Asymmetric power relations and cooperation in anarchy.
Sutter, Daniel
Anarchy as an organizing principle for society must appeal to anyone
who places individual freedom on his scale of values.... It is not
surprising that "anarchy" and "anarchism" have
re-emerged as topics of discussion in the 1960's and the
1970's, as tentacles of government progressively invade private
lives and as the alleged objectives of such invasions recede yet further
from attainment.
Winston Bush [5, 1]
I. Introduction
The political system of anarchy generates strong responses (positive
and negative) from scholars. Conflictual and cooperative visions of
anarchy coexist. The most famous proponent of the former view is Thomas
Hobbes, who depicts the state of nature as a war of all against all
where life is "solitary, poore, nasty, brutish, and short"
[17, 186]. The Hobbesian vision has dominated the discussion of anarchy,
which for many is a synonym for chaos.
I consider the prospects for cooperative anarchy within the
institutional framework of anarcho-capitalism in which private,
for-profit agencies offer sets of legal codes and enforcement of these
codes. In anarchy no institution exists with legitimate authority over
all members of society. Many situations resemble anarchy in this
respect, including international business and trade, relations between
nations, the informal (black market) sector of controlled economies, the
underground (criminal) sector, political promises and deals, and
constitutional (or social) contracts. Cooperation is not unknown in such
situations. The Merchant Law in early medieval Europe [2] and the
Maghribi traders' coalition [12] are examples of institutions that
enable cooperation. These examples suggest Hobbesian vision
underestimates the possibilities for cooperation in anarchy.
I proceed as follows. Section II discusses the literature on
cooperation in anarchy and elaborates on the nature of
anarcho-capitalism. The key issue for the effectiveness of
anarcho-capitalism is the distribution of property rights. Section III
models the relationship between individuals and protection agencies. I
illustrate how this asymmetric power relationship might be biased in
favor of the agencies, which could degenerate into exploitative gangs.
Section IV considers a number of extensions to the model which allow the
allocation of rights between individuals and agencies to be relatively
equitable, and is the main contribution of this paper. Section V
concludes by examining asymmetric relations in actual anarchic situations. Anarcho-capitalism itself has never been implemented.
Competition between governments, however, does occur. This and several
other situations sufficiently resemble my model to provide relevant
evidence and illustrate the general applicability of this research. I
find evidence of mixed effectiveness of the devices discussed in section
IV.
II. The Emergence of Property Rights and Cooperation in Anarchy
Government performs two tasks which facilitate market exchanges: it
secures individuals' initial possessions, and it enforces
agreements made by individuals. In some anarchic situations initial
possessions are secure but government-enforced contracts are
unavailable. Many scholars have examined how spontaneous (or market)
forces, through the means of reciprocity, reputation, and hostages, can
readily substitute for government enforcement in this circumstance.(1)
Conditions which facilitate cooperation include repeated interaction
between a set of parties, a low discount rate on the part of all
parties, and the ability to recognize and identify trading partners.
Several anarchic situations, including anarcho-capitalism, lack both
enforceable agreements and secure initial possession. In the absence of
government, spontaneous forces have to fulfill both tasks. If stable
property rights can be established, reciprocity and reputation indicate
economic activity could flourish in anarchy. But can secure property
rights be provided in the absence of government?
A small but growing body of research examines the emergence of
property rights in an-archic situations. These models emphasize the
allocation of power among individuals and the effectiveness of predatory
action in determining the allocation of property [6; 16; 32; 33; 36;
37]. The distribution of rights depends critically on the balance of
force: "... all private ownership rights are ultimately founded on
the ability to forcefully exclude potential competitors. Force, not
fairness, determines the distribution of wealth in a society" [36,
57]. Although models of the emergence of property rights focus primarily
on symmetric conflict situations, the implication for asymmetric
situations is that the stronger party dominates.(2)
I consider the implications of this research for cooperation in the
anarcho-capitalism model of anarchy,(3) which represents the total
privatization of government. For-profit agencies offer a set of legal
codes and protection and enforcement of these codes. Agencies may differ
in the "laws" they offer; for example, agency A may include
gambling and prostitution as "crimes" and enforce the death
penalty for some offenses while agency B might not. Agencies may also
differ in the level of protection and enforcement of their codes; A may
rely on padlocks and alarms to protect clients' homes and
businesses while B may offer armed guards. People choose the agency that
most satisfies their preferences for laws and enforcement.
