Can the government talk cheap? Communication, announcements, and cheap talk.
Conlon, John R.
I. Introduction
A great deal of attention has recently been focused on communication
in economic contexts. While some models of credible announcements have
been based on reputational forces or penalties imposed by third parties,
as in Sobel |21~ and Cothren |4~, several recent papers have addressed
the possibility of communication through "cheap talk," that
is, talk in situations with no explicit penalties for deception. Perhaps
the most prominent application of cheap talk in the literature is the
recent model of Federal Reserve announcements by Stein |22~.(1)
This paper will show that cheap talk equilibria of the sort modeled
by Stein and others often depend in a fundamental way on implausible discontinuities in public responses to government announcements. That
is, cheap talk equilibria are frequently only possible if certain
infinitesimally small changes in government announcements are capable of
causing large, discontinuous changes in public expectations and
behavior.
Intuitively, if public expectations are a continuous function of
government announcements, then the government can "fine tune"
these expectations. The government will therefore often be tempted to
deviate from the cheap talk equilibrium announcements in order to
manipulate expectations. This causes the equilibrium to unravel.
Discontinuous public reactions sometimes prevent these equilibria
from unraveling because they convert continuous choice problems, which
allow manipulative fine tuning, into discrete choice problems, where
such fine tuning is impossible. These discontinuities are implausible,
however, and this may often rule out cheap talk as a realistic model of
governmental policy announcements.(2)
While attention in the next two sections is focused on Stein's
paper for concreteness, a similar criticism also applies to some, though
not all, of the other cheap talk models in the literature. As will be
argued below, cheap talk models seem to fall into two major categories:
(a) models which, like Stein's, depend upon discontinuous
reactions to convert continuous into discrete choice problems, and
(b) models in which cheap talk plays essentially a coordination role,
usually in some sort of intrinsically discrete choice setting.
In models of type (b), the announcer cannot fine tune reactions since
reactions are discrete by assumption. Cheap talk is therefore frequently
more plausible in this case. However, if the discrete choices in models
of type (b) are simply used as an approximation to a continuous choice
reality, then cheap talk in such models may still depend implicitly on
implausibly discontinuous reactions. In such cases, the arguments in
this paper are still relevant.
Section II below describes Stein's model, and section III draws
attention to the discontinuities required in public expectations.
Section IV discusses the plausibility of these discontinuities. Section
V then discusses other cheap talk models in the literature, and section
VI concludes. An appendix generalizes the discussion in section III.
II. Stein's Model
The details of Stein's model are unimportant, since a variety of
different models can lead to the same class of policy dilemmas. However,
to keep the discussion concrete, the following gives a general idea of
how Stein models the Federal Reserve's policy problem. Stein begins
with a two period model in which the Fed has target interest rates with
normalized values of zero in both periods, and target exchange rates of
T in both periods. The public knows the target interest rate of zero,
but does not know the target exchange rate T.
The Fed has one policy instrument in Stein's model, the second
period money supply |M.sub.2~. A high money supply in period 2 pushes
the exchange rate up but pushes the interest rate down. The Fed
therefore chooses the second period money supply |M.sub.2~ = T/2 to
balance off second period interest rate and second period exchange rate
targets. However, the Fed wants the public in period 1 to expect
|M.sub.2~ to equal T, since this will cause the first period exchange
rate to equal the target level of T. Specifically, the Fed would like to
manipulate |Mathematical Expression Omitted~ to minimize |Mathematical
Expression Omitted~ where |Mathematical Expression Omitted~ is the
public's first period expectation of |M.sub.2~. Equivalently, the
Fed would like to manipulate |T.sup.e~ to minimize |(|T.sup.e~ -
2T).sup.2~ where |T.sup.e~ is the public's expectation regarding
the exchange rate target.
The important thing in this model is that the Fed is planning on a
money supply of |M.sub.2~ = T/2, but it wants the public to expect
|M.sub.2~ to equal T. Or, expressed in terms of exchange rate targets,
if the Fed's exchange rate target is T, it wants the public to
believe that its target is 2T. The Fed's dilemma then becomes, how
can any announcement it makes in period 1 be credible, given that it has
an incentive to deceive the public, and no penalty for doing so?
Stein argues that vague, but only vague announcements will be
credible. His argument actually shows less, however. Specifically, he
shows that if the Fed is somehow restricted to a certain discrete set of
permissible announcements, then it will have an incentive to choose the
accurate announcement, so its announcements will be believed. Thus,
Stein's argument must assume some mechanism which will restrict the
Fed to this discrete set of announcements. In the next section it is
shown that the Fed will only restrict itself to this discrete set of
announcements if it is compelled to do so by public expectations which
are a discontinuous function of Fed announcements.
