Learning in sequential auctions.
Jeitschko, Thomas D.
1. Introduction
A fundamental question of economics concerns the impact of market
structure and institutions on the allocation of resources. A class of
trading mechanisms that has received much attention in this respect over
the past several years is the transfer of resources through auctions.
While tremendous advances have been made in understanding single-unit auctions (see the surveys by Milgrom 1985; McAfee and McMillan 1987;
Wilson 1992; and Wolfstetter 1996), only recently have auction theorists
begun to embed this analysis in broader and more realistic institutional
settings.(1)
Auctions are often part of an institutionalized market in which
trades are recurring events, for example, markets for government
treasury securities, used cars, fresh fish, and many wholesale
agricultural commodities (flowers, cheese, tobacco, and so on). The
focus of this study is the potential impact of information transmission
and learning when goods in these markets are auctioned sequentially.
The transmission of information and the resolution of uncertainty
during a sequential auction can have important implications for bidding
behavior and auction outcomes. First, each participant learns about the
valuations of other bidders before it is "too late" to act on
the information. Specifically, a trader is able to use the behavior of
rivals in earlier rounds to update beliefs about rivals' valuations
for the item currently on the trading block. This leads to the second
informational effect. When deciding on bids in earlier auctions, bidders
must take into account how these bids affect the flow of information.
Specifically, bidders must account for how their own bids affect the
information they obtain about their rivals in later auctions. Hence,
sequential auctions exhibit two learning effects not present in static
auctions: a direct effect in which information gleaned from earlier
rounds is used to formulate current bids and an anticipation effect in
which bidders incorporate the impact of their earlier bids on the direct
effect in future rounds.
Despite the potential significance of information transmission in
sequential auctions, most of the existing literature in this area has
focused on other aspects of these markets. Gale and Hausch (1994), for
example, present a model in which two "stochastically equivalent" objects are auctioned in sequence to two bidders with
unit demands. However, because there is only one bidder left in the
second auction, the learning effects described above are not present in
this setting. In similar models, Engelbrecht-Wiggans (1994) and
Bernhardt and Scoones (1994) consider scenarios in which values are
assumed to be independent across both bidders and auctions and the
bidders do not know their value of a particular object until it is up
for sale. Together, these assumptions eliminate any learning during the
sequence of sales. Finally, several papers on sequential auctions (e.g.,
Black and de Meza 1992) examine auction formats in which bidders have
dominant strategies that do not depend on information.
Most research studying informational issues in sequential auctions
has focused on the common value paradigm (see, e.g., Engelbrecht-Wiggans
and Weber 1983; Hausch 1986; and Bikhchandani 1988). The focus of this
study, however, is how bidding behavior is affected when bidders have
independent private values, so that learning is not about the value of
the objects for auction but about opponents' types. Since many
sequential auctions are wholesale markets in which the goods purchased
are retailed in downstream markets, the independent private values
assumption is relevant if demand conditions in the downstream markets
are independent of each other. Moreover, even if there is a common value
component to bidders' values, the private values paradigm is
relevant if all bidders are equally (not necessarily fully) informed
about the common value elements of the good, so that the opponents'
strategies reveal no additional information about one's own value
of the good.
The papers most closely related to this investigation are Milgrom and
Weber (1982), Weber (1983), and McAfee and Vincent (1993). In these
studies, identical goods are sold sequentially through first price
sealed bid auctions to bidders who have independent private values and
unit demands. Rather than information transmission, however, the focus
of these papers is the equilibrium price path. In fact, information
transmission is of little importance in these models. In equilibrium,
bidders assess their option value of continuing in further auctions if
they lose the current auction. This option value depends solely on the
probability of winning or losing the first auction, not, however, on
estimations of how high the winning bid actually turns out to be. Given
this option value, bidders bid their estimation of the highest valuation
of their opponents, conditioning on their valuation being the highest.
Because of this conditioning, bids are independent of the prior history
of the game. In sum, bidders' strategies depend only on which
auction they are currently in but not on any past price realizations or
on estimations of future price realizations. Hence, bidders do not
update their beliefs about their opponents in the course of the auction
and therefore need not anticipate learning either.
The reason for the absence of learning and the anticipation of
information is that valuations are modeled to come from a continuous
distribution, so there is zero probability that any two bidders have the
same valuations. If, however, a bidder thinks there is a positive
probability that another bidder has the same valuation for an object for
auction, this bidder can no longer condition his bids on him having the
highest valuation. In this instance the bidder uses a mixed strategy to
avoid tying bidders of the same type. This strategy depends critically
on the probability of another bidder having the same valuation.
Bidders' beliefs about this probability are updated in the course
of the auction, and thus bidders' expected payoffs are affected by
their learning about rivals' types. This illustrates the direct
effect of information transmission mentioned above. To appreciate the
indirect effect, note that in the first auction bidders must trade off
the benefits associated with winning the auction and retiring against
the benefits of losing the first round and learning more about their
rivals' valuation in the second auction. In sum, learning and the
anticipation of information being generated affect bidders' optimal
strategies and hence expected payoffs throughout the sequence of sales.
The remainder of this paper contains three sections. In section 2 the
model is formalized and the equilibrium discussed. In section 3
properties of the equilibrium are studied. It is shown that bidders who
learn from the outcome of the first auction have higher expected
payoffs. Moreover, the anticipation of information leads to greater
payoffs when compared to "myopic" bidding in the first auction
because myopic bidders are unaware of the trade-off between winning the
first auction and being better informed in the second auction.
In equilibrium, prices may fluctuate. The probability that prices
increase or decrease depends on the information generated in the first
auction. However, regardless of this information, and thus independent
of the probability of increasing or decreasing prices, the price in the
second auction is, on average, the same as the price in the first
auction. This result is also obtained in the case for a continuum of
bidders' types (see, e.g., Weber 1983). Thus, although
bidders' strategies are affected differently when types are
distributed discretely as opposed to continuously, the equilibrium price
path forms a martingale in either case. Another analogy is found when
considering the institution chosen for the sale of the objects, namely,
contrasting the sequential auction with a simultaneous (static) auction.