The parallel with consumer choice in the market is at the core of the
intuitive appeal of the system. The power of competition (hopefully)
forces for-profit agencies to be more responsive to consumer preferences
than bureaucratic, monopoly government. The system relies on the ability
of reputation and reciprocity to allow contracting between individuals
and agencies and to facilitate interagency relations. If the analogy to
freedom of choice within the market place is inappropriate, the system
is unlikely to perform as advertised.
Will people be able to choose which agency to patronize in
anarcho-capitalism? Market exchange occurs within a political system
which enforces property and contract rights. In anarcho-capitalism there
is no corresponding institution. Freedom to choose must arise as an
outcome within the system. Unfortunately, the advocates of
anarcho-capitalism do not adequately tackle how freedom of choice is
attained as an equilibrium of the system.
The problem of securing initial possessions is different from
providing enforceable agreements. Reputation and reciprocity work only
after the former task is accomplished. The distribution of force among
participants is crucial in the emergence of stable property rights. In
anarcho-capitalism the key relationship is between the protection agency
and the individual, which is asymmetric. As a consequence, the resulting
distribution of rights may be highly skewed, with no effective freedom
of choice between agencies for individuals. Since personal freedom is an
important normative criterion for anarcho-capitalists, such a negative
result is very damaging.
Must the protection agencies necessarily degenerate into exploitative
gangs? Or might spontaneous forces be able to provide effective
protection to the rights of individuals? I address this question in
section IV, which represents the major contribution of this paper.
To facilitate examination of the relationship between individuals and
agencies I accept uncritically several features of anarcho-capitalism
worthy of consideration in a more general study. I assume more than one
protection agency exists and that agencies do not collude. I do not
examine which laws and enforcement procedures agencies offer potential
customers. The issue of interagency relations and dispute resolution is
ignored entirely (i.e., what happens when a client of A is accused of an
offense against a client of B). The internal structure of agencies and
the effects of the system on economic performance are not examined.(4)
IIl. A Model of Anarcho-Capitalism
A population of many individuals inhabits a given region with m
([greater than] 1) existing protective agencies. Let M be the set of
agencies, M = {1,..., m}. Each individual is either a client of one of
the agencies or is independent. Clients of an agency make payments in
exchange for protection services. Let v [is greater than] 0 be the
profit an agency makes on the typical individual.(5) I consider an
agency A and an individual d who does not wish to be a client of A. Let
s [is greater than] 0 be the value to d of not patronizing A, either to
remain independent or be a client of agency B. The reasons for d's
preference are immaterial but may include the laws offered by A. Any
differences in the products (laws and services) offered by agencies are
assumed not to affect the per client profit. The efficient outcome in
each of the games of this section is for d not to become or remain a
client of A.
For simplicity I describe the relationship between agencies and
individuals as if the former were genuinely offering protection services
to their clients. The model can be interpreted in strictly exploitative
terms if the reader wishes. The amount v, for example, then is the net
value of wealth expropriated from d. Protection agencies are motivated
by profit and implement any strategy which increases profit whether
violent or not. Moral standards affect the activities of protection
agencies only through consumer response (if any) to brutality.
The assumption v [is greater than] 0 imposes that the market
structure for protection services is oligopolistic.(6) The protection
market would likely not be perfectly competitive for several reasons.
First, economies of scale in providing protective services are likely.
Agencies need to attain a minimal size to be able to successfully
confront other agencies; this limits the number of agencies and creates
a barrier to entry. Second, reputation effects, stressed in the
operation of anarcho-capitalism by the authors mentioned, are
inconsistent with perfect competition. Once agencies have reputations
they no longer supply a homogeneous product in the eyes of consumers.(7)
One person is small relative to any existing protection agency. An
agency always wins a confrontation with an individual and this is common
knowledge. The confrontation has negligible cost to the agency while the
individual suffers a large cost P. An agency may fine a client who
attempts to exit an amount p ([is greater than or equal to] 0) which can
only be collected if the attempt fails.