First, however, we summarize Stein's solution. Suppose possible
exchange rate targets for the Federal Reserve board are uniformly
distributed along the interval |Mathematical Expression Omitted~. Also,
suppose that |Mathematical Expression Omitted~ is partitioned using
|Mathematical Expression Omitted~, with
|a.sub.i + 1~ = 6|a.sub.i~ - |a.sub.i - 1~. (1)
Then Stein shows that the Fed will honestly report the interval into
which its target T will fall. That is, if the Fed is restricted to make
announcements of the form:
"T is in the interval ||a.sub.i~, |a.sub.i + 1~~" for some
i, or
"T is in the interval ||-a.sub.i~, |-a.sub.i - 1~~" for
some i, (2)
then it will announce the correct interval.(3) Equilibria of this
kind are called "partition equilibria" |5~.
The intuitive logic of this result is as follows. If the Fed is
forced to choose from the discrete set of announcements in equation (2),
then any deviation from the truth in a given direction will push
expectations too far in that direction, so the Fed prefers telling the
truth to lying. As Stein puts it, "if the Fed wants to lie, it has
to tell big lies, rather than small ones. And . . . such big lies can be
less attractive than telling the truth" |22, 38~. The question
remains, however, what prevents the Fed from deviating from the
announcements in (2), and so, telling small lies? This is the issue
addressed in the next section.
Stein does not himself solve equation (1). However, using standard
methods for solving difference equations |20~, it can be shown that
|Mathematical Expression Omitted~
(this formula can easily be checked by substitution into (1); also,
it is easy to see that |a.sub.0~ = 0 and |Mathematical Expression
Omitted~).(4)
III. A Closer Look at the "Cheap Talk" Equilibrium
It is now shown that the sort of mechanism modeled by Stein requires
the public's expectations to be a discontinuous function of
government announcements. That is, the cheap talk equilibrium breaks
down entirely if small differences in government announcements can cause
only small differences in public expectations.(5) For concreteness, we
focus on the Stein model of Federal Reserve announcements. The general
case is examined in the Appendix.
The key point is that, to determine whether an equilibrium is self
enforcing we must, in the spirit of Kreps and Wilson's |13~
sequential equilibria, indicate what public expectations will be
"off of the equilibrium path." That is, we must indicate, not
only what the public does if the Fed chooses one of the intervals
indicated in (2) above, but also what the public would do if the Fed
made some other announcement. Stein's equilibrium is then shown to
be self enforcing only if the public's reactions to any other
announcement are so undesirable to the Fed, that the Fed would never
choose any announcements other than those indicated in equation (2).
Such undesirable reactions, in turn, are shown to depend upon beliefs
which are implausibly discontinuous.(6)
Suppose that the Fed makes an announcement of the form "our
exchange rate target T is between a and b" (or a |is less than or
equal to~ T |is less than or equal to~ b, or T |is an element of~ |a,
b~). To consider all possible announcements, not just
"equilibrium" announcements, we must let a and b vary
continuously. Finally, let the public's expectation of T given the
announcement "T |is an element of~ |a, b~" be
|T.sup.e~ = f(a, b). (4)
This formulation forces us to model the public's reaction to all
possible announcements, not just equilibrium announcements.
It will now be shown that the public expectations function f is
either constant or discontinuous. That is, either Fed announcements have
no effect on public expectations, or public expectations are
discontinuously sensitive to certain infinitesimally small changes in
Fed announcements.
For suppose that f is continuous and nonconstant. Then as a and b
vary, the range of possible values of f(a, b) must form a closed bounded
interval |A, B~. Using technical jargon, since the domain of f is a
compact connected set (the set of all pairs (a, b) with |Mathematical
Expression Omitted~), the range must be a compact connected subset of
the real line, that is, an interval of the form |A, B~ (see, e.g.,
Theorems 3.4, 3.21, and 3.19 in Armstrong |1~).
Thus, the interval |A, B~ represents the set of all T's which
the Fed can lead the public to expect. That is, f(a, b) |is an element
of~ |A, B~ for all a and b, and for any number T# in |A, B~ there is an
announcement |a, b~ which leads the public to expect T to be T#, so f(a,
b) = T#.
Now, the Fed wants the public to expect T to be |T.sup.e~ = 2T, where
T is its true exchange rate target. Thus, the Fed chooses the
announcement "T in |a, b~" to minimize
|(|T.sup.e~ - 2T).sup.2~ = |(f(a, b) - 2T).sup.2~. (5)
This yields an optimal announcement function which expresses the
announcement interval |a, b~ as a function of the target T, as in
|a, b~ = h(T). (6)
The function h is not necessarily unique. That is, there may be
several different announced intervals |a, b~ which would all lead the
public expectations of T to be the same optimal value.