Despite the fact that learning has no role, the static auction yields
the same expected final allocation of goods and bids, as does the
sequential auction. Thus, expected revenue equivalence studied in Weber
(1983) and Engelbrecht-Wiggans (1988) carries over to the case of a
discrete distribution of types.
Some brief concluding remarks appear in section 4, and the appendix
contains the proofs to the propositions and theorems.
2. The Model and the Equilibrium
Two identical objects are auctioned in sequence to three bidders.
Each bidder can be one of two possible types: have either a high
valuation for a unit or a low valuation for a unit. Without loss of
generality, valuations are normalized to 1 and 0. Bidders have an ex
ante probability of [Rho] [Epsilon] (0,1) of having a high valuation for
a unit of the goods, and 1 - [Rho] that they have a low valuation. They
know their own valuation for a unit of the good and have beliefs [Rho]
that any given opponent has a high valuation for a unit of the good.
Bidders have unit demands; that is, a bidder's value for a second
unit is nonpositive. Bidders have a reservation utility of zero, which
they obtain if they do not win one of the goods; otherwise, their
utility is given by the difference between their valuation of a unit and
the price they pay. In both auctions the strategy space is the real
line; that is, negative bids are permitted. Ties are broken by the roll
of a die. The auction format is a first price sealed bid auction in
which only the winning bid is announced.(2)
Notice that the auction format does not maximize expected revenue of
the sellers. However, in most markets in which sequential auctions are
used, the institutional framework is agreed on by both sellers and
buyers, as these markets are often arranged by trade associations or the
like. Thus, one would expect these markets to be efficient yet not
necessarily producer surplus maximizing.(3) The model under
consideration, which yields efficient allocations, serves as a
formalization to highlight the informational issues that bidders are
confronted with in these markets.
An equilibrium to this model is a strategy and set of beliefs, in
each auction for each bidder, such that given the opponents'
strategies the expected payoff of every bidder is maximized. The
equilibrium presented and studied is the symmetric noncooperative
perfect Bayesian equilibrium. The model illustrates how the observation
of the outcome of the first auction allows bidders to learn and thus
affects behavior in the second auction. It also shows how the
anticipation of information available in the second auction impacts
bidders' strategies in the first auction.
In equilibrium, bidders with a high valuation use behavioral strategies to avoid tying. This is particularly intuitive in the types
of markets under consideration as bidders often encounter the same set
of opponents in consecutive sequential auctions and thus, in mixing
their bids, remain unpredictable to these opponents. Bidders with a low
valuation for the good bid their own value and receive a payoff of zero.
This is a reflection of the fact that there are more bidders than goods
to be auctioned, and hence there is never excess supply.
The equilibrium strategies in the two auctions are summarized in the
following proposition. It is understood that in the second auction the
winner of the first auction does not participate. The derivation of
these strategies and the proof that these strategies constitute an
equilibrium are found in the appendix. The bidders' updated beliefs
after resolution of the first auction are denoted by [[Rho].sub.L]; that
is, [[Rho].sub.L] denotes the subjective belief that a bidder's
opponent in the second auction has a high valuation for the good.(4)
PROPOSITION 1. If the type is high, the strategy in the first auction
is [F.sub.1](b) = [(b + [b.sup.1/2])/(1 - b)][(1 - [Rho])/[Rho]], on [0,
[[Rho].sup.2]], and the expected payoff is 1 - [[Rho].sub.2]. If the
type is high, the strategy in the second auction is [F.sub.2](b) = [b/(1
- b)][(1 - [[Rho].sub.L])/[[Rho].sub.L]], on [0, [[Rho].sub.L]], and the
expected payoff is 1 - [[Rho].sub.L]. If the type is low, the strategy
in both auctions is zero, and the expected payoff is zero.
All proofs are in the appendix.
Notice that in the limit as (1 - [Rho])[Rho] goes to 0, [[Rho].sub.L]
must tend to [Rho]; that is, in the full information environment there
is no updating. Hence, as the probability of all bidders having a
valuation of 1 goes to one, the bids in both auctions go to 1, and as
the probability of all bidders having a valuation of 0 goes to one, the
bids in both auctions go to 0.
Since the equilibrium is found through backward induction, it is best
to focus on the second auction before studying the first auction.
Learning and the Equilibrium Strategies in the Second Auction
For bidders to determine their optimal strategies in the second
auction, they must form beliefs regarding their opponents'
valuations and strategies. After the conclusion of the first auction,
the winning bid is revealed. Bidders use this information to update
their beliefs regarding the types of their opponents. In the first
auction a low type bids 0 with probability one. The probability that a
high type bids 0 or below that is zero. It follows that by observing the
winning bid, bidders infer the type of the winner.
Thus, after completing the first auction, all bidders know their own
type as well as the type of the winner of the first auction. However,
since the winner of the first auction does not compete in the second
auction, any information regarding the winner's type is unimportant to the bidders in the second auction. In other words, bidders are
concerned only with the valuations of their opponents in the second
auction (i.e., the other losers of the first auction). To solve the
bidders' problem in the second auction, it is necessary to
establish the information that bidders have regarding their opponents
who lost the first auction. The fact that the losers did not win the
first auction implies that their bids are below the winning bid, which
allows bidders to learn about the type of their opponents. Let (1 -
[[Rho].sub.L]) denote the posterior probability that any loser of the
first auction is a low type. Let Pl denote the winning bid in the first
auction.
PROPOSITION 2. In equilibrium, the posterior probability that a loser
of the first auction is a low type is
(1 - [[Rho].sub.L]) = (1 - [Rho])/[(1 - [Rho]) +
[Rho][F.sub.1]([P.sub.1])].
The proof is an application of Bayes' rule.
Since [F.sub.1]([p.sub.1]) [element of] [0,1], (1 - [[Rho].sub.L])
[greater than or equal to] (1 - [Rho]). That is, any bidder who loses
the first auction is more likely to be a low type, so the average
valuation is nonincreasing in the course of the auction. This is so
because if a high type is present in the first auction, another high
type has a chance of winning the first auction; a low type, however,
does not.