Confrontations between protection agencies are skirmishes which do
not threaten the existence of the losing agency and are costly for both
the winning and losing sides. The outcome and costs are functions of the
size of the protection agencies. For simplicity, assume strength is
proportional to agency size and agencies do not differ in their ability
to produce strength. Let q(j) be the number of clients of agency j. The
probability of victory for agency j in a confrontation with k is
[Alpha](q(j), q(k)). Assume [Alpha]([center dot], [center dot]) [is an
element of] [0, 1] is increasing in q(j) and decreasing in
q(j[prime]).(8) Let D([center dot]) be the cost of winning a
confrontation as a function of the size of the defeated agency and
L([center dot]) the cost of losing a confrontation as a function of the
size of the victorious agency. Both D([center dot]) and L([center dot])
are increasing and for all q [is greater than or equal to] 0, L(q) [is
greater than] D(q) [is greater than] 0.
The Protection Racket Game examines relations between A and d. The
game is illustrated in Figure 1. The interaction depicted occurs either
when A attempts to win the patronage of an independent d or when d
attempts to leave A. Assume that once confronted by A an individual is
unable to flee to avoid confrontation, or equivalently an agency may
always challenge an exiting client. The payoffs of the game are as
follows. A receives v if d becomes a client. d receives s if she does
not end up a client of A and -P if involved in a fight with A. The
unique Nash equilibrium (in pure and mixed strategies) is
NE = {(d = Accept, A = Confront)}, (1)
so d becomes a "customer" of A. Agencies do not have to
bargain with independents to win their patronage. Alternatively, an
individual cannot end a relationship with a protection agency even if it
were voluntarily entered into. The equilibrium illustrates how the
allocation of rights between protection agencies and individuals in
anarcho-capitalism may favor the agencies.
IV. Prospects for Equal Treatment of Individuals
Several unrealistic assumptions were made in section III to highlight
the asymmetry between individuals and agencies. The relaxation of these
assumptions on the whole weakens the position of the agency. I assumed
an agency could costlessly and with certainty challenge any individual.
More realistically the probability A can challenge an exiting d is a
function of the resources A spends on fences, guards, etc. If these
inputs are not sufficiently productive, they may not be a worthwhile
investment for A. In equilibrium the probability of interdiction will
generally be less than one, so exit is not totally foreclosed. An exit
attempt may be rational for individuals even if there is a chance of
being caught. Also a confrontation with an individual imposes some costs
on an agency because some employees will be injured and equipment
damaged in a lopsided fight. It may not be cost-effective for A to fight
d, even if the outcome is not in doubt. Together these additions ensure
some mobility exists in anarcho-capitalism. Exactly how much and whether
it is sufficient to induce competition among protection agencies are
interesting questions, though beyond the scope of this paper.
The analysis of section III suggests anarcho-capitalism may resemble
a market with switching costs. Klemperer [19] shows the equilibrium of a
competitive market with switching costs mimics the collusive oligopolistic equilibrium. Two factors which increase competition in a
switching cost model are first period competition for customers before
they become "locked in" and entry of new customers to the
market after the first period [19; 20]. My analysis suggests each of
these factors would be weak in anarcho-capitalism. Once agencies become
sufficiently large, they do not have to "compete" for
unaffiliated customers - they can coerce patronage. Since individuals
cannot remain independent, there is no pool of potential new customers
in a future period. Additionally children could enter adulthood locked
in to their parents' agency. The only source of new clients in a
future period is migration into the region.
Since d values exiting A, following the logic of the Coase Theorem,
she might purchase her freedom. With only two parties involved,
transactions costs would be low. Coasian sidepayments are unlikely to
work effectively in anarcho-capitalism for several reasons. Credit
markets may be imperfect or individuals may be wealth constrained. Most
importantly the freedom thus purchased would not be credible; d and A
would return to the situation of the Protection Racket game and the
cycle could begin anew.
An individual was unable to leave her current agency in the
Protection Racket Game. Since an individual is weak relative to an
agency, help is needed to exit. A profit-motivated agency could possibly
provide this assistance. The Exit Game examines when d, currently a
customer of A, attempts to switch to a rival agency B. A person may wish
to leave her current agency for several reasons, including that she was
"recruited" as in the Protection Racket Game. I again assume
that A can contest the exit attempt if desired with certainty and at
zero cost; also that the cost to d of moving is zero. A game tree
illustrating the Exit Game is contained in Figure 2. The game has three
players, d, A, and B. d moves first and attempts to defect. A next
decides to allow or contest the defection. B then decides whether to
backdown or confront A, in which case there is a battle. If B backs
down, d abandons the exit attempt and returns to A, which fines d an
amount p [is greater than or equal to] 0. If them is a battle, d ends up
a client of the victorious agency.(9)
The payoffs of the Exit Game are as follows. If d does not exit or if
B backs down, A and B receive a payoff of 0; d is fined and injured if
she exits and B backs down. If A allows exit, v is transferred from A to
B while d receives the benefit s of escaping A. If A and B battle, d is
fined if A wins or receives benefit s if B wins. A and B suffer damage
from the fight and v is transferred if B wins.