However, while the optimal announcement function h(T) is not
necessarily unique, it turns out that the composite function f(h(T)) is
unique. This composite function is therefore very convenient to work
with. The function f(h(T)) expresses public expectations as a function
of an announcement chosen optimally as a function of T. That is, if the
Fed's target is T, then its optimal announcement will be h(T), so
the public will expect T to be f(h(T)). Briefly, f(h(T)) is the target
which the Fed leads the public to expect, when the true target is T.
We now show that f(h(T)) takes the following form:
|Mathematical Expression Omitted~.
This may be seen as follows. First, the middle line of (7) simply
says that whenever possible (i.e., when 2T |is an element of~ |A, B~),
the Fed makes an announcement h(T) which leads the public to expect
exactly what the Fed wants it to expect, i.e., 2T, so public
expectations are f(h(T)) = 2T in this case. Similarly, the top line says
that when 2T |is less than~ A, the Fed causes public expectations to be
as close as possible to 2T, i.e., |T.sup.e~ = A, since A is the lowest
value of T which the Fed can lead the public to expect. Thus, f(h(T)) =
A in this case. Similarly, the bottom line indicates that f(h(T)) = B
when 2T |is greater than~ B.
Thus, if 2T |is an element of~ |A, B~, then the Fed gets the public
to expect exactly 2T, and if 2T |is not an element of~ |A, B~ the Fed
leads public expectations to be as close as possible to 2T. The function
f(h(T)) is shown in Figure 1.
Now suppose the public sees the Fed make the announcement "our
target exchange rate T is in |a, b~" where f(a, b) = T# and A |is
less than~ T# |is less than~ B. That is, the Fed makes an announcement
which leads the public's expectation to be strictly between A and
B. Assume that a rational public understands (7). Then the public knows
that T# = f(h(T*)) = 2T*, where T* is the Fed's true exchange rate
target. Therefore, the public knows the Fed's true target T* is
T#/2, so the public expects T to be T#/2, rather than the value T# =
f(a, b) given by the public's expectations function. The
equilibrium therefore unravels. This contradicts the original assumption
that f was continuous but nonconstant.
The expectations function f must therefore either be constant or
discontinuous. If it is constant, then government announcements have no
effect on public expectations. That is, the public ignores government
announcements. If, on the other hand, the public expectations function f
(a, b) is discontinuous, then public expectations must be capable of
changing discontinuously in response to certain very small changes in
government announcements, which seems implausible (see section IV).
Stein's solution does remain a possibility, though his solution
can only be maintained if public expectations are a discontinuous
function of announcements. His solution depends upon public expectations
of the form
f(|a.sub.i~, |a.sub.i + 1~) = (|a.sub.i~ + |a.sub.i + 1~)/2 and
f(|-a.sub.i~, |-a.sub.i - 1~) = -(|a.sub.i~ + |a.sub.i - 1~)/2 (8)
for the |a.sub.i~ given in equation (3).
However, it is not clear how to define f(a, b) for other values of a
and b. Perhaps f(a, b) could be set equal to zero for other values (Fed
announcement ignored). This would require the Fed to make vague
statements, but choose its ranges very carefully. Alternatively, the
public could simply match the Fed's announcement to the closest
approximating interval from (2). This would require public expectations
to be constant for wide variations in Fed announcements, but then change
dramatically in response to other very small changes in announcements.
Each possibility requires discontinuous reactions by the public to
certain slight changes in Fed announcements. The likelihood of such
discontinuities is briefly discussed in the next section.
IV. Are Discontinuous Reactions Plausible?
The previous section showed that cheap talk equilibria of the type
developed by Stein |22~ depend upon public reactions which are
discontinuous functions of government announcements. Moreover, the proof
suggests that, if the set of possible public reactions is sufficiently
dense, then cheap talk will unravel, even if the public reaction
function is discontinuous. As above, the announcer would be tempted to
fine tune public reactions, and so, reveal its true information, causing
the equilibrium to fall apart.
Thus, if one believes that cheap talk of the sort modeled by Stein
actually exists in the economy, then one must conclude that public
reactions are highly discontinuous. It would then be an interesting test
of the theory if one could identify these discontinuities empirically.