Proposition 2 applies to equilibrium actions in the first auction.
However, beliefs must also be specified if in the first auction a bidder
uses a strategy other than the equilibrium strategy. Since only the
winning bid is revealed, the only way that bidders can become aware that
an out-of-equilibrium strategy was used is if the winning bid is above
the support of the equilibrium mixed strategy used by high types. All
other winning bids would be mistaken for bids resulting from an
equilibrium strategy. Should the winning bid be above the support,
bidders do not know which type placed the bid. However, assuming that
the winner's unit demand is fulfilled, beliefs about this
bidder's type are irrelevant. The remaining bidders participate in
the second auction with their posterior beliefs coinciding with their
prior beliefs, as no information is revealed about the losers of the
first auction. Hence, Proposition 2 describes bidders' learning in
the sequential auction with the provision that the bidders' beliefs
are subjective beliefs.(5)
The Anticipation of Information in the First Auction
In determining equilibrium strategies in the first auction, bidders
account for the possibility of participating in the second auction. For
low-type bidders this is irrelevant since their future payoff is zero.
For the high-type bidder the future payoff (i.e., the payoff in the
second auction) depends on the history of the game. That is, the high
type's payoff in the second auction depends on the outcome of the
first auction. Specifically, high types who win the first auction have
their unit demands satisfied and do not participate in the second
auction, receiving a payoff of zero in the second auction. However, a
high type who loses the first auction participates in the second auction
and expects to obtain the second good with some probability. In other
words, there is an opportunity cost of winning the first auction, as
this necessarily implies the loss of the expected payoff in the second
auction that accrues only to those who lose the first auction.
To consider the significance of this opportunity cost, one must
determine the expected payoff that the high types obtain when
participating in the second auction (given that they lose the first
auction). Applying Proposition 2 to the payoff given in Proposition 1,
one obtains (1 - [[Rho].sub.L]) = (1 - [Rho])/[(1 - [Rho]) +
[Rho][F.sub.1]([p.sub.1])]. Hence, the high type's payoff in the
second auction depends on the winning bid in the first auction,
[p.sub.1], and the first auction mixed strategy of the high types,
[F.sub.1]. However, prior to the first auction the winning bid is not
known. It is at this point that information impacts bidders'
strategies. Since the winning bid is unknown prior to the first auction,
bidders take expectations regarding the winning bid to determine their
expected future payoff. The distribution of the winning bid, however,
depends on the strategies used in the first auction. Moreover, since the
expectation is taken conditional on the bidder losing the first auction,
the conditional distribution of the winning bid is different for any bid
under consideration. In sum, a bidder's future expected payoff
depends on the information generated in the first auction; the
expectation of this information, in turn, depends on the distribution of
the winning bid; and, finally, the distribution of the winning bid, in
turn, depends on which bid the high type who loses places in the first
auction.
In particular, in assessing the implications of winning the first
auction in terms of forgone second auction payoffs, high types trade off
winning the first auction and retiring by placing higher bids against
learning and increased second auction payoffs by placing lower bids.
That is, the higher the bid the high type places is, the greater the
probability of winning the first auction is, yet, at the same time, the
lower the second auction payoff is expected to be if he loses the first
auction. This is illustrated in the following proposition, in which
[E.sub.1] denotes the expectations operator prior to the first auction.
PROPOSITION 3. The expectation of the payoff in the second auction of
a high type conditioned on losing the first auction when placing the bid
b is decreasing in the high type's first auction bid; that is,
(d/db)[E.sub.1][(1 - [[Rho].sub.L])[where]b [less than] [p.sub.1]]
[less than] 0.
The trade-off between winning the first auction and having higher
second auction expected payoffs becomes particularly clear when
considering a high type who in the first auction bids the lower end of
the support. If this is the winning bid, then clearly the opponents must
be low types. But in this case the winning bid in the second auction is
0 with certainty, and the bidder is indifferent between winning the
first or the second auction since both are concluded at the same price.
The implications for the strategies of the high types in both
auctions of the anticipation of information in the first auction and
learning in the second auction are the subject of the next section.
3. The Impact of Information and Learning
As indicated in the previous section, information and learning impact
bidders' strategies and payoffs in both auctions. Thus, information
and learning create a two-way link between the two auctions. Consider
first the second auction. After observing the outcome of the first
auction, bidders update their beliefs regarding their opponents'
types. In doing so, the strategy of high-type bidders in the second
auction is influenced by the outcome of the first auction. That is, the
second auction equilibrium strategy is a function of the information
generated. Since the second auction equilibrium strategies affect the
expected payoff in the second auction, the second auction expected
payoff is also a function of the information generated.
Regarding the first auction, high-type bidders consider the
opportunity cost of winning the first auction. Specifically, the
expected opportunity cost of obtaining the good from the first auction
is the expected second auction payoff, which the losers of the first
auction obtain. In taking the expectation of the second auction payoff,
bidders take into account the effect that learning has on the second
auction payoff. High-type bidders anticipate the information generated
by the outcome of the first auction for each bid on the support of their
equilibrium strategy. In sum, the second auction equilibrium is affected
by the outcome of the first auction through changes in beliefs; and the
first auction equilibrium is affected through bid-dependent opportunity
costs.
To understand the importance of information on the two auctions, a
basis of comparison is needed. The equilibrium is contrasted to auction
outcomes when bidders are unaware of informational effects. That is,
when bidders determine their strategies in the second auction, they do
not take into account the information generated in the first auction.
Consequently, in the first auction, bidders are myopic - they do not
anticipate the information being generated when determining their
strategies. Therefore, in the comparison bidding behavior, the prior and
posterior beliefs of all bidders are the same; that is, their posterior
beliefs are given by [Rho], and the expectation regarding the posterior
beliefs are also [Rho]. The resulting bidding behavior in this
comparison auction allows one to study the impact of information at each
stage of the two-auction equilibrium. The benchmark strategies are
derived as in the previous section with [Rho] replacing [[Rho].sub.L]
and [E.sub.1]([[Rho].sub.L]), respectively, and are given below with
superscript us.
