Value judgments and the principles of economics textbook.
Heath, Will Carrington
I. Introduction
Economics principles texts almost never confuse basic theoretical
issues, and yet some of the leading texts do confuse a rather
fundamental point of methodology. They mistakenly identify the
distinction between positive and normative with the distinction between
facts and values--a misidentification that is so widespread as to be
axiomatic for many economists.
The following brief essay will attempt to clear up the methodological
confusion surrounding the positive/normative distinction, then offer
some suggestions as to what should, and should not, constitute the
textbook discussion of this important topic.
II. The Positive/Normative Distinction
Most textbook discussions of economic methodology emphasize the
positive/normative distinction. Samuelson and Nordhaus |12, 9~ give the
subject a fairly standard treatment:
Positive economics describes the facts and behavior in the economy.
What are the causes of poverty in the United States? What will be the
effect of higher cigarette taxes on smokers? How has the economic
performance of socialist countries compared with that of capitalist
countries? These questions can be resolved only by reference to facts .
. . they are all in the realm of positive economics.
Normative economics involves ethical precepts and value judgments.
Should the government give money to poor people? Should the budget
deficit be reduced by higher taxes or lower spending? Should the
socialist countries introduce private property and stock markets? These
issues can be debated, but they can never be settled by science or by
appeal to facts. There are no right or wrong answers to these questions
because they involve ethics and value judgments rather than facts.
This passage confuses two very different distinctions. First is the
distinction between statements of "what is" and statements of
"what ought to be." This, the positive/normative distinction,
correctly recognizes that "ought" statements embody one or
more value judgments in addition to the positive principles of
economics. The other distinction is between facts and values. We refer
to this as the "fact/value distinction," but it actually
denotes an epistemological perspective on value judgments; specifically,
that they lie beyond the realm of objective scientific knowledge.
According to this perspective the "validity" of value
judgments is ultimately a matter of subjective opinion (or even faith)
and as such cannot be tested in any objective sense.
Samuelson and Nordhaus are not the only authors who import the
fact/value distinction into their discussion of the positive/normative
distinction. McConnell and Brue |8, 6~ write that "Positive
economics concerns what is, while normative economics embodies
subjective feelings about what ought to be"; similarly, Gwartney
and Stroup |5, 13~ tell their readers that positive economics
"attempts to determine 'what is'," while normative
economic statements "concern 'what ought to be,' given
the philosophical views of the advocate." They add that "In
contrast with positive statements, normative economic statements cannot
be tested and proved false (or confirmed to be correct) . . . since
their validity rests on value judgments." Parkin |9, 17-18~ states
that a "difference of opinion on a positive matter can ultimately
be settled by careful observation and measurement. A difference of
opinion on a normative matter cannot be settled in that way."
Baumol and Blinder |2, 16~ hope to give their readers "a good
understanding of when the right course of action turns on disputed
facts, on value judgments, and on some combination of the above."
Arnold |1, 20~ states that normative economics deals with "opinions
that cannot be tested," adding that it would be wrong if readers
"accepted as true something that we simply state as an
opinion". According to Spencer and Amos |13, 5~, "Normative
economics consists of subjective and/or unsubstantiated statements that
lack positive knowledge or proof." Byrns and Stone |3, 17~ assert
that "Positive statements may be either true or false," while
"Few normative issues are settled by looking at evidence, because
value judgments involve faith and argument, not scientific proof."
These authors invoke the fact/value distinction as though it were the
very essence of the positive/normative distinction. Correctly
understood, the latter neither entails the former nor depends upon it.
To recognize that normative statements embody value judgments is one
thing, but to pass judgment on the legitimacy of those value judgments
is quite another matter.
III. The Fact/Value Distinction
Let us develop a little further what the fact/value distinction
means. Assertions of truth may be arranged according to the degree of
stringency appertaining to them. First in this ordering would be
statements of pure logic, followed by assertions of empirical fact, and
finally, subjective value judgments. The question is where to establish
the boundaries of objective knowledge, and the fact/value distinction
draws the line between empirical fact and value judgments.(1)
Acceptance of the fact/value distinction seems quite widespread
today, at least among academic social scientists, but it was not always
so; only in recent decades has a fairly general consensus crystallized.
Even the term "value judgment" was absent from the vocabulary
of social science until roughly the second half of the nineteenth
century. The Aristotelian scheme of explanations included four
"causes": the material, the efficient, the formal and the
final. The final cause, or the purpose for which a thing exists or a
change takes place, was teleological, yet considered necessary for a
full understanding of objective reality. During the Middle Ages every
explanation of natural events was value-laden, and even Copernicus
maintained that it was better for the stars to be at rest than for the
earth to be so, because the stars are nobler and more divine.
