Against the Tide: An Intellectual History of Free Trade.
Crucini, Mario J.
By Douglas A. Irwin.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996. Pp. viii, 265.
$29.95.
Irwin's book begins with a quotation of Harry Johnson (1977):
"The proposition that freedom of [international] trade is on the
whole economically more beneficial than protection, is one of the most
fundamental propositions economic theory has to offer for the guidance
of economic policy." Irwin's history chronicles the
theoretical arguments for and against free trade and the emergence of a
consensus in its favor that Johnson's statement so eloquently
summarizes.
The book does not cover the implication of Johnson's statement
for the conduct of commercial policy. As someone with an interest in
both trade theory and commercial policy, I thought I would be cheated
out of half of the story. After reading the book, I have arrived at an
entirely different conclusion. Irwin's decision not to delve into
the history of commercial policy contributes to the clarity of his
message.
The voices that we hear in Against the Tide: An Intellectual History
of Free Trade are recognized as belonging to scholars keenly interested
in their subject matter. What makes this book a joy to read is the sense
that Irwin has assembled everyone in a single room to debate each issue
on its merits. An invitation is extended to an economist yet unborn if
only to ensure an argument progresses or dies a timely death, and an
economist from the past arrives to the chagrin of some whippersnapper who has taken his argument out of context. For the most part, however,
the book follows an historical chronology that is divided into two major
parts.
The first part, titled "Origins of the Free Trade
Doctrine," traces the debate from its origins in the writings of
philosophers, clergy, and political leaders into the mercantilist
literature and ends with the contributions of the classical school. The
second part of the book, "Controversies about the Free Trade
Doctrine," devotes a chapter to each of eight arguments against, or
qualifications of, free trade policy. The final chapter, "The Past
and Future of Free Trade," summarizes the book and places the free
trade debate into a broader context.
The structure of Irwin's book also serves to highlight its two
main conclusions - first, that the writing of the classicists
represented an abrupt improvement in the formalism of economic analysis
and, second, that the forward progress of economic theory eventually
revealed weaknesses in many of the arguments against free trade, eroding
their appeal, while increasing the consensus in favor of free trade.
Frustration will meet readers who choose to search the first few
chapters for economic analysis. I chose a more passive approach and
found historical perspective conveyed in an entertaining manner.
Consider Plato's (1930, p. 153) contribution to international
economics dating from about 380 BC: "The result [of such a
division], then, is that more things are produced, and better and more
easily when one man performs one task according to his nature, at the
right moment, and at leisure from other occupations." Compare this
with the statement by Horace (1960, p. 27) reflecting on God's
apparent lack of foresight: "In vain has God in his wisdom planned
to divide the land by the sea's separation, if, for all that,
ungodly ships are crossing the water that he placed out of bounds,"
and one gets a sense of the diversity of opinion in the earliest
recorded thoughts on foreign commerce.
During the mercantilist period, the debate shifted toward more
pragmatic issues, no doubt influenced by the vast expansion of
international trade. Here, more than elsewhere in the book, Irwin must
carefully navigate the channels separating arguments rooted in
self-interest and economic arguments possessing merit. On occasion, we
see the futility of this endeavor. An example is the widely held view
that a favorable trade balance is desirable in its own right. Was this a
reflection of how a merchant would profit from buying low and selling
high or had mercantilists happened upon an analytical result that total
consumption possibilities were augmented by a favorable trade balance? I
am persuaded by Irwin's account that these are questions to which
we may never know the answers because the analytical details are rarely,
if ever, to be found in the mercantilist's writing. One is left
with the image of an intellectual landscape littered with mercantilist
pamphlets awaiting the tidy logic of the classicists.
The next two chapters cover the basic logic of the classical
arguments in favor of free trade. The first chapter deals with Adam
Smith's contributions, while the second introduces us to his
eminent contemporaries: David Ricardo, John Stuart Mill, Robert Torrens,
James Mill (John Stuart's father), John Ramsay McCulloch, and
Nassau Senior. The contributions of this group will be familiar to
students of international trade: development of national output as a
measure of national welfare and its application to tariff policy; how
protective duties, by diminishing competition, increase domestic prices
and encourage inefficient management; how free trade expands the extent
of the market, bringing about added productivity advantages in terms of
the division of labor; and how comparative, rather than absolute, costs
are the key to understanding the gains from trade.
While the coverage of the classical school is generally very well
done, two issues are bothersome. The first has to do with the novelty of
Smith's (and later Ricardo's) contributions to free trade
doctrine. The introduction to the chapter on Adam Smith's
contributions contains a prominent quotation of Schumpeter (1954, p.
184): "The Wealth of Nations does not contain a single analytic
idea, principle, or method that was entirely new in 1776." Given
that the book is not primarily concerned with the attribution of credit,
I found these references disturbing to the continuity of the text.
Furthermore, the discussion is too limited to present a balanced case.
No reference is made to what general equilibrium theorists identify as
one of Smith's most original contributions - a poetic expression of
a competitive market system. Second, each chapter that follows with an
argument against free trade is at least as long as "Adam
Smith's Case for Free Trade." I would have liked to have seen
a more balanced approach. I temper this criticism only because the
classical case inevitably gets elaborated upon in the context of
subsequent arguments against free trade.