If the type is high, the strategy in the first auction is
[Mathematical Expression Omitted] and the strategy in the second auction
is [Mathematical Expression Omitted], on [0, [Rho]]. If the type is low,
the strategy is zero in both auctions.
Compared to the benchmark scenario, the information generated in the
first auction has a positive value to high-type equilibrium bidders.
This is independent of whether in the first auction bidders are myopic
or anticipate information and use the equilibrium strategies. The value
of information is manifested in higher expected payoffs as, on average,
bidders place lower bids in the equilibrium case than in the benchmark
case. Specifically, the value of information to a high-type loser of the
first auction is the difference in the expected payoffs in the second
auction. This difference, denoted by V([p.sub.1]), where [p.sub.1] is
the winning bid in the first auction, is zero for low-type bidders. For
high-type bidders, V([p.sub.1]) is given in the following theorem.
THEOREM 1. The value of information to the high-type loser is
V([p.sub.1]) = b[(1 - [[Rho].sub.L]) - [[Rho].sub.L](1 -
[Rho])/[Rho]].
Moreover, the value of information to the high-type loser is positive
and strictly decreasing in the first auction winning bid; that is,
[Mathematical Expression Omitted]
and
dV([p.sub.1])/[dp.sub.1] [less than] 0.
To understand the intuition for dV([p.sub.1])/[dp.sub.1] [less than]
0, recall that, in equilibrium, bidders update their beliefs regarding
losers of the first auction. For high types to lose the first auction,
it is necessary that their bid be below the winning bid, which is more
likely if the winning bid is high. The lower the winning bid, the less
likely it is that a loser drew a bid from the distribution
[F.sub.1]([center dot]). In other words, it is more likely that the
bidder is a low type and placed the bid 0. This means that the
informational content of the winning bid is decreasing in the winning
bid. This can be seen clearly in the limit cases. First, let
[Mathematical Expression Omitted] then [[Rho].sub.L] = [Rho] and the
winning bid does not allow any inferences about the type of the loser of
the first auction (i.e., the winning bid contains no additional
information). Next, let [p.sub.1] = 0; then [[Rho].sub.L] = 0 (i.e.,
there is full information).
The next theorem shows how the information generated in the first
auction affects the bidding behavior in the second auction. Regardless
of the outcome of the first auction, the probability of high bids is
lower in the second auction of the equilibrium model than in the
benchmark model. This is a reflection of the fact that information has
positive value to high types. Furthermore, the difference in bids
increases as the first auction winning bid declines; that is, the lower
the first auction winning bid, the lower, on average, are the bids
placed in the second auction. This is a reflection of the fact that the
value of information is decreasing in the first auction winning bid.
THEOREM 2. The second auction benchmark distribution of high types
first degree stochastically dominates the equilibrium mixed strategy
distribution; that is,
[Mathematical Expression Omitted], [Mathematical Expression Omitted].
Furthermore, given two first auction prices [p[prime].sub.1] and
[p[double prime].sub.1] with [p[prime].sub.1] [greater than] [p[double
prime].sub.1], the second auction mixed strategy resulting from
[p[prime].sub.1] first degree stochastically dominates the second
auction mixed strategy resulting from [p[double prime].sub.1]; that is,
[Mathematical Expression Omitted].
The second part of Theorem 2 follows from the fact that the lower the
first auction winning bid, the more informative the winning bid is to
the losers of the first auction.
These theorems demonstrate the impact of learning on the second
auction equilibrium strategies of the high-type bidders. Regarding the
first auction, recall that bidders anticipate the generation of
information in the first auction when determining their optimal bidding
strategies. Specifically, high types face an opportunity cost of winning
the first auction, namely, not having an expected payoff in the second
auction after having won the first auction. This opportunity cost incurs
regardless of whether bidders are sophisticated or myopic. However, only
the sophisticated bidders take into account that the expected payoff in
the second auction depends on the bid placed in the first auction and
hence on the expected information generated by placing any particular
bid. That is, sophisticated bidders are aware that there is a trade-off
between increasing the probability of winning the good in the first
auction by placing higher bids and increasing the amount of information
by placing lower bids and thus increasing the expected payoff in the
second auction. Since the myopic bidders overlook the latter effect, on
average, in the first auction they place higher bids than the
sophisticated bidders. This is formalized in the following theorem.
THEOREM 3. The strategy used by myopic bidders in the first auction
first degree stochastically dominates the strategy used by sophisticated
bidders in the first auction; that is,
[Mathematical Expression Omitted], [Mathematical Expression Omitted].
The Equilibrium Price Path
Thus far it has been shown how information and learning impact the
strategies and payoffs at each stage of the auction. In this section
properties of the equilibrium price path are studied. It is shown that,
in equilibrium, prices may decrease from the first to the second
auction. However, there is also a probability that the second price is
higher than the first price. The probability that the second price is
above or below the first price depends on the first price. Specifically,
the higher the first auction price, the more likely it is that the
second auction price is greater than the first auction price. The reason
for this is twofold. First, the higher the first price, the more likely
it is that many high-type bidders participated in the first auction.
This suggests a high probability of high types competing in the second
auction. Second, the higher the first price, the less (additional)
information is generated. By Theorem 2, this leads high types to place
higher bids in the second auction, as their mixed strategies
stochastically dominate any equilibrium mixed strategy that would have
been used had a lower first auction price been observed.(6) Let
[p.sub.i] denote the price in the ith auction and let
[W.sub.2]([p.sub.2][where][p.sub.1]) denote the distribution of the
second auction price given [p.sub.1].
THEOREM 4. For all first auction prices greater than 0, the second
price is different, with probability one, than the first price; that is,
Pr{[p.sub.2] = [p.sub.1][where][p.sub.1] [greater than] 0} = 0.