Analysis of the game focuses on play in the subgame between A and B
which occurs if d announces an intention to defect to B. The Nash
equilibria in pure strategies for the subgame are:
NE = {(A = Contest, B = Backdown), (A = Allow exit, B = Confront)}.
(2)
The following conditions ensure the strategy combinations in (2) are
Nash. They imply the costs of a battle are larger than the profit the
agency earns from the typical client.
-D(q(A)) [is greater than] v (to ensure [z.sub.3] [is less than] 0);
(3)
-D(q(B)) [is greater than] v (to ensure - [z.sub.2] [is greater than]
v). (4)
In the second equilibrium of (2) d is able to defect from A to B. The
addition of a rival agency can allow for free exit by individuals even
given the strict assumptions of the Exit Game. As a result, the
allocation of rights between individuals and agencies would, in this
equilibrium, be relatively equal. The existence of a no exit equilibrium
in (2) is, nonetheless, a serious threat to the viability of
anarcho-capitalism. If protection agencies need not cater to consumer
preferences the performance of the system is likely to be poor. The
existence of a dismal equilibrium is probably sufficient to induce all
but its strongest supporters to dismiss anarcho-capitalism. So I seek
further means by which the rights of individuals could be protected in
the no exit equilibrium of the Exit Game.
The rival agency has a greater incentive to confront A if a group of
clients attempts exit. Let k be the number of clients of A seeking to
exit to B. Since k must be small relative to the size of A to remain
within the context of the model, the effect on q(A) and q(B) is ignored.
Payoffs for A and B as functions of k are
[z.sub.2](k) = -[Alpha] [center dot] D(q(B)) + [1 - [Alpha]] [center
dot] [-L(q(B)) - k [center dot] v], [z.sub.5](k) = -k [center dot] v;
(5)
[z.sub.3](k) = -[Alpha] [center dot] L(q(A)) + [1 - [Alpha]] [center
dot] [-D(q(A)) + k [center dot] v], [z.sub.6](k) = k [center dot] v. (6)
The rank orderings of the payoffs for A and B can change as k
increases. Examination reveals that A's payoffs, [z.sub.2](k) and
[z.sub.5](k), are decreasing functions of k while B's payoffs,
[z.sub.3](k) and [z.sub.6](k), are increasing functions of k. As long as
[Alpha] [is greater than] 0, [z.sub.6](k) [is greater than] [z.sub.3](k)
for all k, but when k is sufficiently large, [z.sub.3](k) [is greater
than] 0. Confront then becomes a (weakly) dominant strategy for B. Exit
in groups may possibly rescue freedom of exit (contract). When k is
sufficiently large, however, [z.sub.5](k) [is greater than]
[z.sub.2](k). The net expected value to A of a confrontation with B is
then positive; exit in groups may give A an incentive to fight to
prevent exit.
Four cases are possible depending on the ordering of [z.sub.3],
[z.sub.2], and [z.sub.5]. In one case, [z.sub.3](k) [is greater than] 0
and [z.sub.5](k) [is less than] [z.sub.2](k), the unique equilibrium of
the subgame between A and B is (A = Allow Exit, B = Confront). Freedom
of exit for individuals in groups is protected here. A necessary
condition for this case is that q(B) [is greater than] q(A) so only the
strongest agencies benefit from exit in groups. Exit by groups over time
may increase market concentration and is at best an imperfect means of
providing freedom to contract.
A further generalization of the Exit Game incorporates that while
some clients wish to defect from A, some from other agencies will want
to join A. Protection agencies may have an incentive to allow their
clients to exit in exchange for similar guarantees from other agencies.
I examine conditions under which this might occur.