By the time of Newton, interpretations of nature's processes
were given in terms of "efficient" causation mostly; the
"final" cause had lost its place in science as such. This
"modern" conception of science was gradually assimilated into
the social sciences, due largely to the work and person of Max Weber.
Science meant to Weber the exploration of cause and effect relationships
meticulously kept separate from all value judgments.
The attempt to separate value judgments from pure cause and effect
relationships is entirely appropriate, and not especially controversial,
but Weber actually went much further. When he assumed the editorship of
Archiv fur Sozialwissenschaft und Socialpolitik, Weber declared |15,
55-57~ that "to judge the validity of . . . values is a matter of
faith" and that "it certainly does not fall within the
province of an empirical science in the sense in which it is to be
practiced here" (emphasis in the original). The search for
generally valid value judgments was not to be the task of the Archiv.
Nor could it be "in general the task of any empirical
science," for "|s~uch a thing would not only be impracticable;
it would be entirely meaningless as well."
Though it seems that many, perhaps most, social scientists today
would agree with Weber that the search for scientifically valid value
judgments is "entirely meaningless," it should be recognized
that some respected twentieth-century scholars have held forth against
this view. The eminent political scientist Eric Voegelin, for instance,
maintained |14, 11~ that the fact/value distinction "made sense
only if the positivistic dogma was accepted on principle; and it could
be accepted only by thinkers who did not master the classic and
Christian science of man," adding that "Only when ontology as
a science was lost, and when consequently ethics and politics could no
longer be understood as sciences of the order in which human nature
reaches its maximal actualization, was it possible for this realm of
knowledge to become suspect as a field of subjective, uncritical
opinion."
Among economists, Wilhelm Ropke was perhaps the most eloquent critic
of the fact/value distinction. He believed that some value judgments are
more subjective than others--that is, more subject to individual tastes,
preferences and fancies |10, 11~:
The popular indignation of scientists at value judgments seems to
suggest that it were more or less like a matter of the taste in
neck-ties. In the case of neck-ties our judgments . . . will be highly
various, arbitrary and subject to individual fancies . . . But taking
all possible value judgments together we observe that the degree of
subjectivity may range from anything like zero to 100 per cent. In a
great number of cases, i.e., in that of the more vital and comprehensive
judgments of value, the degree of subjectivity becomes so negligible as
to give them an objective character. Save again for the "idiot
fringe", we all agree on them because they are part of the normal
make-up of man.
Clearly Ropke wished to establish the boundaries of objective
knowledge somewhere within the sphere of value judgments. Who but a
lunatic would prefer disease to health, Ropke would ask, or choose the
actions of a Hitler over those of a Mother Teresa? Why should value
judgments about such matters not be accorded the status of objective
fact? But important questions remain unanswered, perhaps unanswerable:
Precisely how does one know when a value judgment is "less" or
"more" subjective, or how to argue the difference with someone
else who fails to see it? And how would one objectively determine
"the normal make-up of man"? There is little reason to expect
a consensus on these and similar kinds of questions.
The ambiguity and inevitable "messiness" of serious moral
discourse tends to repel many economists, particularly those most
enamored of the simplicity and precision of formal economic analysis.
Yet in recent years it seems that moral philosophers and economists are
again learning from one another, having discontinued virtually all
interdisciplinary communication during the time coinciding (but not
coincidentally!) with the heyday of positivist methodology in both
disciplines. Hausman and McPherson |6~ have surveyed the recent
contributions to normative economics by the diverse works of such moral
theorists as Richard Brandt, John Broome, Ronald Dworkin, James Griffin,
Russel Hardin, Richard Hare, John Harsanyi, Shelly Kagan, Tibor Machan,
John McDowell, Thomas Nagel, Robert Nozick, Derek Parfit, Peter Railton,
John Rawls, John Roemer, Amartya Sen, and Peter Singer, to name just a
few.(2) Hausman and McPherson |6,678~ urge all economists to acquaint
themselves with at least a smattering of modern moral philosophy because
it will "help exorcise unjustifiable skeptical doubts (to which
economists have been prone) about the possibility of rational argument
concerning values." But their cautionary words |6, 712~ also bear
repeating here: "Very little in ethics is completely
uncontroversial . . . We've tried to provide a rough map of the
terrain, but we make no guarantees that those who venture in will not
find some surprises. It's tough and tangled territory."