Moreover, the higher the first auction price, the more likely it is
that the price sequence is increasing. In other words, the lower the
first auction price, the more likely it is that prices decrease; that
is,
d[W.sub.2]([p.sub.1][where][p.sub.1])/[dp.sub.1] [less than] 0.
Despite the properties of the equilibrium price path, prior to the
first auction the expected price sequence is constant; that is, on
average, both prices are the same. Even more striking is the fact that
after resolution of the first auction (i.e., after [p.sub.1] is known),
the expected second auction price, [p.sub.2], is equal to the first
price, [p.sub.1]. In other words, no matter how likely it is that the
second price will be below the first price, given the first price there
will always be occasional second auction prices so high that, on
average, the second auction price is equal to the first price.
Weber (1983) proves that the expectation of the second price is equal
to the first price for the case of a continuum of bidder types. Unlike
the case of a continuum of types, however, in this model with a discrete
distribution, the result critically depends on bidders drawing the
correct inferences when observing the winning bid of the first
auction.(7) In the case of a discrete distribution, the result is
explained by observing that there are three differences between the
distributions of the winning bid in the first and second auctions.
First, in the second auction there is one less bidder than in the
first auction since the winner of the first auction drops from
competition in the second auction because the unit demand of the winner
is met. Since average bids (and thus the winning bid) are increasing in
the number of bidders, this difference in the distributions of the
winning bids leads to lower bids in the second auction.
Second, since in equilibrium a low type does not win the first
auction when there are high types present, it is less likely that the
bidders participating in the second auction are high types (i.e.,
[[Rho].sub.L] [less than] [Rho]). This leads to lower bids, on average,
because the distribution of the winning bid puts more weight on bids
placed by low types. Moreover, high types place lower bids, on average,
as it is more likely that their opponents are low types. Both of these
differences, which lead to lower prices in the second auction, are in
contrast to the third difference in the distributions of the winning
bids in the two auctions.
The third difference in the distributions of the winning bids is that
bidders in the second auction value winning more highly, as there is no
opportunity cost to winning the second auction. That is, bidders who
lose the first auction participate in the second auction and then have a
chance of obtaining a good. However, if bidders also lose the second
auction, the auction ends without them having obtained a good. Due to
the worse implications of losing the second auction when compared to
losing the first auction, high types place, on average, higher bids than
they otherwise would. The third difference in the distributions of the
winning bids leads to higher prices in the second auction. In
equilibrium, this increased bidding in the second auction exactly
offsets the first two effects, so that the expected second price is
equal to the first price.
These properties of the equilibrium price path are formalized in
Theorem 5, where [E.sub.i] denotes the expectations operator prior to
the ith auction.
THEOREM 5. Ex ante, the difference in expected prices is zero; that
is,
[E.sub.1] ([p.sub.1] - [p.sub.2]) = 0.
Moreover, the expected second price, given the first price, is equal
to the first price. That is, prices form a Martingale:
[E.sub.2]([p.sub.2][where][p.sub.1]) = [p.sub.1], [Mathematical
Expression Omitted].
Finally, another analogy to the case of a continuum of bidder types
is worth pointing out. Despite the importance of information and
learning throughout the auctions, a surprising result is that a static
auction format in which the goods are auctioned simultaneously rather
than sequentially yields the same expected final allocation.(8)
THEOREM 6. The sequential auction and the simultaneous auction yield
the same expected final allocations.
The equilibrium of the static auction has an interesting property:
Although there are only two possible values for the goods, they may be
sold at different prices. Different prices occur with certainty if one
or more of the bidders has a high valuation for the good. This is
because there are more bidders than there are goods, so bidders avoid
tying by using mixed strategies.
The reason that both auctions yield the same expected final
allocation is that the economic problem in both auctions is the same:
There are two goods and three bidders, whose only costs are winning
bids. Thus, this particular change in the institutional arrangements of
the market does not affect the final allocation. However, the importance
of the auction format is significant in determining equilibrium
strategies. As illustrated, in the sequential auction bidders must
account for informational effects when determining equilibrium
strategies. However, the information is public (i.e., observable by all
bidders). Thus, by symmetry of the strategies, informational gains
offset each other in the course of the sequential auction. That is, in
the second auction all bidders have the same beliefs regarding the
probability of facing a specific type of bidder.
4. Conclusion
In this paper, the impact on bidders' strategies and payoffs is
studied when in the course of a sequential auction winning bids are
disclosed. In the model, bidders are one of two types (high or low
value), so bidders face the possibility that rivals are of the same type
as themselves. It is shown that the revelation of the winning bid leads
bidders to update their beliefs regarding their opponents' types at
the auction. This updating affects the bidders' strategies in such
a way that, on average, they place lower bids than bidders unaware of
the information would. Consequently, in equilibrium, bidders have
increased expected payoffs because of their learning after information
is revealed.
Bidders are aware of this impact of information on the later
strategies and hence anticipate this impact in earlier auctions. In
participating in the early auction, however, a bidder's action
directly influences the flow of information. Hence, when determining
strategies in the early auction, bidders take into consideration how
current actions influence their expectations regarding the revelation of
information and its impact on subsequent behavior. Specifically, bidders
trade off increasing the probability of winning the early auction with
being better informed and hence increased expected payoffs in the later
auction. Since the value of information in the later auction is
decreasing in the winning bid, this trade-off leads bidders to place
lower bids, on average, in the early auction when compared to bidders
who are unaware of the impact of information and learning in the course
of the sequential auction.
Thus, this paper helps to further the understanding of the importance
of information in determining bidders' optimal strategies in
sequential auctions. However, there are still many unresolved issues
regarding the impact of information on bidders' optimal strategies
in markets in which sequential auctions are utilized. For instance, it
is worth exploring how other auction formats and policies regarding the
revelation of information impact bidders' strategies in sequential
auctions. Moreover, these questions should be studied for other
assumptions regarding the distribution of bidders' types, such as
affiliated values or a richer type space.
Finally, just as the anticipation of information and learning
increase the bidders' expected payoffs, the anticipation of
information and learning decrease the sellers' expected revenues.