Alternatively, if one believes that such discontinuities are
implausible, this would tend to rule out cheap talk equilibria of the
sort modeled by Stein.(7) My own opinion is that such knife-edge
reactions should be very unusual, and should only occur when agents are
acutely aware of their own knife-edge behavior. I know of no compelling
evidence for the existence of such behavior.
Furthermore, the equilibrium also requires perfect unanimity in
public reactions. Heterogeneous public interpretations of Fed
announcements would tend to yield continuity in the overall public
expectations function f(a, b), because any small change in announcements
would cause at most a few people to revise their expectations
discontinuously, and so, cause only a small change in average
expectations. The continuous public expectations function could, then,
be manipulated by the Fed in the manner suggested above. For an argument
along these lines, see Conlon |3~.
On the other hand, it could be argued that the limited number of
words in the English language allows a cheap talk equilibrium to be
maintained without the conscious effort of the Fed or the public.
However, the public must still be extremely suspicious of attempts by
the Fed to fine tune its language. Otherwise the Fed will be tempted to
adopt terms like "somewhat large," "fairly large,"
"quite large," etc., to manipulate the public in the manner
suggested above, and the equilibrium would unravel.
It could also be argued that the implausibility of discontinuous
expectations should be weighed against the possibility that the
uninformative (f constant) equilibrium may not be neologism-proof or
announcement-proof (see, e.g., Farrell |7~, or the discussion in Farrell
and Gibbons |9~ or Matthews et al. |15~). That is, the Fed could do
something like explain a Steinlike equilibrium to the public, and then
announce an interval. However, such neologisms may be more problematic
in the above continuous state space case than in, e.g., the two-state
model of Farrell and Gibbons.(8) This is clearly an issue that merits
further study.
Finally, it should be noted that there are contexts in which cheap
talk equilibria may be more plausible than they are in the case of
government policy announcements. One example is diplomatic language,
which is very rigid, and intended to communicate to a very specialized,
highly trained audience. The argument above suggests that the rigidity of diplomatic language may serve a very specific purpose, since it
limits the ability of the speaker to manipulate the listener through
talk, and therefore preserves some of the communicative value of the
language.
V. Other Cheap Talk Models in the Literature
The previous sections treated Stein's model of Federal Reserve
announcements at some length. In this section, we indicate how our
concerns apply to other cheap talk models in the literature. Our
discussion is necessarily brief, since it is not possible to examine
each of these papers at length. The interested reader is encouraged to
consult the original papers.
Cheap talk models generally seem to fall into two major categories:
(a) models which, like Stein's, depend upon discontinuous
reactions to convert continuous into discrete choice problems, and
(b) models in which cheap talk plays essentially a coordination role,
usually in some sort of intrinsically discrete choice setting.
However, if the discrete choices in models of type (b) are actually
used as an approximation to a continuous choice reality, then cheap talk
in such models may still depend implicitly on implausibly discontinuous
reactions. We now discuss a second model of type (a), and then briefly
describe some models of type (b).
Another Model which Depends on Discontinuities
Perhaps the model which most resembles Stein's in its dependence
on discontinuous reactions is Matthews |14~. The following gives a brief
description of the model (for details see the original Matthews paper).
Suppose that Congress and the President are considering the funding
level of some new program. The Congress's most preferred level of
funding is common knowledge, but the President's most preferred
(target) level of funding is known only to the President, but not to
Congress.
The timing of the process is as follows: First the President makes
some sort of announcement to try to influence Congress. Then Congress
chooses a level of spending and offers a bill to the President. The
President, finally, decides whether to veto the bill or not.
This situation is a lot like the Stein model considered above. The
President is the speaker, and Congress is the audience. The President
would often like to deceive Congress about her target level of spending,
in order to coax a more favorable compromise bill out of Congress. Thus,
in the Matthews model, as in the Stein model, the speaker wants to
mislead the audience, and faces no direct penalty for deception.
In the Matthews model, as in Stein's this leads to partition
equilibria. Therefore, as in Stein's model, successful
communication depends on rigid behavior. In the one nontrivial communication equilibrium, the President simply makes a threat to veto
or not. The President does not vary the intensity of the threat in
proportion with her feelings on the subject, even if she has access to a
very rich language. Similarly, Congress responds to any veto threat with
the same compromise bill. That is, Congress does not respond to
"stronger" threats with more favorable compromises.