In the second part of the book, the reader is treated to many novel
insights and an increasingly familiar cast of characters. At the time
Robert Torrens first made his argument that a unilateral tariff could
benefit the imposing country, economists assumed the bilateral terms of
trade were halfway between autarkic relative prices. Torrens's
argument gained currency as efforts were made to formalize the
determination of the terms of trade beginning with supply and demand
analysis of Mills, continuing with Edgeworth's (1894) use of
Marshall's offer curves, and culminating in Harry Johnson's
(1950, 1951) precise mathematical formulation of the optimal tariff. Of
course, it was not long after the initial formulation of the argument
that it was cast into doubt as an effective policy tool upon recognition
that retaliation would likely follow. Unfortunately, Irwin does not
treat the reader to game theoretic contributions to this issue before
closing the chapter.
Irwin takes the infant industry argument from cradle to grave. James
Steuart supported the use of tariffs for this purpose with few
qualifications, John Stuart Mill gave qualified support only to later
recant, while Smith remained vehement that the source of foreign
industry's superiority was irrelevant to the proposition of free
trade. John Rae (1834) was among the first to consider the role of
externalities, his contribution relating to technology transfer.
However, few arguments in favor of protection to infant industries dealt
with the opportunity cost of encouraging an infant industry, and none
anticipated Robert Baldwin's (1969) classic critique - that tariff
protection creates exactly the opposite incentives required to drive an
industry toward higher productivity that formed the basis for the
argument in the first place.
Before reading Irwin's book, I would have guessed that
Manoilescu's wage differential argument related to the fear of
imports from low-wage countries, but it actually prescribed the use of
tariffs by developing countries to shift labor from low-wage agriculture
to high-wage industry. Many years earlier, Henry Martyn had pointed out
that wage differentials might be a function of productivity
differentials, but no one seems to have recognized its relevance to the
debate. Ohlin (1931) stated his objection with characteristic insight by
posing the following question: "Why does labor not shift across the
sectors on its own but instead requires import duties or other forms of
intervention to bring about the reallocation?" Later Meade (1955)
introduced the notion of externalities to the labor market in a way that
might rationalize the primitives of Manoilescu's case, but he, and
later Bhagwati and Ramaswami (1963), established that, in many cases
where externalities led to inefficient resource allocation, tariffs were
rarely, if ever, the first-best policy response.
To ensure that the lessons of history are not lost on
macroeconomists, Irwin includes Keynes's views on trade. In 1923,
Keynes sounds as unequivocal about free trade as did Adam Smith in 1776,
but by the early 1930s, Keynes began advocating tariffs as a solution to
British unemployment. Keynes argued that a tariff would be stimulative
in the aggregate if wages were downwardly rigid, the exchange rate was
maintained, and labor was underemployed. While Lionel Robbins, T. E.
Gregory, Arnold Plant, J. R. Hicks, and others had collaborated on a
book that did not concede that classical theory was inoperative under
conditions of unemployment, Keynes was unmoved. It was Hicks who
conceded a great deal in assessing the state of affairs in 1951,
concluding that free trade had been called into severe question by the
theoretical changes brought about by Keynes.
Irwin goes on to argue that the erosion of the macroeconomic case for
tariffs was a byproduct of flexible exchange rates freeing up monetary
policy to stabilize prices. The difficulty I see with this argument is
that much of the liberalization of tariff levels since the 1930s had
occurred well before industrialized countries moved to flexible exchange
rates. Surely policymakers had come to recognize the harm done to
international trade by the retaliatory tariffs of the 1930s.
As an overall assessment of the book, I offer the reader this last
piece of information: Against the Tide: An Intellectual History of Free
Trade is located on a prominent shelf in my study between the Wealth of
Nations and Free To Choose.
References
Baldwin, Robert. 1969. The case against infant industry protection.
Journal of Political Economy 77:295-305.
Bhagwati, Jagdish, and V. K. Ramaswami. 1963. Domestic distortions,
tariffs and the theory of optimal subsidy. Journal of Political Economy
71:44-50.
Edgeworth, F. Y. 1894. The theory of international values. Economic
Journal 4:424-43.
Horace. 1960. The odes and epodes of Horace, translated by J.P.
Clancy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Johnson, Harry. 1950, 1951. Optimum welfare and maximum revenue
tariffs. Review of Economic Studies 19:28-35.
Johnson, Harry G. 1977. Aspects of the theory of tariffs. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Meade, James E. 1955. Trade and welfare. London: Oxford University
Press.
Ohlin, Bertil. 1931. Protection and non-competing groups.
Weltwirtschaftliches Archiv 33:30-45.
Plato. 1930. The republic. Leob Classical Library.
Rae, John. 1834. Statement of some new principles of political
economy. Boston: Hilllard, Gray.
Schumpeter, Joseph. 1954. History of economic analysis. New York:
Oxford University Press.
Mario J. Crucini Ohio State University