Green taxes: can we protect the environment and improve the tax system at the same time?
Oates, Wallace E.
I. Introduction
On a cursory inspection, public economics appears to provide a
straightforward and compelling answer of YES to the question posed in
the title to this paper. As economists have long argued, appropriately
designed taxes can, in principle at least, efficiently restrain levels
of polluting activities. And, in addition, such taxes will generate
revenues so that we can reduce rates on other forms of taxation that
distort the functioning of the economy. Green taxes, in short, promise a
"double dividend": they can both reduce excessive levels of
pollution and increase the efficiency of the overall tax system. At
least, so several economists have argued recently [17; 20].
But is this really so? With the growing recognition of the enormous
revenue potential of certain environmental taxes (especially carbon
taxes to address the problem of global warming), public economists have
returned to this question with a new round of research efforts directed
both to understanding the properties of pollution taxes as revenue
sources and to estimating their revenue potential and the magnitude of
their effects on the economy. And the newly emerging literature is
producing some quite astonishing and very troubling findings.(1)
In this paper, I want to review this work and explore its
implications. When viewed in relation to some other research, it appears
to suggest that most forms of regulatory activity (at least those that
increase the costs of the regulated activities) may have hitherto
unappreciated costs of a stunning magnitude. What many of us would have
taken to be "second-order side effects" of environmental and
other regulatory policies can be of a magnitude that compromises to a
significant extent their welfare-enhancing properties. Having reviewed
this body of work, I wish also to explore some issues in the political
economy of green taxes. It is helpful to begin by briefly putting the
issue in historical perspective.
II. Some Background
The early work on Pigouvian taxes or charges essentially ignored the
revenue issue. The assumption, either explicit or implicit, was that the
revenues would somehow be returned to the economy in lump-sum fashion so
as not to cause any distortions in economic activity. The one
qualification in this literature is that the revenues must not be used
to compensate victims for the damages they suffer from polluting
activities, for such compensation would compromise the incentives for
efficient levels of defensive activities by victims. But, for our
purposes here, the essential point is that the early literature (with
the important exceptions of Agnar Sandmo [22; 23] and Yew-Kwang Ng [16])
gave little serious attention to Pigouvian taxes as a source of public
revenues.(2)
A later strand in the literature took up this issue. David Terkla
[27] actually estimated the potential efficiency gains from substituting
revenues from a hypothetical set of nationwide taxes on particulate and
sulfur oxide emissions for revenues from federal income (or
alternatively corporate income) taxes. Using an optimal tax framework,
Dwight Lee and Walter Misiolek [14] explored the determination of
pollution tax rates to maximize the efficiency gains. Drawing on such
work, observers advanced the seemingly compelling intuitive case for a
"double dividend" from pollution taxes. Not only can such
taxes raise social welfare by reducing polluting activities to (or at
least toward) their efficient levels, but they can give us an improved
revenue system by reducing reliance on income, sales, and other
distorting taxes. Pollution taxes, in short, can give us both enhanced
environmental quality and a better tax system.
III. Is There a Double Dividend?
But things do not turn out to be quite this simple. As often happens
when we enter the murky waters of the second-best, our economic
intuition is not a very reliable guide. In this instance, we find that,
in the presence of existing distortions, the introduction of pollution
taxes can itself exacerbate these distortions with a resulting increase
in the level of excess burden. And the striking result in the new
literature is that this effect can easily outweigh the efficiency gains
from recycling the revenues so as to reduce rates on existing taxes.
Thus, there may be no double dividend.(3)
There are certainly instances where a double dividend exists. Sandmo
[24] cites an especially transparent case. Suppose that the revenues
from pollution taxes set equal to marginal social damage provide
sufficient funds to finance the entire public budget. Then, of course,
all distorting taxes can be done away with. And we will achieve both
efficient levels of externality-generating activities and a revenue
system with no excess burden. Here there is clearly a double dividend
from the introduction of environmental taxes. But, more generally, where
pollution taxes must exist alongside distorting levies, the various
economic linkages between the demands for different goods and in their
production will typically be the source of additional excess burden.