As in Stein's model, this rigidity is necessary in order to
prevent the President from telling "small" lies. Thus, suppose
that Congress's behavior was a continuous function of the intensity
of the veto threat, so that a "mild" threat would cause
Congress to yield less, and a "strong" threat would cause
Congress to yield more. Then the President would be tempted to fine tune
Congressional reactions, and, in the process, would reveal her true
target spending level. This would cause Congress to deviate from its
putative reaction function, and the equilibrium would unravel, just as
it does in the Stein case. Thus, the Matthews model depends upon the
same sorts of rigid behavior on the audience's part as does the
Stein model.(9)
Models in which Cheap Talk Plays a Coordination Role
In the Matthews model, as in the Stein model, the state space (i.e.,
the space of things that the speaker knows, but the listeners do not
know) is a continuous set. Thus, in Stein's model, the Fed's
exchange rate target was drawn from a uniform distribution in the
interval |Mathematical Expression Omitted~, while in the Matthews model,
the President's most preferred spending level was also drawn from a
continuous distribution on an interval. The listeners' action
spaces in the two models were also continuous.
Thus, if the speaker has access to a sufficiently rich language in
these models, and if audience reaction functions are continuous, then
the speaker will be able to fine tune the listener's reactions.
Therefore, if the speaker wants to deceive the audience, the equilibrium
unravels.
However, if the state and action spaces are discrete, then cheap talk
may be more robust. Thus, consider the two person game in figure 2. In
this game, there are two possible states of the world, |t.sub.1~ and
|t.sub.2~, corresponding to the two rows in the figure. One person, the
"speaker," knows the state of the world. The other person, the
"receiver," can take one of two possible actions, L and R,
corresponding to the two columns in the figure. The first (second)
number in the cell gives the speaker's (receiver's) payoff as
a function of the state of the world and the receiver's action.
Thus, if the state of the world is |t.sub.1~, and the receiver chooses
action L, then the speaker gets payoff 3 and the receiver gets 2. Note
that the speaker cannot control the state of the world, but he/she can
communicate with the receiver.
In this game, one very plausible equilibrium is for the speaker to
always truthfully reveal the state of the world, and for the receiver to
choose L if the speaker says the state is |t.sub.1~, and choose R if the
speaker says the state is |t.sub.2~.
In this game, the speaker has no incentive to manipulate the
receiver, since truthful revelation already induces the receiver to act
in exactly the way that the speaker wants. In a sense, there is no
conflict of interest in this game, and cheap talk plays essentially a
coordination role. Thus, even though talk is cheap, the equilibrium
seems fairly robust.
Several papers in the literature model cheap talk in roughly this
way. That is, they assume discrete state and/or action spaces, and model
cheap talk as essentially a form of coordination. However, if the
discrete state and action spaces in these models are seen as
approximations to continuous state and action spaces, then these models
may depend, implicitly, on the same sorts of discontinuous reactions as
the Stein and Matthews models.(10) Thus, even in this sort of model,
thought must be given to the appropriateness of cheap talk equilibria in
actual applied situations.(11)
By contrast, cheap talk may sometimes play a coordinating role in
situations where the discreteness of choices arises naturally in the
model. For example, Farrell and Saloner |10~ show that cheap talk can
facilitate coordination when agents are faced with the discrete choice
of whether or not to switch from an old standard to a new one (e.g.,
from the English to the metric system of measurements). Similarly,
Farrell |6~ shows that two firms may coordinate using cheap talk when
they are each considering the discrete choice of whether or not to enter
a market which is too small for both of them. Other models that may fall
into this category are Ordeshook and Palfrey |18~, and Forges |11~.
Perhaps the most striking example of cheap talk as a coordination
device is in Matthews and Postlewaite |16~. In this model, a seller with
private information can use cheap talk to choose from a continuum of
possible equilibria, depending on her type. In one equilibrium, cheap
talk completely reveals the speaker's type. However, the subsequent
play following the announcement is an equilibrium, and, in fact, the
equilibrium most preferred by the speaker, even though the
speaker's type is fully revealed. Thus, the revealed information
does not cause the equilibrium to unravel, in contrast to the Stein case
discussed above.(12)
VI. Conclusion
The reasoning above suggests that "cheap talk" equilibria
of the sort considered by Crawford and Sobel |5~, Stein |22~, and
Matthews |14~ may provide implausible models of communication. If we
want to discipline our model building efforts by assuming that the
public's expectations are a continuous function of government
announcements, we must conclude that "cheap talk" will have no
effect on audience reactions in these models.
The analogy with Samuelson's |19~ correspondence principal may
be illuminating in this regard. Just as the correspondence principal
rules out equilibria which are dynamically unstable, in the same way,
the assumption of continuity of public expectations rules out
"cheap talk" models of policy announcements, since if
expectations are a continuous function of government announcements, then
the government will attempt to manipulate the public, and the
equilibrium will break down.
