitable behavior may be "efficient"
for the firm (i.e., privately efficient) it is not socially efficient.
Discussion of price discrimination is a good opportunity to make this
distinction.
Appendix
Note: All results are rounded.
Given: Demand of type 1 buyers: [Q.sub.1] = 100 - 4[P.sub.1]
Demand of type 2 buyers: [Q.sub.2] - 25 - 0.5[P.sub.2]
Long-run supply (S) = marginal cost = $20
1. Perfectly competitive market
Single demand:
[Q.sub.T] = [Q.sub.1] + [Q.sub.2] = (100 - 4[P.sub.1]) + (25 -
0.5[P.sub.2]) = 125 - 4.5P
Therefore, inverted demand (D):
P = 27.8 - 0.224[Q.sub.T] and MR = 27.8 - 0.448[Q.sub.T]
Perfectly competitive equilibrium:
D = S
27.8 - 0.224[Q.sub.T] = 20
[Q.sub.T] = 35
[P.sub.c] = $20
Profit = 0
Consumer surplus = $275
Dead weight loss = 0
Note that, with constant costs, economic profit for each firm is
also zero.
2. Nondiscriminating firm with market power
Demand:
[Q.sub.T] = [Q.sub.1] + [Q.sub.2] = (100- 4[P.sub.1] + (25 -
0.5[P.sub.2]) = 125 - 4.5P
Therefore, inverted demand (D):
P = 27.8 - 0.224[Q.sub.T] and MR = 27.8 - 0.448[Q.sub.T]
Nondiscriminating equilibrium:
MR = MC
27.8 - 0.448[Q.sub.T] = 20
[Q.sub.ND] = 17.5
[P.sub.ND] = $24
Profit of nondiscriminating firm = $70
Consumer surplus = $172.70
Dead weight loss = $32.30
3. First-degree (perfect)price discrimination
Demand:
[Q.sub.T] = [Q.sub.T] + [Q.sub.2] = (100 - 4[P.sub.1] + (25 -
0.5[P.sub.2]) = 125 - 4.5P
Therefore, inverted demand (D):
P = 27.8 - 0.224[Q.sub.T] = [MR.sub.1stPD]
Perfect price-discriminating firm equilibrium:
[MR.sub.1stPD] = MC
27.8 - 0.224[Q.sub.T] = 20
[Q.sub.1stPD] = 35
Profit for first-degree price-discriminating firm = $275.25 (=
total consumer surplus)
Consumer surplus = 0
Dead weight loss = 0
4. Third-degree price discrimination
Demand of type 1 buyers: [Q.sub.1] = 100 - 4[P.sub.1]
Demand of type 2 buyers: [Q.sub.2] = 25 - 0.5[P.sub.2]
Inverted demand ([D.sub.1]): [P.sub.1] = 25 -
0.25[Q.sub.1][MR.sub.1] = 25 - 0.5[Q.sub.1]
Inverted demand ([D.sub.2]): [P.sub.2] = 50 - 2[Q.sub.2] [MR.sub.2]
= 50 - 4[Q.sub.2]
Third-degree price-discriminating equilibrium by buyer type:
[MR.sub.1] = MC [MR.sub.2] = MC
25 - 0.5[Q.sub.1] = 20 50 - 4[Q.sub.2] = 20
[Q.sub.1] = 10 [Q.sub.2] = 7.5
[P.sub.1] = $22.50 [P.sub.2] = $35
Consumer surplus (C[S.sub.1]) = $12.50
Consumer surplus ([CS.sub.2]) = $56.25
Note that [Q.sub.1] + [Q.sub.2] = 17.5 = [Q.sub.M] and that total
consumer surplus = $68.75
Profit for third-degree discriminating firm:
[TR.sub.1] = $225 [TR.sub.2] = $262.50
Total cost of all output (TC) = $20(17.5) = $350
[Profit.sub.3rdPD] = [TR.sub.1] + [TR.sub.2] = TC = $225 + $262.50
- $350 = $137.50 [greater than] [Profit.sub.ND] = $70
Dead weight loss ([DWL.sub.3rdPD]) = $68.75 [greater than]
([DWL.sub.ND]) = $32.30
Note also that [Profit.sub.3rdPD] = $137.50 [less than]
[Profit.sub.1stPD] = $275.25
The authors thank Michael Bradley, Jonathan Hamilton, and an
anonymous referee for helpful comments on an earlier draft of the paper.
1 Scherer and Ross (1990), Shepherd (1997), and Shugart (1997) each
use this definition of price discrimination. In addition, Viscusi et al.
(1992) define price discrimination this way in their text on regulation
and antitrust. An alternative definition of price discrimination
compares the difference between the price and the marginal cost of a
good across buyers or units of the good. If this difference is measured
as a proportion of the sale price, then the resulting value is the
Lerner index. Both this definition of price discrimination and the one
stated in the text may be overly restrictive. Carlton and Perloff (1994)
use the term more broadly to include any pricing scheme in which the
firm is able to increase its profit over that earned from a single
price. These schemes raise profits because they enable the firm to
charge more to consumers who are willing to pay more and charge less to
consumers who value the product less.
2 It is in more complex pricing situations such as this that the
broader definition of price discrimination suggested by Carlton and
Perloff (1994) may be appropriate.
3 The first taxonomy, by Fritz Machlup (1952), listed several
different types of price discrimination, summarized by Shepherd (1990).
The three types described by Machlup are: personal discrimination, in
which the firm tailors price to the specific buyer; group
discrimination, wherein identifiable groups are charged different
prices; and product differentiation, which involves different prices
charged for identical goods over time, say through end-of-season sales.