Thus, it is worth examining how sellers can manipulate the flow of
information to increase expected revenue.(9) For instance, the sellers
could improve expected revenue if they had the option to charge a fixed
price in the first auction. This could lead to increased expected
revenue in the first auction and, because it blocks learning in the
second auction, also increase revenue in the second auction.
This paper is based on the first chapter of my Ph.D. dissertation written under the guidance of Leonard J. Mirman, whose help and
encouragement I gratefully acknowledge. I thank Curtis Taylor, Rajiv Sarin, Ray Battalio, Jonathan Hamilton, and two anonymous reviewers for
helpful comments and the Private Enterprise Research Center for
financial support.
1 See, e.g., Rothkopf and Harstad (1994) and the literature cited
therein.
2 This is the informational equivalent to the descending bid (Dutch)
auction. In a Dutch auction, a bid clock is successively lowered until
one of the bidders stops the clock. Thus, in the Dutch auction, only the
winner and the winning bid are revealed.
3 In some markets revenue-maximizing schemes are particularly
unlikely. For instance, in the sequential auctions for tobacco in the
United States, there are fewer than ten tobacco curing companies bidding
for units from many small tobacco farmers (there are in excess of
350,000 tobacco quota owners), so that one might expect the bidders to
have more discretion over the auction rules than the sellers (cf. Raper,
Love, and Shumway 1997).
4 Notice that the equilibrium is isomorphic to a common-value
sequential auction in which the value of the goods is known to be 1, yet
there are an unknown number of bidders, each of three potential bidders
having a probability of [Rho] of participating in the auctions.
5 These subjective beliefs coincide with objective probabilities only
in equilibrium or when only one bidder deviates from the equilibrium and
this bidder wins the first auction. However, bidders are necessarily
unaware of any possible discrepancy between subjective beliefs and
objective probabilities.
6 Ashenfelter (1989) and Ashenfelter and Genesove (1992) show that in
sequential auctions of wine and condominiums, prices on average
declined. This price decline is termed the afternoon effect. The ex ante
probability of observing the afternoon effect in this model depends on
the parameters of the model.
7 Recall that in the case of a continuum of types, the equilibrium
strategies are independent of past price realizations, so bidders need
not draw any inferences about the other bidders.
8 Because of revenue equivalence of the discriminatory format and
other static auctions for multiple objects when bidders are risk
neutral, this result does not depend on the particular format of the
static auction (cf. Vickrey 1962). In Jeitschko (1995) it is shown that
even risk-averse bidders obtain the same expected payoff in the
sequential and simultaneous auctions.
9 This issue was brought to my attention by a reviewer. Taylor (1998)
examines the issue in the case of the sale of a single item of which the
quality is uncertain.
10 Notice that in the proof of Proposition 3 only the fact that high
types use a mixed strategy is used. In particular, the distribution of
the high types' bids is not needed in the proof.
Appendix
Proof of Proposition 1. Consider first the second auction strategies.
Given the bidders' posterior beliefs, [[Rho].sub.L], it must be
shown that no bidder type can improve on the payoffs resulting from the
proposed strategies. Low types bid their own value and receive a payoff
of zero on which, given the other bidders' strategies, they cannot
improve. The distribution of the high types' bids must be
continuous, as otherwise (by symmetry) they have positive probability of
tying their opponents at the discontinuity. This is dominated by bidding
infinitesimally above any atom in the distribution. It is clear that the
lower end of the support of the strategy must be the bid placed by low
types (i.e., 0). Finally, high types must be indifferent between any
particular bid placed with positive probability. This yields the
following equation, where [Mathematical Expression Omitted] denotes the
upper end of the support of the strategy,
[Mathematical Expression Omitted]. (A1)
Equation A1 is used to determine the equilibrium expected payoff of
the high type who participates in the second auction. Letting [Phi]
denote the expected payoff,
[Mathematical Expression Omitted] (A2)
Setting Equations A1 and A2 equal to each other yields the
equilibrium mixed strategy [F.sub.2]. Specifically,
(1 - b)[(1 - [[Rho].sub.L] + [[Rho].sub.L])[F.sub.2](b)] = (1 -
[[Rho].sub.L]) [tautomer] [F.sub.2](b) = [b/(1 - b)][(1 -
[[Rho].sub.L])/[[Rho].sub.L]].
Clearly, a bidder cannot improve by placing a bid off the support, as
this either implies losing the auction or winning with an unnecessarily
high bid.
Consider now the first auction. The argument is the same for low
types since their future expected payoff is zero. Hence, low types bid
their value and obtain an expected payoff of zero in the first auction.
For high types, the expected payoff of the entire game must be constant
on the support of their mixed strategy. Letting [Pi] denote the high
types' expected payoff from the entire game, the analogous equation
to Equation A1 is given by
[Mathematical Expression Omitted]. (A1[prime])
By Proposition 3 below,(10) a high type's expected future payoff
is a function of the bid placed in equilibrium. Applying Equation A3
from the proof of Proposition 3, Equation A A1[prime] becomes
[Mathematical Expression Omitted] (A1[double prime])
This yields the expected payoff of the entire two-auction game to the
high type. Analogous to Equation A2, one obtains
[Mathematical Expression Omitted]. (A2[prime])
Setting Equations A1[double prime] and A2[prime] equal to each other
gives [F.sub.1](b) as a quadratic equation of which only the positive
root yields a distribution function. That is,
[Mathematical Expression Omitted].