To get a better sense of this, consider a case where there exist
taxes on labor income (as in the seminal paper by Bovenberg and de Mooij
[3]). There is thus a distortion in the work-leisure choice (assuming
that the compensated labor supply function is not perfectly inelastic).
A tax on polluting waste emissions in the production of various goods
will raise the price of these goods, thereby reducing the return to work
effort and inducing a substitution of additional leisure for
consumption. Lawrence Goulder [10] calls this the "tax-interaction
effect." And as Ian Parry [19] shows, so long as the output of
polluting industries exhibits a (roughly) average degree of substitution
for leisure, this effect will operate to increase the excess burden
associated with the undersupply of work effort.
Note that although the induced change in work effort (employment) may
be small, the incremental distortion in the labor market can be quite
large because the welfare loss per unit of employment at the margin is
large reflecting the large difference between the gross and net wage.(4)
In terms of our usual diagrams, the point here is that the incremental
distortions take the form of "tall" rectangles so that their
area can be substantial even though their base is relatively small.
These incremental distortions can be offset to some extent by using the
revenues from the pollution taxes to reduce the rate of taxation of
labor income (the "revenue-recycling effect"), but the
conditions required for the revenue-recycling effect to offset fully the
tax-interaction effect are stringent as Parry [18; 19] shows in his
simple and very helpful analytical models.(5) Existing distortions in
the labor market, incidentally, are by no means the only source of
additional excess burdens. Programs, especially those that affect the
prices of intermediate goods, can produce a wide range of incremental
excess burdens in other markets.
We find, more generally, in the large CGE models that are being used
to simulate hypothetical carbon taxes, that the incremental distortions
from pollution taxes can be substantial [2; 13]. The distortions
introduced by these taxes often exceed the reductions in excess burden
from revenue recycling with the implication that the optimal Pigouvian
tax is something less, not more, than marginal social damage. Bovenberg
and Goulder [2], for example, in their seminal work on this issue find
that their model suggests rates of pollution taxation significantly
below Pigouvian levels. Likewise, in his simpler but more transparent
analytical model, Parry [19] turns up tax rates on pollution that, for
certain cases, are roughly 70 percent of marginal environmental damages.
These results are admittedly quite sensitive to the structure of the
models, the values of key parameters (including the elasticity of labor
supply, the elasticity of substitution between polluting goods and
leisure, the tax elasticity of waste emissions, etc.), and the
assumptions concerning the form of revenue-recycling. It is certainly
possible (although not typical in these models) for there to exist a
double dividend - that is, instances where the gains from
revenue-recycling exceed the losses from the distorting effects
associated with the introduction (or increase) in pollution taxes. But
the general thrust of the findings seems to run in the opposite
direction, thus undermining the case for a double dividend.
The cases in which we find a double dividend are typically those
where there is some highly distorting tax in the system (as taxes on
capital may be under certain circumstances) so that the revenues from
the green taxes result in major reductions in existing excess burden
(as, for example, in Jorgenson and Wilcoxen [13]). But this is a
somewhat contrived result in that such efficiency gains could presumably be achieved through tax reforms of other kinds.
I don't wish to suggest that the double-dividend issue is
resolved at this juncture. The outcomes vary significantly across
different models and different assumptions concerning key parameter
values. And they axe especially sensitive to the form that
revenue-recycling takes. But the basic point seems well founded; in
particular, the simpler analytical models (like those of Bovenberg and
de Mooij [3] and of Parry [18; 19]) generate outcomes with no double
dividend in a comprehensible and compelling way. The case for the double
dividend appears shaky at best.
IV. Some Further Implications of the New Literature on Pollution
Taxes
The insight that first-best policy measures may have their
efficiency-enhancing properties compromised by existing distortions is
obviously not a new idea; the second-best has been with us for many
decades. In the field of environmental economics, for example, Albert
McGartland [15] among others has shown that measures to control
pollution in agriculture will have very different effects in the
presence of U.S. farm programs than in an unregulated farm sector. But
such cases involve policy measures with direct effects on distorted
markets.