The objective status of value judgments is an enormously, beguilingly
complicated issue, and an adequate examination of it would take us very
far afield; it is not, at any rate, the purpose of this note. The point
to be made here is that the axiomatic assertion of the fact/value
distinction, as one finds in many textbook discussions, fails to do
justice to the subject, and to those scholars who have thought so
incisively and written so eloquently about it.
IV. Value Judgments and the Principles of Economics Textbook: A
Suggestion
Authors should drop the fact/value distinction from principles-level
textbook discussions of the positive/normative distinction. Normative
analysis embodies value judgments in addition to the positive principles
of economic science, and of course it is appropriate to emphasize this
point in a textbook discussion of economic methodology. It is
appropriate also to emphasize that these value judgments are not among
the principles of economic science. But little else need be said about
value judgments or the question of their epistemological status.
A good illustration of the approach recommended here is offered by
Henderson and Poole |7, 11-12~. They stress that "normative
analysis depends centrally upon value judgments", but nowhere do
they assert that value judgments as such cannot be evaluated. And their
claim that "|e~conomists do not bring to normative analysis any
special claim to expertise regarding preferences or goals" nicely
delineates economics from moral philosophy, but wisely leaves the matter
at that. Ruffin and Gregory |11~ also refrain from pronouncing on the
objective status of values. Their discussion |11, 13~ of normative
economics emphasizes instead the economist's instrumental
role--sorting out the likely effects of this policy or that--with
special attention to the Hayekian "principle of unintended
consequences". They see this principle not as "a council for
despair". Rather, "the principle tells us that the challenge
|of normative analysis~ is to develop good economic policies, not
superficial solutions." Likewise Colander |4, 23~ stresses the
instrumental rationality of normative analysis when he writes that
"in normative economics, economists try to figure out objectively
what will make society better."
One final point. An admittedly subjective normative proposition
underlies this whole discussion: that economic instructors generally,
and not only textbook authors, ought to be more clear, and perhaps less
glib, about the assumptions that underlie economic analyses. Certainly
those who insist upon making the fact/value distinction one of those
assumptions ought to present it explicitly for what it is: a
philosophical perspective on the status of value judgments. Then
students can judge for themselves whether it seems legitimate or false,
helpful or not.
Intellectual honesty would seem to demand that the fact/value
distinction be presented as a debatable proposition; at the very least,
clarity of thought requires that it not be confused with the
positive/normative distinction. Students, and their teachers, deserve
both in their principles textbooks.
1. This discussion borrows from Ropke |10, 3~.
2. For further discussion and particular references, see Hausman and
McPherson |6~.
References
1. Arnold, Roger. Economics. New York: West Publishing, 1992.
2. Baumol, William and Alan Blinder. Economics: Principles and
Policy. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1988.
3. Byrnes, Ralph T. and Gerald W. Stone. Economics. New York: Harper
Collins College Publishers, 1993.
4. Colander, David C. Economics. Homewood, Ill.: Richard D. Irwin,
Inc., 1993.
5. Gwartney, James and Richard Stroup. Economics: Private and Public
Choice. New York: Dryden/Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1992.
6. Hausman, Daniel M. and Michael S. McPherson, "Taking Ethics
Seriously: Economics and Contemporary Moral Philosophy." Journal of
Economic Literature, June 1993, 671-731.
7. Henderson, Vernon and William Poole. Principles of Economics.
Lexington: D.C. Heath, 1991.
8. McConnell, Campbell and Stanley Brue. Economics: Principles,
Problems and Policy. New York: McGraw-Hill, Inc., 1993.
9. Parkin, Michael. Economics. New York: Addison-Wesley, 1993.
10. Ropke, Wilhelm, "A Value Judgment on Value Judgments."
Revue de la Faculte des Sciences Economiques d Istanbul Nos. 1/2, 1942,
1-19.
11. Ruffin, Roy J. and Paul Gregory. Principles of Economics. New
York: Harper College Publishers, 1993.
12. Samuelson, Paul and William Nordhaus. Economics. New York: McGraw
Hill, 1992.
13. Spencer, Milton H. and Orley M. Amos, Jr. Contemporary Economics.
New York: Worth Publishers, 1993.
14. Voegelin, Erik. The New Science of Politics. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1952.
15. Weber, Max. The Methodology of the Social Sciences. New York: The
Free Press, 1949.