Given that the high type's second auction payoff depends on the
opponents' beliefs, it must be verified that a high type does not
benefit by manipulating the others' beliefs by deviating from the
proposed equilibrium. As noted above, however, only a bid placed above
the support would be detected as an out-of-equilibrium bid, and this bid
clearly decreases the bidder's expected payoff. Finally, consider a
high type bidding below the support of the proposed strategy. In this
case the bidder loses the first auction and expects to obtain a payoff
of (1 - [[Rho].sub.L]) (cf. Equation A2) in the second auction. However,
the value of [[Rho].sub.L] depends on the winning bid in the first
auction, but, as in the proof of Proposition 3, it is possible to
calculate the expected value of [[Rho].sub.L] The distribution of the
winning bid, [W.sub.1]([p.sub.1]), conditioned on a bid below the
support of the mixed strategy is [[(1 - [Rho]) +
[Rho][F.sub.1]([p.sub.1])].sup.2]. Hence, the expectation of the second
auction payoff of a high type who places a bid below the lower end of
the support is
[Mathematical Expression Omitted],
which is exactly the payoff that the bidder receives when playing the
equilibrium mixed strategy. Hence, there is no increase in the expected
payoff by bidding below the support of the mixed strategy, and the
proposed strategies constitute a Nash equilibrium.
Proof of Proposition 3. Since the high type who is taking the
expectation conditions on one of the opponents winning the first
auction, the distribution of the winning bid comes from the bids that
the opponents place. Since there are two opponents, the distribution of
the highest of the opponents' bids is [W.sub.1]([p.sub.1]) = [[(1 -
[Rho]) + [Rho][F.sub.1]([p.sub.1])].sup.2]. However, since the high type
places a bid in the first auction, the distribution must be conditioned
on the winning bid, [p.sub.1], being greater than the bid, b, that the
high type places when taking the expectation. Thus, the conditional
distribution of the winning bid is [W.sub.1]([p.sub.1][where][p.sub.1]
[greater than] b) = [[W.sub.1]([p.sub.1]) - [W.sub.1](b)]/[1 -
[W.sub.1](b)], with density [w.sub.1]([p.sub.1][where][p.sub.1] [greater
than] b) = 2[(1 - [Rho]) +
[Rho][F.sub.1]([p.sub.1])][Rho][f.sub.1]([p.sub.1])/{1 - [[(1 - [Rho]) +
[Rho][F.sub.1](b)].sup.2]}. Given (1 - [[Rho].sub.L]) in Proposition 2,
the expected posterior beliefs that a high type who loses the first
auction has regarding the losing opponent of the first auction,
conditional on the bid that the type whose beliefs are in question
places, is
[Mathematical Expression Omitted]. (A3)
The derivative of this with respect to the bid being placed, b, has
the same sign as does
-[f.sub.1](b){1 - [[(1 - [Rho]) + [Rho][F.sub.1](b)].sup.2]} + [1 -
[F.sub.1](b)]2[(1 - [Rho]) + [Rho][F.sub.1](b)][Rho][f.sub.1](b),
which simplifies to -[[Rho].sup.2][f.sub.1](b)[[1 -
[F.sub.1](b)].sup.2]. Hence, (d/db)[E.sub.1][(1 - [[Rho].sub.L])[where]b
[less than] [p.sub.1]] [less than] 0.
Proof of Theorem 1. The benchmark expected payoff in the second
auction to high-type losers of the first auction is given by the payoff
they receive, given the bid they place, (1 - b), multiplied by the
probability of winning given that bid. The probability of winning, given
that bid, depends on the objective posterior probability of the type of
their opponent. Because the bidder does not learn and has subjective
beliefs [Rho], the objective probability of facing a low-type opponent
differs from the subjective beliefs. The objective posterior probability
is given by (1 - [[Rho].sub.L]); that is, it is the same as the
posterior beliefs of the informed bidders. Therefore, the probability of
winning, given a bid, b, is [Mathematical Expression Omitted] Hence, the
expected payoff is
[Mathematical Expression Omitted].
Thus,
[Mathematical Expression Omitted].
Furthermore, leaving open which strategy bidders use in the first
auction and letting G denote either [F.sub.1] or [F[double
prime].sub.1], d(1 - [[Rho].sub.L])/d[p.sub.1] = -(1 -
[Rho])[Rho]g([p.sub.1])/[[(1 - [Rho]) + [Rho]G([p.sub.1])].sup.2] [less
than] 0. That is, the lower [p.sub.1], the greater (1 - [[Rho].sub.L])
and the greater the value of information; that is,
dV([p.sub.1])/[dp.sub.1] [less than] 0.
Proof of Theorem 2. Regarding the first statement in the theorem,
first consider [F.sub.2](b) and [Mathematical Expression Omitted]. Then
[Mathematical Expression Omitted].
From Proposition 2, (1 - [[Rho].sub.L]) = (1 - [Rho])/[(1 - [Rho]) +
[Rho][F.sub.1]([p.sub.1])]. So, (1 - [[Rho].sub.L])/[[Rho].sub.L] = (1 -
[Rho])/[Rho][F.sub.1]([p.sub.1], so the inequality becomes
[F.sub.1]([p.sub.1]) [less than] 1. Next, consider the distributions for
[Mathematical Expression Omitted]. Then, [Mathematical Expression
Omitted] for all [Mathematical Expression Omitted]. Regarding the second
part of the theorem, the inequality similarly reduces to
[F.sub.1]([p[prime].sub.1]) [less than] [F.sub.1]([p[double
prime].sub.1]).
Proof of Theorem 3. The statement is true for [Mathematical
Expression Omitted] since [Mathematical Expression Omitted]. It remains
to be shown that
[Mathematical Expression Omitted].
The function h is continuous on its domain [Mathematical Expression
Omitted] or, equivalently, {(b,p)10 [less than] b [less than] 1 [and]
[b.sup.1/2] [less than] p [less than] 1}. Notice that
[Delta]h/[Delta][Rho] = b/[([Rho] - b).sup.2] [greater than] 0, [for
every] b [greater than] 0. Hence, h must obtain its infimum, where p is
smallest (i.e., at p = [b.sup.1/2]) or, equivalently, where b =
[[Rho].sup.2]. In other words, h reaches its infimum where the function
g([Rho]) [equivalent to] h(b = [[Rho].sup.2], [Rho]) has its infimum.
However,
g([Rho]) = 1/[(1 - [Rho]).sup.2] - 1(1 - [Rho]) [greater than] 0,
[for every] 0 [less than] [Rho] [less than] 1.
Hence, h(b,[Rho]) is positive on its domain.