What is striking here is that apparently secondary effects operating
through linkages with other markets can be of such magnitude. This same
result is emerging in other sorts of studies. Edgar Browning [8], for
example, has re-examined the issue of the welfare losses from monopoly.
The traditional Harberger results based on the distortion in output
markets suggest quite small losses. But when Browning integrates this
analysis into a setting with a large existing distortion at the margin
in the labor market, he finds that the welfare losses from monopoly are
from 5 to 15 times higher than when the effect on the labor market is
ignored!
This suggests that regulatory programs that raise prices of regulated
outputs may have hitherto unimagined costs resulting from the
incremental distortions they generate in other markets. Returning to
environmental policy, consider the case of systems of tradeable
emissions permits where the permits, rather than being sold to sources
at auction, are simply distributed without charge (perhaps under a
grandfathering scheme - like that of the acid-rain provisions in the
1990 Clean Air Act Amendments). Such programs generate no revenues;
hence, there is no revenue-recycling effect to offset (at least in part)
the tax-interaction effect. Parry [18] finds that for such programs, it
is quite possible for the distortions from the tax-interaction effect to
exceed the entire welfare gain from pollution control!
The findings in this newly emerging body of research must certainly
be taken as preliminary at this juncture. Much remains to be understood.
But this work suggests strongly that we must be cautious in drawing
policy conclusions from partial-equilibrium analyses - or from
general-equilibrium analyses that ignore pre-existing distortions in the
system. The effects operating through the linkages between distorted
markets in a general-equilibrium system appear to have far greater
implications for policy design than we have appreciated. And I suspect
that we have just scratched the surface of this issue.
V. On the Political Economy of Pollution Taxes
For the remainder of this paper, I shift the focus to a set of
important issues in the actual design and implementation of pollution
taxes. In the course of legislative debate and compromise, it is easy
for environmental tax programs to become emasculated in ways that
undermine their basic economic rationale. In this section, I want to
comment briefly on what I see as some central matters in the actual
design of pollution tax legislation.
The Tax Base
Economic theory is clear on this issue: taxes on externalities should
be levied directly on the activity that generates the external cost. If
the process of production of some commodity involves the emissions of
damaging wastes, it is the emission of the wastes that should be the
subject of a unit tax, not the commodity itself (aside from the unusual
case of fixed coefficients of production). A tax on the output or
profits of a polluting industry is not, in general, a good substitute
for a tax on the offending activity itself.
There are, of course, cases where because of difficulties of
monitoring waste emissions, we may have no alternative but to tax an
activity closely related to the emitting of the damaging wastes. But
wherever possible we should design the tax to address directly the
polluting act. This may in some instances require some ingenuity. To
take one example, automobile emissions are a primary source of urban air
pollution in many countries. It is tempting to regard such emissions
from a particular vehicle as beyond our monitoring capacities and to
settle for a tax on gasoline. But such a tax, while perhaps discouraging
driving to some extent, fails to provide needed incentives to purchase
automobiles with desirable emissions characteristics and, equally
important, to maintain them in ways to keep pollutant emissions at low
levels. But there are taking place important advances in monitoring
technology. It may soon be possible through periodic inspections (or
perhaps even remote detection devices) to measure the levels of
emissions from individual vehicles and then, with some measure of miles
driven, to fashion tax bills that reflect reasonably accurately actual
emissions.
Auto emissions is obviously a difficult case. It is clearly easier to
levy pollution taxes on sulfur emissions from power plants or the carbon
content of various fuels, but my point here is that in designing these
measures, it is important to be sure that, as closely as possible, we
are taxing the right thing.
Setting the Tax Rate
As Sandmo's [23] earlier paper and the ongoing research makes
clear, the determination of the second-best optimal tax rate on
polluting activities is a complicated enterprise. In particular, it
involves elements that reflect both the environmental costs associated
with the pollution and the way the tax measure interacts with the rest
of the revenue system. In practice, this suggests that the actual design
of environmental taxes will involve two distinct sets of policy makers:
environmental regulators and fiscal managers. And the setting of the
rates of pollution taxes will entail$some sort of compromise reflecting
environmental objectives and revenue needs.