The subset of agencies currently cooperating is called a coalition
and designated C. Assume agencies which cooperate in this manner agree
(i) to allow their clients who wish to defect to other members of the
coalition to do so; and (ii) not allow their clients to defect to the
agencies outside the coalition. All other agencies not in C are assumed
in the no exit equilibrium of the Exit Game. The "coalition"
is for analytical purposes; actual cooperation need not be formally
organized or chartered at all. At any time assume there is only one
active coalition. If C = M, full freedom of choice for individuals
exists. If the protection agencies are exploitative gangs, the movement
described here could be a slave trade.
Let [Pi](j) be the probability a client of agency j = 1,...,m wishes
to defect from j during the period under consideration. The expected
number of j's clients wanting to defect is F(j) = [Pi](j) [center
dot] q(j). Let [Beta](l; j) be the probability that an agent who wishes
to leave j wants to join agency l. Then [summation of] [Beta] (l; j) = 1
where l [is not equal to] j and the expected number of defectors from j
to l is [Beta](l; j) [center dot] F (j).
The behavior of individuals is now summarized in [Pi](j) and
[Beta](l; j). Assume when an individual switches from agency A to B that
B is able to perfectly price discriminate and capture all the benefit
(s) of the switch. This extreme assumption is the upper bound on revenue
an agency could expect from a new client and simplifies analysis.
An agency joins C if its expected net payoff from membership is
positive. The payoff to j from membership in C, W(j; C), is
[Mathematical Expression Omitted].
Each agency would be willing to join M as a coalition if
[Mathematical Expression Omitted].
for each j [is an element of] M.
The numerator of the RHS of (8) is the number of clients expected to
defect from agency j to other agencies while the denominator is the
number of now clients agency j can expect to gain from other agencies.
The ratio of lost to new clients cannot exceed (s + v)/v.
If (8) does not hold, full freedom of contract will not arise. (8) is
less likely to hold if: i) an agency j is large; ii) an agency is
particularly likely to lose clients; iii) an agency is not likely to
gain new clients; and iv) profit per typical member v increases. The
final condition implies freedom of contract is less likely to arise if
the market for protection is concentrated.
A particularly exploitative agency is relatively unattractive to
consumers. Its ratio of desired defectors to potential newcomers would
be very high so (8) is unlikely to hold for such an agency. Cooperation
is therefore unlikely to involve the worst (from the consumers'
point of view) agencies.
Two factors diminish the possibility of cooperation described here.
First, the probabilities [Pi](j) and [Beta](l; j) may not be known by
all agencies. An agency is less likely to cooperate if it overestimates
the number of clients it expects to lose or underestimates the number of
new clients it expects to gain. Even if agencies are correct on average
in their estimates of [Pi](j) and [Beta](l; j). misestimated components
make cooperation less likely. Estimation could be difficult if
anarcho-capitalism has been in a no exit equilibrium.
Second, the coalition may act aggressively toward nonmember agencies.
As the number of agencies in C increases, the benefit to C of
confronting an independent agency (A) and the probability C wins
increase. In the limit the situation resembles that between an
individual and a protection agency. If C is sufficiently large it could
intimidate A into allowing its disgruntled clients to exit. The
coalition attains the benefits of cooperation with A without having to
allow its unhappy clients to join A.
V. Evidence and Implications
The arguments presented in the previous section suggest the
relationship between private protection agencies and individuals may not
be as one-sided as the distribution of power. Empirical evidence is
necessary to decide the issue. The model of anarcho-capitalism is
abstract and speculative and since it has never been explicitly
implemented, no direct test exists. Several social situations, however,
resemble the model fairly closely and the nature of asymmetric power
relations in these cases provide some evidence concerning the
effectiveness of devices discussed in IV.