Proof of Theorem 4. The distribution of the winning bid in the second
auction, [W.sub.2]([p.sub.2][where][p.sub.1] [greater than] 0) = [[(1 -
[[Rho].sub.L]) + [[Rho].sub.L][F.sub.2]([p.sub.2][where][p.sub.1]
[greater than] 0)].sup.2], is continuous on [Mathematical Expression
Omitted], so the probability that any particular price [p.sub.2] =
[p.sub.1] [greater than] 0 is realized is zero.
Given the equilibrium mixed strategy in the second auction,
[F.sub.2], [W.sub.2]([p.sub.2][where][p.sub.1]) = [[(1 -
[[Rho].sub.L])/(1 - [p.sub.2])].sup.2]. Inserting [F.sub.1] from
Proposition 1 into Proposition 2 yields [Mathematical Expression
Omitted]. The probability that the second auction price is lower than
the first auction price is [Mathematical Expression Omitted]. Hence,
[Mathematical Expression Omitted].
Proof of Theorem 5. Since the latter statement implies the former,
only the latter is proved: [E.sub.2]([p.sub.2][where][p.sub.1]) =
[integral of] [p.sub.2] d[W.sub.2] between limits [[Rho].sub.L] and 0 =
[[Rho].sub.L] - [integral of] [W.sub.2] d[p.sub.2] between limits
[[Rho].sub.L] and 0. Given [W.sub.2]([p.sub.2]) = [[(1 -
[[Rho].sub.L])/(1 - [p.sub.2])].sup.2], as in the proof to Theorem 4,
[Mathematical Expression Omitted]. Now notice that, as in the proof of
Theorem 4, [Mathematical Expression Omitted].
Proof of Theorem 6. Because of the same reasoning as in the
sequential auction, low types bid their own value in the simultaneous
auction and have expected payoffs of zero in either auction. Analogous
to the sequential auction, the high types' expected payoffs in the
simultaneous auction are given by (1 - b)Pr{winning[where]b}. High types
win whenever they submit the first- or second-highest bid. Whenever they
face either one or two low types, they win for sure. The probability of
this occurring is [(1 - [Rho]).sup.2] + 2(1 - [Rho])[Rho]. In all other
cases they face two high types using some mixed strategy
[F.sub.1]([center dot]) with [F.sub.s](0) = 0. Hence, their payoff is
[(1 - [Rho]).sup.2] + 2(1 - [Rho])[Rho], which is the same as for the
sequential auction as given in Equation A2[prime].
References
Ashenfelter, Orley. 1989. How auctions work for wine and art. Journal
of Economic Perspectives 3:23-36.
Ashenfelter, Orley, and David Genesove. 1992. Empirical evidence on
auction theory - Testing for price anomalies in real-estate auctions.
American Economic Review 82:501-5.
Bernhardt, Dan, and David Scoones. 1994. A note on sequential
auctions. American Economic Review 84:653-7.
Bikhchandani, Sushil. 1988. Reputation in repeated second-price
auctions. Journal of Economic Theory 46:97-119.
Black, Jane, and David de Meza. 1992. Systematic price differences
between successive auctions are no anomaly. Journal of Economics and
Management Strategy 1:607-28.
Engelbrecht-Wiggans, Richard, and Robert J. Weber. 1983. A sequential
auction involving asymmetrically-informed bidders. International Journal
of Game Theory 12:123-7.
Engelbrecht-Wiggans, Richard. 1988. Revenue equivalence in
multi-object auctions. Economics Letters 26:15-9.
Engelbrecht-Wiggans, Richard. 1994. Sequential auctions of
stochastically equivalent objects. Economics Letters 44:87-90.
Gale, Ian L., and Donald B. Hausch. 1994. Bottom-fishing and
declining prices in sequential auctions. Games and Economic Behavior 7:318-31.
Hausch, Donald B. 1986. Multi-object auctions: Sequential vs.
simultaneous sales. Management Science 32:1599-610.
Jeitschko, Thomas D. 1995. Information and learning in markets with
sequential auctions. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Virginia,
Charlottesville, VA.
McAfee, R. Preston, and John McMillan. 1987. Auctions and bidding.
Journal of Economic Literature 25:699-738.
McAfee, R. Preston, and Daniel Vincent. 1993. The declining price
anomaly. Journal of Economic Theory 60:191-212.
Milgrom, Paul R., and Robert J. Weber. 1982. A theory of auctions and
competitive bidding, II. Unpublished paper, Northwestern University.
Milgrom, Paul R. 1985. The economics of competitive bidding: A
selective survey. In Social goals and social organization-Essays in
memory of Elisha Pazner, edited by Leonid Hurwicz, David Schmeidler, and
Hugo Sonnenschein. Cambridge, New York, and Sydney: Cambridge University
Press, pp. 261-89.
Raper, Kellie Curry, H. Alan Love, and C. Richard Shumway. 1997. A
nonparametric statistical test for monopsony market power: Monte Carlo experiments and application to U.S. cigarette manufacturing. Unpublished
paper, University of Massachusetts.
Rothkopf, Michael H., and Ronald M. Harstad. 1994. Modeling
competitive bidding: A critical essay. Management Science 40:364-84.
Taylor, Curtis R. 1998. Time-on-the-market as a sign of quality.
Unpublished paper, Texas A&M University.
Vickrey, William. 1962. Auctions and bidding games. In Recent
advances in game theory, edited by O. Morgenstern and A. Tucker.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, pp. 15-27.
Weber, Robert J. 1983. Multiple-object auctions. In Auctions,
bidding, and contracting: Uses and theory, edited by R.
Engelbrecht-Wiggans, M. Shubik, and R. Stark. New York: New York
University Press, pp. 165-91.
Wilson, Robert. 1992. Strategic analysis of auctions. In Handbook of
game theory 1, edited by R. J. Aumann and S. Hart. Amsterdam: Elsevier
Science Publishers, pp. 227-79.
Wolfstetter, Elmar. 1996. Auctions: An introduction. Journal of
Economic Surveys 10:367-420.