This is a tricky legislative and administrative issue. While
effective cooperation between environmental and fiscal agents is
certainly possible in some settings, it is also easy to think of cases
where one authority or the other will determine the levels of pollution
taxes. Taking a public-choice perspective on this matter, suppose that
the public revenue authority [e.g., Treasury officials or a tax
committee in the legislature] sets tax rates. To take an extreme case,
Geoffrey Brennan and James Buchanan [6] have argued that we can view the
public sector as a revenue-maximizer, a "Leviathan" that seeks
to extract the most it can in public revenues from the economy. For this
polar case, the authority would seek tax rates on polluting activities
that maximize the inflow of revenues- rates that would get us to the top
of the Laffer curve.
What would be the environmental consequences of such behavior? Some
environmentalists have expressed the concern that tax rates are likely
to be set too low from an environmental perspective; such rates they
fear would not provide an adequate incentive to reduce waste discharges.
Is this a legitimate concern or would Leviathan set rates that are too
high? Or put differently, how would the revenue-maximizing rate compare
with the Pigouvian tax rate? There appears not to be a general answer to
this question, for it depends on the elasticity of the tax base. Suppose
that given an existing set of other taxes, the environmental authority,
following the dictates of some environmental economists, were to set
pollution taxes such that marginal abatement costs equal marginal social
damages (although this is admittedly not, in general, optimal in a
distorted setting). Next, suppose that rate-setting authority were
transferred to a Leviathan fiscal agent. Would this agent raise or lower
the tax rates on polluting activities? The answer is that it could go
either way, depending on the elasticity of the tax base (at the
Pigouvian rate). If the base is revenue elastic, our Leviathan agent
would lower the tax rate and vice-versa. Moreover, as Lee and Misiolek
[14] suggest, there is no strong presumption here; their estimates of
the elasticities of the tax base for a number of pollutants in the
United States exhibit considerable variation, some well below unity and
others above unity. Thus, Leviathan could turn out to be either a friend
or foe of the environment!
Note further that for the Leviathan case, there would be no welfare
gains from revenue-recycling; the added revenues would simply go to
swell the size of the public budget. This is admittedly a contrived
case. More realistically, we might expect even a revenue authority to
give some weight to the environmental and other economic effects of
these taxes in the setting of rates. But there are potential problems
associated with the locus of tax authority. If, incidentally, it comes
to a choice of placing pollution taxes under the aegis of either a
fiscal authority or an environmental regulator, my preference would go
to the latter. Pollution taxes are a potentially quite powerful tool for
environmental management, one of a quite limited set of efficient policy
instruments. To place such taxes in the fiscal domain is likely to
discourage environmental regulators from shifting away from their
traditional command-and-control instruments for pollution control.
On Environmental Trust Funds
Environmental taxes have not been widely employed. Moreover, as
Robert Hahn [11] and others have pointed out, environmental authorities
that have used such taxes have typically employed them not so much as
instruments for regulating levels of polluting activities, but rather as
devices to raise funds for environmental projects. Rates have often been
set at levels that will raise the requisite monies for certain
environmental programs, not to regulate waste flows.
This is an important issue in the political economy of environmental
taxes. Various proposed bills in the United States for pollution taxes
have contained within them special provisions for the creation of a
"trust fund" into which the revenues would flow. The funds
would then be allocated to certain kinds of environmental projects. Such
earmarking of funds has a certain appeal. And in the political process
it can be an effective way to coalesce the support of environmental (and
other interested) groups in support of such measures.
But such inclinations, I want to argue, should be resisted. If
revenues from pollution taxes are siphoned off into trust funds, they
will result in increased spending, and there will obviously be no
opportunity to realize the welfare gains from revenue-recycling.
Moreover, it will mean that certain environmental projects are likely to
be undertaken simply because there are unused monies in the trust fund.