Competition between local governments within a federal system is one
example, although the analogy is not exact. The efficient equilibria of
Tiebout models of local public goods provision illustrate the potential
for competition when the costs of movement are low. Cities and states do
offer different sets of laws in the form of zoning ordinances, traffic
laws, and community standards. San Francisco, New Orleans, and Provo,
Utah, are clearly catering to different groups of citizens. States
compete with one another for businesses, both in general laws (on
incorporation and collective bargaining) and with specific tax
concessions and subsidies as with the Saturn Corporation and
professional sports teams. Competition between local governments within
a federal system differs from anarcho-capitalism in one important
respect: the national government prohibits the local governments from
interfering with citizen mobility.(10)
International migrations affect national policies. But nations can
impose restrictions on the movement of persons, capital, and wealth
instead of modifying their policies. Hence competition between national
governments is a very close approximation of anarcho-capitalism. The
German Democratic Republic was extremely susceptible to its citizens
voting with their feet throughout its entire existence. Over two and a
half million people fled to West Germany between 1949 and 1961,
prompting the erection of the Berlin Wall [23, 5]. Migration, first in
the tens of thousands through Hungary in the summer of 1989 and then in
the millions following the collapse of the Wall in November, brought
about reunification. The Iron Curtain shows, however, that nations can
effectively restrict the movements of their citizens. International
capital and wealth flows can also constrain governments and recent
developments in communications, information-transmission, and travel
have significantly reduced the effectiveness of governmental
restrictions on mobility [24]. And restrictions on mobility impose a
cost on national governments in foregone foreign investment and
technology which may outweigh the benefits of a captive population.
Competitive pressures may force a nation to accept liberalization [11].
In addition to placing restrictions on their own citizens, nations
can also offer inducements for defection, which in part offset the
negative controls on mobility of the home country. Higher salaries and
better research facilities in the United States were a cause of the
"brain drain" emigration of scientists, doctors, and engineers
in the 1950s and 1960s. Competition between governments for scholars has
a lengthy history, which reveals considerable mobility by and
consequently a high standard of living for scholars. The Ptolomies of
Egypt lured many scholars from Athens to the Library and Museum of
Alexandria [8, 13-16]. Scholars and students at the University of
Bologna in the 12th, 13th, and 14th centuries were often targets of
raids by other cities in Europe anxious to establish a university [8,
22-27]. One particular group was the object of competing offers from
Florence, Sienna, and Padua, and overall more than twenty such
migrations occurred. In an effort to prevent such departures,
authorities in Bologna first required professors to take an oath not to
leave the university and later imposed the death penalty on professors
who left without permission. The penalties were less than effective, but
the university continued to flourish anyway
... not so much because of the threat of the death penalty ... but
because it managed to develop a policy of strengthening the
institutional framework of the university and its relations with the
authorities of the republic. It also took care that the salaries of the
teaching doctors did not lag behind those of other universities [8, 27].
In addition, freedom of movement has alleviated conditions for serfs
in the early middle ages [35], for freed slaves in the postbellum South
[13], and for prostitutes in the United States [34].
The prostitution market approximates anarcho-capitalism. The
relationship between pimps and prostitutes is asymmetric. Theoretically
pimps could have to compete with one another for the services of women.
Although there is some variance, the relationship often resembles the
Protection Racket Exit Game:
The dangers of strolling someone else's tuff are particularly
acute for newcomers or "outlaws," those who refuse to work for
a pimp. In Boston's famous "Combat Zone" an unwritten code declares that all prostitutes must have pimps. Pimps or their women
beat those who try to beat the system [34, 177].
A prostitute who wishes to switch pimps, or to work without a pimp or
to retire will find that her current pimp will probably feel quite
possessive. Pimps generally wish to control decisions about when a
prostitute may leave his group, so that those who leave on their own
instigation may find the consequences are severe.... Pimps often inflict
violence on unruly prostitutes, as an example to others contemplating
rebellion [27, 21].
Freedom of choice between pimps may be wholly absent thwarting
possibilities for competition and leading to a distribution of rights
which is as lopsided as the distribution of force.
Another example is the asymmetric relationship between bookies and
organized crime in the illegal gambling market. The distribution of
property is skewed in favor of organized crime which successfully
extorts bookies [29, 158-94]. Because they are engaged in illegal
activities, the bookies' possessions are not secured by the state.
To remain in business, potential customers must be able to locate them,
which means the crime syndicate can also always locate and confront the
bookmaker. And the syndicate can cheaply "win" a confrontation
by use of force or by threatening to reveal the illicit activities to
the state authorities. The skewed outcome of the Protection Racket Game
is observed.
Bribes to high level officials, soldiers, and police are a way of
life in many authoritarian nations. These illustrate that Coasian
sidepayments can mitigate the exploitation individuals face. Prostitutes
sometimes purchase their freedom from pimps in this fashion [27, 21-22].
A problem with such payments is that they are not legally binding
agreements. As a result they are most likely to be effective when the
agency cannot renege on its bargain. For example, pimps cannot (legally)
coerce women into (or to return to) prostitution. Border guards cannot
effectively renege ex post on a deal to let someone slip out of the
country.
