Unhealthy Charities: Hazardous to Your Health and Wealth.
Lee, Dwight R.
Most economists are by their nature contrarians. Let any proposition
become widely accepted and some economist will begin attacking it with
the heavy fire power of economic analysis. Contrariness does not always
make economists popular, but it does make them useful. Comfortable
beliefs are tempting, but often misguided because they ignore harsh
realities that good economists were put on Earth to constantly and, if
need be, obnoxiously remind people of. Few economists are better
contrarians than James Bennett and Thomas DiLorenzo, and their latest
book, Unhealthy Charities, is a great example of how useful the critical
application of economic analysis to widely held views can be.
Some of the most trusted organizations in America today are health
charities, in particular the Big Three: the American Lung Association,
the American Cancer Society, and the American Heart Association. Because
they are so trusted, the Big Three health charities can raise large sums
of money and have considerable latitude in how that money is used. There
is a widespread belief that most of the money contributed to the Big
Three is being used to fund medical research and to help disease victims
who, because of their income or circumstances, are most in need of help.
Bennett and DiLorenzo put this belief in the crosshairs of their
analytical artillery and unleash a devastating barrage of theory and
fact against it.
Bennett and DiLorenzo examine the three major health charities the
way good economists examine any organization. Of primary importance is
to consider how people who have not yet fully mastered the art of
ignoring their self-interest can be expected to respond to the relevant
incentives. And if the analysis suggests that people will behave
differently than indicated by their pronouncements, it is the
pronouncements that are questioned unless supported by a hard look at
the evidence.
Competition for consumer dollars serves as an effective means of
channeling self-interested behavior into public-interest outcomes in
most private settings. Such competition is not completely without force
in the case of charities, and one implication of a self-interest model
is that those who operate a charity will not appreciate competition from
rival charities even when that competition promotes the charitable
objective. Indeed Bennett and DiLorenzo have a fascinating chapter
(Chapter 8) on attempts by the Big Three health charities to use their
political power to eliminate competition that they would welcome if
their only concern was to advance their stated objectives.
But a crucial difference in the competition faced by most private
organizations and the competition faced by charities results from
different motivations of those paying for the service. In most cases
those who pay for a service provided by an organization are the primary
beneficiaries of the service. So those who pay for the service have the
ability and motivation to determine whether the service meets their
expectations. This is obviously not the case with charities. Those who
pay for charitable services (donors) are not those who receive the
primary benefit (the poor, the infirm, the worthy, the artistic, etc.).
Why then do donors donate? Primarily because of private benefits from
donating to what are seen as worthy causes, positive benefits that come
from feelings of virtue and not-so-positive benefits that come from
social pressure. Donors also receive the benefits of living in a society
with less poverty, better care for the ill, greater artistic
appreciation, etc., if the contributions are used wisely, but these are
public goods and in most cases do little to motivate charitable
contributions. So once a contribution is made, the donor has little
motivation to determine how the money is actually spent. Indeed, there
may be a negative motivation to do so, since information on what a
charity does with your donation may be hazardous to the sense of virtue
you received when making it. It is not surprising then that, as Bennett
and DiLorenzo point out on page 96, "Only a miniscule proportion of
donors takes the effort to check out charities to which they
contribute."
An important implication of "rationally ignorant" donors is
that those who operate charities have more latitude than most people
realize to put their own interests ahead of the interests of their
donors and putative beneficiaries. Far less money donated to the Big
Three actually goes for the worthy purposes they supposedly promote than
most people realize. For example, despite the widely accepted claims by
the Big Three that they are contributing large amounts to medical
research, in fact they contribute very little. And what they do show as
research expenditure is usually seed money to help medical researchers
prepare proposals for federal funding, with tax dollars funding almost
all of the actual research. The researchers selected for receipt of seed
money are, of course, appreciative, and happy to lend their scientific
prestige to enhance the reputation and credibility of the Big Three with
the public. The Big Three use this public support to lobby the federal
government for more funding for the National Institutes of Health
(greatly appreciated by these Institutes), and to urge the NIH to
support favored researchers. The result is a closely knit network of
professionals from the health charities, established research
organizations and the National Institutes of Health which Bennett and
DiLorenzo argue fosters an "in-group" mentality that may have
retarded progress in medical research.
The authors document a host of other instances of how donations to
the Big Three are allocated in ways that do more to serve the private
interests of charity professionals than to promote their stated
objectives. Although economists should not be surprised by the activity
Bennett and DiLorenzo uncover, some of it will shock even us. Bennett
and DiLorenzo make suggestions for reform in their closing chapter, such
as applying state freedom of information acts to health charities. But
their previous discussion does not inspire much hope that these reforms
will be implemented any time soon, or do much good even if they are.
It should be emphasized that although the authors concentrate their
attention on the Big Three health charities, their analysis is quite
general. So if you want to secure at least a warm and fuzzy feeling of
virtue in return for being pressured into donating to the United Way
this year, then don't read this book. But if you enjoy a
provocative discussion, backed up by solid theory and compelling
evidence, then I highly recommend Unhealthy Charities.
Dwight R. Lee University of Georgia