Environmental projects should have to meet the same economic and
budgetary tests as other projects; they should not be undertaken simply
by virtue of the availability of some earmarked funds.
Revenue-Neutral Tax Reform and Equity
A more appealing approach to the introduction of pollution taxes is
as part of a revenue-neutral tax package that realizes the potential
gains from revenue-recycling. This approach has considerable political
potential, for the new taxes on pollution can be combined with welcome
reductions in other taxes that will generate support for the proposed
reform.
The Swedish Tax Reform of 1991 is instructive in this respect [1;
26]. Among other elements, the reform act included the introduction of
taxes on carbon-dioxide and sulfur emissions. The revenues from these
new levies were part of a package involving reductions in other tax
rates. In particular, to reduce distortions in the labor-leisure choice,
the top marginal income tax rates were dramatically reduced: these rates
were reduced to about 30 percent for 80 to 90 percent of income earners and to about 50 percent for the remaining high income earners (from a
top marginal rate of 73 percent in 1989 and 85 percent a few years
earlier).(6)
Such revenue-neutral reforms can also address equity issues. There is
concern that broad-based pollution taxes are likely to be somewhat
regressive in their pattern of incidence. And some evidence [21] exists
to support this contention. But in a revenue-neutral tax reform, it is
possible to increase progressivity elsewhere in the tax system so as to
offset (or more than offset) the regressivity inherent in the new taxes
on pollution. Reductions in the lowest tax rates under the income tax or
perhaps tax credits for low-income households can address this
objective.
VI. Some Concluding Remarks
Pollution taxes can play a significant and constructive role in the
revenue system. And the work described in this paper should not, in my
view, be interpreted as a serious challenge to this basic claim. Not
only do such taxes serve to reduce levels of polluting activities, but,
as environmental economists have emphasized repeatedly, compared to
their commend-and-control counterparts, they provide important
incentives for research efforts into new and improved abatement technologies.
The theme of this paper is that the design of these measures must be
undertaken with care. The tax base, wherever possible, should be the
polluting activity itself- not some related activity. Moreover, there is
a strong case to introduce these measures in (approximately)
revenue-neutral ways so that the recycling of the revenues can be used
to reduce some of the more damaging features (in both efficiency and
equity terms) of the existing tax system. The ongoing research on this
issue has much to contribute to our understanding of how best to do all
this.
1. There is much current research addressing this important issue
(most, at the writing of this paper, still in draft form). For a small
sampling, see Bovenberg and Goulder [2], Bovenberg and de Mooij [3; 4],
Boyd, Krutilla, and Viscusi [5], Goulder [9; 10], Johansson [12],
Jorgenson and Wilcoxen [13], Parry [18; 19], and Schob [25].
2. I am somewhat puzzled why the work on optimal taxation in the
presence of externalities by Sandmo [22; 23] and Ng [16] was overlooked.
It certainly did not appear in obscure places. Ian Parry has suggested
that the rather complicated optimal tax formulas may have masked the
interpretation of the results and that their work had no empirical
counterpart to give some sense of its likely importance. But for
whatever reason these papers had no real impact on the environmental
economics literature.
3. See Goulder [10] for a careful treatment of the concept of the
double dividend. The literature employs this term with somewhat
different meanings.
4. See Edgar Browning [7] for an illuminating treatment of the
sources (both tax and non-tax) and the magnitude of the
"wedge" at the margin between the gross and net wage.
5. Note that the revenue-recycling effect is itself offset to some
extent by a loss in revenues from the tax on labor resulting from the
reduction in work effort induced by the pollution tax. This is a kind of
"tax-erosion" effect.
6. It is hard to believe that the efficiency gains from
revenue-recycling were not quite sizeable here!
References
1. Bohm, Peter. "Environment and Taxation: The Case of
Sweden," in Environment and Taxation: The Cases of the Netherlands,
Sweden, and the United States. Paris: OECD, 1994, pp. 51-101.
2. Bovenberg, A. Lans and Lawrence H. Goulder. "Integrating
Environmental and Distortionary Taxes: General Equilibrium Analyses." Unpublished paper, 1994.