The rights of local governments within a federal system are not
subject to government protection. The rarity of succession indicates
many federal republics are in the no exit equilibrium. The historical
trend toward stronger national government is a natural result. Swiss
cantons, however, have retained a great deal of autonomy. The
mountainous terrain of the country provides the cantons tremendous
natural defensive advantages securing their initial independence and
maintaining an effective exit option.(11) The rights of individuals are
also subject to encroachment by government as the erosion of economic
liberties under the contract and takings clauses of the U.S.
Constitution illustrates [9; 31].
The experience of miners' camps during the California Gold Rush raises the possibility that force asymmetries may not be very great
[36]. Coalitions of miners or protection agencies can be defined in
terms of transactions costs: these costs must be lower between members
of an agency than between members and nonmembers. High transactions
costs apparently inhibited the formation of miners' coalitions [36,
47-48]. The persistence of organized crime indicates, however, the
mining experience may be atypical. Returns to scale in the conflict
technology also influence the development of protection agencies.
Organizations of sufficient size to exploit individuals were maintained
throughout the Lebanese Civil War of 1975-1990 [14].
What are the prospects for cooperation in anarcho-capitalism?
Spontaneous forces must provide secure property rights and enforceable
contracts to escape the Hobbesian war of all-against-all. Existing
research indicates the latter task can likely be solved contingent on a
solution to the former. And some distribution of stable property rights
is likely to emerge. What is critical, given the libertarian views of
its advocates, is the distribution of rights among individuals and
protection agencies. Government and anarcho-capitalism are alternative
means of protecting individual rights. I have examined several ways in
which the distribution of rights in anarchy might be more equal than the
distribution of force between individuals and agencies. Further research
is necessary to determine the efficacy of each means. The research would
have applications to the situations discussed in this section where
stable possessions must emerge. The political rights of ethnic
minorities and the sovereignty of small nations are two areas where a
more equal distribution of rights than might is desirable on normative
grounds.
1. For an examination of reciprocity and reputation in general
situations, see Axelrod [1], Benson [3], Kronman [21], and Oye [26]. The
role of market forces within the context of a government sponsored
market order is examined in Klein and Leffler [18] and Williamson [38].
2. The weaker party often does better than expected in conflict
situations due to an incentive to fight harder [15].
3. For elaboration on how such a system might work, see Benson
[3,349-78], Friedman [10, 109-64], and Rothbard [28, 219-54]. I most
closely follow Friedman. A discussion of the moral aspects of private
protection agencies and the minial state is contained in Nozick [25].
"Anarchy" actually successfully governs many informal
relations within society [4]. For a bibliography of the literature on
anarcho-capitalism, see Benson [3] and Cowen [7].
4. Many of these issues become moot if the protection agencies turn
out to be gangs.
5. I assume the distribution of these profits does not affect the
choices of any clients in the model.
6. I do not require firms to make positive profit. If firms make zero
profit due to fixed costs then v would be the amount by which the
typical client's payment exceeds avenge variable costs.
7. For a general discussion of reputation, incentives, and
competition see Shapiro and Stiglitz [30].
8. My main concern is agency-individual relations and not the
agency-agency contest success function. For a detailed discussion of
conflict functions and how they affect equilibrium see [16; 32].
9. The game tree of Figure 2 is a possible representation of this
situation; it is not the only plausible representation. In particular
the order of play for A and B could be reversed or made simultaneous. As
a consequence, I do not use subgame perfect equilibrium since then the
analysis would depend on the order of play by A and B.
10. Greater restrictions are placed upon the mobility of firms, such
as layoff notices, environmental regulations, required repayment of tax
breaks, moral suasion, and litigation to prevent relocation.
11. A viable exit option is crucial in the maintenance of a
constitutional contract [22].
References
1. Axelrod, Robert. The Evolution of Cooperation. New York: Basic
Books, 1984.
2. Benson, Bruce L., "The Spontaneous Evolution of Commercial
Law." Southern Economic Journal, January 1989, 644-61.
3. -----. The Enterprise of Law. San Francisco: Pacific Research
Institute, 1990.
4. Buchanan, James M. The Limits of Liberty. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1975.
5. Bush, Winston C. "Individual Welfare in Anarchy," in
Essays on Unorthodox Economic Strategies: Anarchy, Politics and
Population, edited by A. T. Denzau and R. J. Mackay. Blacksburg
Virginia: University Publications, 1976.