One must therefore conclude that models in which government policy
announcements convey information to a rational public must either posit
some sort of reputation building process, as in Sobel |21~, or assume
that some third party imposes costs of some sort for dishonest policy
announcements, as in Cothren |4~. Similarly, models that seek to explain
vague announcements should look for foundations other than cheap talk.
One obvious source of vagueness, for example, might simply be government
uncertainty about future plans.
Finally, if one believes that cheap talk is important, even when the
speaker would like to deceive the listener, it seems to me that one must
either (i) argue that agents actually face a discrete choice framework
of a sort which facilitates cheap talk, or (ii) show that the sorts of
discontinuities discussed in this paper actually exist empirically.
Results of type (ii) would be as interesting as they would be
surprising.
Appendix
In this appendix we will extend the argument in the paper to the case
in which government plans, |G.sup.p~, and the public expectations
desired by the government, |G.sup.de~, are arbitrary (well behaved)
functions of the state of the world, x, and show that nontrivial cheap
talk is usually not possible with well behaved public expectations
functions.
Suppose that the government's policy plan, G, depends on the
state of the world, x, as in G = |G.sup.p~(x). Let x be drawn from some
compact, connected probability space X. In addition, suppose that the
value of G which the government wants the public to expect also depends
on the state of the world as in |G.sup.de~ = |G.sup.de~(x), where
"de" stands for "desired |public~ expectations."
Assume that |G.sup.p~ and |G.sup.de~ are continuous.
A credibility problem arises unless the expected value of the
government's policy plan |G.sup.p~(x), given that the government
wants the public to expect |G.sup.de~(x) = G*, is exactly the value, G*
which the government wants the public to expect, or,
E||G.sup.p~(x) such that |G.sup.de~(x) = G*~ = G*. (A1)
Equation (A1) says that, on average, the government will not bias the
public's expectations systematically one way or the other. If (A1)
holds, then the government can simply announce that it wants the public
to believe G*, and a rational public will know that |G.sup.p~(x) will be
G* plus an unpredictable noise term.
A conflict arises when (A1) is almost never true. Thus, for example,
in Stein's case, with G = |M.sub.2~ and x = T, we have |G.sup.p~ =
T/2 and |G.sup.de~ = T, so
E||G.sup.p~(x) such that |G.sup.de~(x) = G*~ = E|T/2 such that T =
|M*.sub.2~~ = |M*.sub.2~/2 = G*/2. (A2)
Thus (A1) is only true for G* = 0 in Stein's case, and the
government faces a credibility problem. To generate a similar conflict
in the general case, assume
Equation (A1) holds for at most a finite set of G*, (A3)
so the government usually has an incentive to systematically deceive
the public.
Suppose the government uses announcements to manipulate public
expectations. Also, suppose as in Stein's case that the government
chooses its announcements, |Alpha~, out of a continuous, compact and
connected set S of possible announcements (in Stein's case,
possible announcements take the form "T is in the interval |a,
b~" with |Mathematical Expression Omitted~). Finally, assume that
public expectations as a function of government announcements are given
by the function |G.sup.e~ = f(|Alpha~).
The announcement function f is either constant or discontinuous. For
suppose f is continuous but not constant. Since S is compact and
connected, so is the set f|S~ of all values of G which it is possible
for the government to lead the public to expect. Since this compact
connected set is a subset of the real line, it is an interval of the
form |A, B~. Thus, it is possible for the government to get the public
to expect G to be any value between A and B.
Now, the government chooses an announcement function |Alpha~ = h(x)
to minimize
|(|G.sup.e~ - |G.sup.de~(x)).sup.2~ = |(f(|Alpha~) -
|G.sup.de~(x)).sup.2~. (A4)
Thus, h(x) gives the optimal announcement for the government to make,
as a function of the state x (note that h is not necessarily unique). An
argument similar to that in the text shows that f(h(x)) is given by
|Mathematical Expression Omitted~.
Thus, when A |is less than~ |G.sub.de~(x) |is less than~ B, the
government's announcement perfectly reveals the value,
|G.sup.de~(x), of G which the government wants the public to expect.
Therefore, if the government's announcement initially causes the
public to expect |G.sup.p~ to be G* = f(|Alpha~) with A |is less than~
G* |is less than~ B, then the public will rethink, remember (A5)
conclude that |G.sup.de~(x) = G*, and so instead expect |G.sup.p~ to be
E||G.sup.p~(x) such that |G.sup.de~(x) = G*~, (A6)
which is different from G* for most G* in (A, B), by (A3). This
contradicts f(|Alpha~) = G*, so our original assumption that the public
expectations function f was nonconstant and continuous must be wrong.