3. Bovenberg, A. Lans and Ruud A. de Mooij, "Environmental
Levies and Distortionary Taxation." American Economic Review
September 1994, 1085-89.
4. -----. "Environmental Tax Reform and Endogenous Growth."
Unpublished paper, 1994.
5. Boyd, Roy, Kerry Krutilla, and W. Kip Viscusi, "Energy
Taxation as a Policy Instrument to Reduce C[O.sub.2] Emissions: A Net
Benefit Analysis." Journal of Environmental Economics and
Management, forthcoming.
6. Brennan, Geoffrey and James Buchanan. The Power to Tax: Analytical
Foundations of a Fiscal Constitution. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1980.
7. Browning, Edgar K., "The Non-Tax Wedge." Journal of
Public Economics, March 1994, 419-33.
8. -----. "The Welfare Cost of Monopoly and Other Output
Distortions." Unpublished paper, 1994.
9. Goulder, Lawerence H. "Effects of Carbon Taxes in an Economy
with Prior Tax Distortions: An Intertemporal General Equilibrium
Analysis." Unpublished paper, 1994.
10. -----. "Environmental Taxation and the 'Double
Dividend:' A Reader's Guide." Unpublished paper, 1994.
11. Hahn, Robert W., "Economic Prescriptions for Environmental
Problems: How the Patient Followed the Doctor's Orders."
Journal of Economic Perspectives, Spring 1989, 95-114.
12. Johansson, Olaf. "Optimal Indirect Taxation in a Second-Best
Perspective with Regard to Externalities, A Public Budget Restriction
and Distribution Effects." Unpublished paper, 1994.
13. Jorgenson, Dale W. and Peter J. Wilcoxen. "Reducing U.S.
Carbon Emissions: An Econometric General Equilibrium Assessment."
Unpublished paper, 1992.
14. Lee, Dwight R. and Walter S. Misiolek, "Substituting
Pollution Taxation for General Taxation: Some Implications for
Efficiency in Pollution Taxation." Journal of Environmental
Economics and Management, December 1986, 338-47.
15. McGartland, Albert M., "Implications of Ambient Ozone
Standards for U.S. Agriculture: A Comment and Some Further
Evidence." Journal of Environmental Management, No. 2, 1987,
139-46.
16. Ng, Yew-Kwang, "Optimal Corrective Taxes or Subsidies When
Revenue Raising Imposes an Excess Burden." American Economic
Review, September 1980, 744-51.
17. Oates, Wallace E. "Pollution Charges as a Source of Public
Revenues," in Economic Progress and Environmental Concerns, edited
by Herbert Giersch. Berlin: Springer-Verlag, 1993, pp. 135-52.
18. Parry, Inn W. H. "Environmental Policy in a Second Best
World." Unpublished paper, 1994.
19. -----, "Pollution Taxes and Revenue Recycling." Journal
of Environmental Economics and Management, forthcoming.
20. Repetto, R., R. C. Dower, R. Jenkins, and J. Geoghegan,
"Green Fees: How a Tax Shift Can Work for the Environment and the
Economy." Word Resources Institute Document, Washington, D.C.,
1992.
21. Robison, H. David, "Who Pays for Industrial Pollution
Abatement?" Review of Economics and Statistics, November 1985,
702-706.
22. Sandmo, Agnar, "Direct versus Indirect Pigouvian
Taxation." European Economic Review, 1976, 337-49.
23. -----, "Optimal Taxation in the Presence of
Externalities." Swedish Journal of Economics, March 1975, 86-98.
24. -----, "Public Finance and the Environment."
Unpublished paper, 1994.
25. Schob, Ronnie. "Evaluating Tax Reforms in the Presence of
Externalities." Unpublished paper, 1994.
26. Sterner, Thomas. "Environmental Tax Reform: The Swedish
Experience." Unpublished paper, 1994.
27. Terkla, David, "The Efficiency Value of Effluent Tax
Revenues." Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, June
1984, 107-23.