4 This situation is much like the "personal
discrimination" of Machlup (1952) and Shepherd (1990) because the
seller must know or be able to learn very specific information about
every consumer to be able to set the highest attainable price on every
unit.
5 Many authors have questioned the accuracy of Niskanen's (197
l) assumptions with regard to the power and information available to
Congress and the bureaus.
6 It is important to note that some discounts arise because the
costs per unit of large-volume transactions are smaller than those from
small-volume transactions. Such cases are not instances of price
discrimination.
7 Interestingly, Shepherd (1990) includes the case of charging
heavy users more for the product as a type of second-degree price
discrimination.
8 These examples beg the question of whether the goods are really
identical. We defer discussion of this point to section 3.
9 Recall that this is one of the examples in Lott and Roberts
(1991). Their argument is that the different prices faced by different
travelers may reflect cost differences and, therefore, are not
necessarily evidence of price discrimination.
10 In monopolistically competitive markets, firms compete not on
price but other concerns such as quality, accessibility, or service.
These firms are not price takers, however. Therefore, we describe them
as having some market power.
11 Lipsey and Courant (1996, p. 230), after defining price
discrimination where a "seller can either distinguish individual
units bought by a single buyer or separate buyers into classes . .
.," state as a proposition that "output under price
discrimination will generally be larger than under single-price
monopoly" (p. 231). Students in an introductory course, where
straight-line demand curves and constant costs are employed (as in the
Lipsey and Courant text) would then believe that all types of price
discrimination are efficient.
12 Algebraic solutions to this problem are presented in the
appendix.
13 We are indebted to our colleague Mike Bradley for suggesting
antiscalping laws as an example in which gains from trade are not
captured because resale is impossible. This effect is strengthened when
the firm controls sale by limiting quantities to any one original buyer.
14 In our example, where marginal cost is constant, output does not
increase with third-degree price discrimination.
15 There are costs associated with switching carriers, although in
some cases, these may be avoided. One of the authors recently changed
from ATT to MCI and hack to ATT in less than two weeks, getting no
monthly fee and 30 minutes of free long distance service per month for
six months. The companies even provided vouchers for the switching
costs.
References
Baumol, William J., and Alan S. Blinder. 1994. Microeconomics:
Principles and policy. Fort Worth, TX: The Dryden Press.
Browning, Edgar K., and Mark A. Zupan. 1999. Microeconomic theory
& applications, 6th edition. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
Carlton, Dennis W., and Jeffrey M. Perloff. 1994. Modern industrial
organization. 2nd edition. New York: Harper Collins College Publishers.
Ekelund, Robert B., Jr., and Richard Ault. 1995. Intermediate
microeconomics: Price theory and applications. Lexington, MA: D.C. Heath and Company.
Gwartney, James D., and Richard L. Stroup. 1995. Microeconomics:
Private and public choice. Fort Worth, TX: The Dryden Press.
Hirshleifer, Jack, and David Hirshleifer. 1998. Price theory and
applications. 6th edition. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice-Hall, Inc.
Landsburg, Steven E. 1998. Price theory & applications. 4th
edition. Cincinnati, OH: South-Western College Publishing.
Lipsey, Richard G., and Paul N. Courant. 1996. Microeconomics. New
York: Harper Collins Publishers, Inc.
Lott, John R. Jr., and Russell D. Roberts. 1991. A guide to the
pitfalls of identifying price discrimination. Economic Inquiry 29:14-23.
Machlup, Fritz. 1952. The political economy of monopoly. Baltimore,
MD: The Johns Hopkins University Press.
Mansfield, Edwin. 1992. Principles of microeconomics. New York: W.
W. Norton & Company.
Mansfield, Edwin. 1997. Applied microeconomics. 2nd edition. New
York: W. W. Norton & Company, Inc.
McConnell, Campbell R., and Stanley L. Brue. 1996. Microeconomics.
New York: McGraw-Hill, Inc.
Miller, Roger LeRoy. 1994. Economics today: The micro view. New
York: Harper Collins College Publishers.
Nicholson, Walter E. 1997. Intermediate microeconomics and its
application. 7th edition. Fort Worth, TX: The Dryden Press.
Niskanen, William A., Jr. 1971. Bureaucracy and representative
government. Chicago: Aldine-Atherton.
Parkin, Michael. 1996. Microeconomics. New York: Addison-Wesley
Publishing Company.
Perloff, Jeffrey M. 1999. Microeconomics. Reading, MA:
Addison-Wesley.
Pindyck, Robert S., and Daniel L. Rubinfeld. 1998. Microeconomics.
4th edition. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice-Hall, Inc.
Samuelson, Paul A., and William D. Nordhans. 1995. Microeconomics.
New York: McGraw-Hill, Inc.
Scherer, F. M., and David Ross. 1990. Industrial market structure
and economic performance. 3rd edition. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company.
Schmalansee, Richard. 1981. Output and welfare implications of
monopolistic third-degree price discrimination. American Economic Review
March:242-7.
Shepherd, William G. 1990. The economics of industrial
organization. 3rd edition. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, Inc.
Shepherd, William G. 1997. The economics of industrial
organization. 4th edition. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, Inc.
Shugart, William F. II. 1997. The organization of industry. 2nd
edition. Houston, TX: Dame Publications, Inc.
Taylor, John B. 1995. Economics. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company.
Tresch, Richard W. 1994. Principles of microeconomics.
Minneapolis/Saint Paul: West Publishing Company.
Varian, Hal R. 1985. Price discrimination and social welfare.
American Economic Review September:870-5.
Viscusi, W. Kip, John M. Vernon, and Joseph E. Harrington, Jr.
1992. Economics of regulation and antitrust. Lexington, MA: D.C. Heath
and Company.