1. Other cheap talk models will be discussed in section V below.
2. Alternatively, one could interpret the results in this paper as
suggesting that public expectations actually do respond to announcements
in a discontinuous manner. This seems unlikely. For example, if there is
any uncertainty about the underlying parameters, and opinions differ,
then average public expectations will tend to be a continuous function
of announcements. For a further discussion, see section IV.
3. The argument goes as follows: If the Fed announces that its target
exchange rate T is in the interval ||a.sub.i~, |a.sub.i + 1~~, and is
believed, then the public expects the target exchange rate to be
(|a.sub.i~ + |a.sub.i + 1~)/2. When the Fed's actual target is T =
|a.sub.i~, the Fed would like the public to expect |T.sup.e~ =
2|a.sub.i~, but it is indifferent between public expectations of
|T.sup.e~ = (|a.sub.i - 1~ + |a.sub.i~)/2 and |T.sup.e~ = (|a.sub.i~ +
|a.sub.i + 1~)/2, assuming the |a.sub.i~ satisfy equation (1). Thus, the
Fed is indifferent between the announcements ||a.sub.i - 1~, |a.sub.i~~
and ||a.sub.i~, |a.sub.i + 1~~. If the target exchange rate T is in the
interior of the interval ||a.sub.i~, |a.sub.i + 1~~, however, then the
Fed prefers the announcement ||a.sub.i~, |a.sub.i + 1~~ to the
announcement ||a.sub.i - 1~, |a.sub.i~~. Proceeding in this way shows
that the Fed will always announce the correct interval. See Stein |22~
for details.
4. Incidently, equation (3) can be used to show that the formula in
Stein's Proposition 2 is incorrect. It should read |lim.sub.i|right
arrow~|infinity~~|a.sub.i~/|a.sub.i + 1~ = |(3 + |square root of
8~).sup.-1~ which equals 0.1715728 . . . Stein's incorrect formula
(involving a geometric sum) simplifies to 35/204 = 0.1715686 . . . These
two numbers are identical if rounded off to five digits as Stein does,
but the formulas do give slightly different numbers.
5. This actually can be shown to follow from Crawford and
Sobel's |5~ solution. However, the following line of reasoning is
less complicated. It also draws on familiar arguments about the
difficulty of manipulating rational agents.
6. Kreps and Wilson |13, 864~ argue that "making explicit the
construction of beliefs off the equilibrium path enables discussion of
which beliefs are 'plausible' and which are not". Thus,
for example, this paper shows that out-of-equilibrium beliefs in a
solution such as Stein's must be discontinuous. It then argues that
this discontinuity is implausible, so that Stein's cheap talk
equilibrium provides an unrealistic model of public reactions to
government announcements. See Kreps |12~, which reviews a growing
literature on equilibrium refinements based on out-of-equilibrium
beliefs.
7. Note that since messages do not enter the utility function
directly, one cannot rule out discontinuous reaction functions a priori.
Thus, ruling out discontinuous reactions reflects beliefs about
"likely," as opposed to strictly rational behavior.
8. The simplest credible neologism seems to be, e.g.,
"|Mathematical Expression Omitted~." An argument similar to
that in note 3 shows that the Fed would prefer this statement to the
no-communication expectation |T.sup.e~ = 0 precisely when T is in
|Mathematical Expression Omitted~. Thus, this neologism is credible,
though, as above, the public should be suspicious unless it is confident
that everyone would reject misleading neologisms such as
"|Mathematical Expression Omitted~."
The statement "|Mathematical Expression Omitted~" would
also be a "weakly credible announcement," in the terminology
of Matthews, Okuno-Fujiwara, and Postlewaite |15~. However, it would not
be a "credible announcement," using the Matthews et al.
terminology, because there are other weakly credible announcements which
the Fed would sometimes prefer to make, even if |Mathematical Expression
Omitted~. Thus, the Fed's choice of one such announcement over
another may reveal too much information about the Fed's true
target. This suggests that the equilibrium with no communication may be
acceptable under the "announcement-proof" criterion, which is
the criterion preferred by Matthews, Okuno-Fujiwara and Postlewaite
|15~.
It is also worth noting that in communication games of this sort, no
equilibrium is generally neologism proof |7~.
9. Certain considerations, however, may make the equilibrium here
somewhat more plausible than in Stein's case. First, since the
decision whether or not to veto is a discrete choice, this may give the
two-message equilibrium a certain saliency, with Congress simply
ignoring the intensity of the threat, and so, the President making no
statements about this intensity.
Second, congressional debate, committee structure, etc., may help
congresspeople to focus on the discontinuous reactions necessary to
support a nontrivial cheap talk equilibrium.