6. ----- and Lawrence S. Mayer, "Some Implications of Anarchy
for the Distribution of Property." Journal of Economic Theory,
August 1974, 401-12.
7. Cowen, Tyler, "Law as a Public Good: The Economics of
Anarchy." Economics and Philosophy, 1992, 249-67.
8. Dedijer, Stevan. "'Early' Migration," in The
Brain Drain edited by W. Adams. New York: Macmillan, 1968.
9. Epstein, Richard A. Takings: Private Property and the Power of
Eminent Domain. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985.
10. Friedman, David. The Machinery of Freedom, 2nd ed. New Rochelle,
N.Y.: Arlington House Books, 1989.
11. Fukuyama, Francis. The End of History and the Last Man. New York:
Avon Books, 1992.
12. Greif, Avner, "Contract Enforceability and Economic
Institutions in Early Trade: The Maghribi Traders' Coalition."
American Economic Review, June 1993, 525-48.
13. Higgs, Robert. Competition and Coercion: Blacks in the American
Economy 1865-1914. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1977.
14. Hiro, Dilip. Lebanon - Fire and Embers: A History of the Lebanese
Civil War. New York: St. Martin's Press, 1992.
15. Hirshleifer, Jack. "The Paradox of Power." Economics
and Politics, November 1991, 177-200.
16. -----. 1993. "Anarchy and Its Breakdown." Working Paper
#674B, Department of Economics, UCLA, 1993.
17. Hobbes, Thomas. Leviathan, edited by C. B. Macpherson. New York:
Penguin Books, 1968.
18. Klein, Benjamin and Keith B. Leffler, "The Role of Market
Forces in Assuring Contractual Performance." Journal of Political
Economy, August 1981, 615-41.
19. Klemperer, Paul, "Markets with Consumer Switching
Costs." Quarterly Journal of Economics, May 1987, 375-94.
20. -----, "The Competitivehess of Markets with Switching
Costs." Rand Journal of Economics, Spring 1987, 138-50.
21. Kronman, Anthony T., "Contract Law and the State of
Nature." Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, Spring 1985,
5-32.
22. Lowenberg, Anton D. and Ben T. Yu, "Efficient Constitutional
Formation and Maintenance: The Role of 'Exit.'"
Constitutional Political Economy, Winter 1992, 51-72.
23. McAdams, A. James. Germany Divided. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton
University Press, 1993.
24. McKenzie, Richard B. and Dwight R. Lee. Quicksilver Capital. New
York: Free Press, 1991.
25. Nozick. Robert. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic
Books, 1974.
26. Oye, Kenneth A. "Explaining Cooperation Under Anarchy:
Hypotheses and Strategies," in Cooperation Under Anarchy, edited by
K. A. Oye. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1986.
27. Reynolds, Helen. The Economics of Prostitution. Springfield,
Ill.: Charles C. Thomas, 1986.
28. Rothbard, Murray N. For A New Liberty. New York: Macmillan, 1973.
29. Schelling, Thomas C. Choice and Consequence. Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press, 1984.
30. Shapiro, Carl and Joseph E. Stiglitz, "Equilibrium
Unemployment as a Worker Discipline Device." American Economic
Review, June 1984, 433-44.
31. Siegan, Bernard. Economic Liberties and the Constitution.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980.
32. Skaperdas, Stergios, "Cooperation, Conflict, and Power in
the Absence of Property Rights." American Economic Review,
September 1992, 720-39.
33. Skogh, Goran and Charles Stuart, "A Contractarian Theory of
Property Rights and Crime." Scandinavian Journal of Economics,
1982, 84(1): 27-40.
34. Symanski, Richard. The Immoral Landscape: Female Prostitution in
Western Societies. Toronto: Butterworth & Co, 1981.
35. Tullock, Gordon. Autocracy. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic
Publishers, 1987.
36. Umbeck, John, "Might Makes Rights: A Theory of the Formation
and Initial Distribution of Property Rights." Economic Inquiry,
January 1981, 38-59.
37. Usher, Dan. The Welfare Economics of Markets, Voting and
Predation. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1992.
38. Williamson, Oliver E., "Credible Commitments Using Hostages
to Support Exchange." American Economic Review, September 1983,
519-40.