Third, Congress reacts to any Presidential statement with a vote. If
we assume the median voter hypothesis, then the median Congressional
reaction may be a discontinuous function of announcements, in accordance with the equilibrium, even if Congressional reactions to announcements
are not unanimous; all that is necessary is that the median
Congress-person act in accordance with the equilibrium (see Conlon |3~).
On the other hand, with logrolling, the median voter hypothesis may be
invalid |17, 82-6~, so the equilibrium may require essentially unanimous
reactions.
10. For example, Austen-Smith |2~ introduces discreteness by allowing
agents to observe a single realization of a discrete distribution. If
the distribution had been continuous, by contrast, then cheap talk may
have required partition equilibria.
Similarly, Farrell and Gibbons |9~ simply posit a discrete choice
problem. The argument above thus suggests that the lessons of the
Farrell and Gibbons paper may extend with some difficulty to the
continuous choice case.
11. On the other hand, a continuous state and action space model may
sometimes be seen as an approximation to a discrete state and action
space model in which the state and action spaces form a fine grid. The
study of cheap talk in such models therefore merits additional study.
Matthews, Okuno-Fujiwara, and Postlewaite |15~ provide an extremely
interesting treatment of cheap talk in a wide range of discrete state
and action space models. Their work shows, among other things, that
cheap talk is by no means unproblematic, even in the discrete choice
framework.
12. For another example of cheap talk between a buyer and seller, see
Farrell and Gibbons |8~.
References
1. Armstrong, Mark A. Basic Topology. New York: Springer-Verlag,
1983.
2. Austen-Smith, David, "Information Transmission in
Debate." American Journal of Political Science, February 1990,
124-52.
3. Conlon, John R. "Robustness of Cheap Talk with a Large
Audience." Paper presented at the North American Summer Meetings of
the Econometric Society, Seattle, June, 1992.
4. Cothren, Richard, "Asymmetric Information, Optimal Money
Growth Targets, and Fed Secrecy in a Monetary Policy Game," Journal
of Macroeconomics, Fall 1990, 599-609.
5. Crawford, Vincent and Joel Sobel, "Strategic Information
Transmission." Econometrica, November 1982, 1431-51.
6. Farrell, Joseph, "Cheap Talk, Coordination, and Entry."
Rand Journal of Economics, Spring 1987, 34-39.
7. -----, "Meaning and Credibility in Cheap-Talk Games,"
forthcoming in Games and Economic Behavior.
8. ----- and Robert Gibbons, "Cheap Talk Can Matter in
Bargaining." Journal of Economic Theory, June 1989, 221-37.
9. ----- and -----, "Cheap Talk with Two Audiences."
American Economic Review, December 1989, 1214-23.
10. ----- and Garth Saloner, "Standardization, Compatibility,
and Innovation." Rand Journal of Economics, Spring 1985, 70-83.
11. Forges, Francoise, "Equilibria with Communication in a Job
Market Example." Quarterly Journal of Economics, May 1990, 375-98.
12. Kreps, David M. "Out-of-Equilibrium Beliefs and
Out-of-Equilibrium Behavior," in The Economics of Missing Markets,
Information, and Games, edited by Frank Hahn. Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1990.
13. ----- and Robert Wilson, "Sequential Equilibria."
Econometrica, July 1982, 863-94.
14. Matthews, Steven A., "Veto Threats: Rhetoric in a Bargaining
Game." Quarterly Journal of Economics, May 1989, 347-69.
15. -----, Masahiro Okuno-Fujiwara, and Andrew Postlewaite,
"Refining Cheap Talk Equilibria." Journal of Economic Theory,
December 1991, 247-73.
16. ----- and Andrew Postlewaite, "Pre-play Communication in
Two-Person Sealed-Bid Double Auctions." Journal of Economic Theory,
June 1989, 238-63.
17. Mueller, Dennis C. Public Choice II. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1989.
18. Ordeshook, Peter C., and Thomas R. Palfrey, "Agendas,
Strategic Voting, and Signaling with Incomplete Information."
American Journal of Political Science, May 1988, 441-66.
19. Samuelson, Paul A. Foundations of Economic Analysis. New York:
Atheneum, 1965.
20. Sargent, Thomas J. Macroeconomic Theory, Second Edition. Orlando:
Academic Press, 1987.
21. Sobel, Joel, "A Theory of Credibility." Review of
Economic Studies, July 1985, 557-73.
22. Stein, Jeremy C., "Cheap Talk and the Fed: A Theory of
Imprecise Policy Announcements." American Economic Review, March
1989, 32-42.