Finance Behind the Veil of Money: An Essay on the Economics of Capital, Interest, and the Financial Market.
Howden, David
FINANCE BEHIND THE VEIL OF MONEY: AN ESSAY ON THE ECONOMICS OF
CAPITAL, INTEREST, AND THE FINANCIAL MARKET
EDUARD BRAUN
LIBERTY.ME, 2014, XXIV + 342 PP.
Based on his doctoral thesis directed by Jorg Guido Hulsmann (who
also wrote the foreword to the book), German economist Eduard
Braun's Finance Behind the Veil of Money aims to show how money
affects our financial decisions. The reader will notice that Braun
approaches this goal from a different angle of most Austrian-school
economists. Instead of looking at how money and credit affect interest
rates and propagate an Austrian business cycle, Braun focuses on the
"subsistence fund." Largely jettisoned from modern Austrian
business cycle theory, in a way Finance Behind the Veil of Money picks
up where Richard Strigl left off with his Capital and Production (1934).
In expounding an updated theory of the definition and role of the
subsistence fund, Braun rewards the reader for the time dedicated to
reading the book. This time is not insubstantial. At 342 pages, the book
is neither concise nor easy reading. It is heavy, dense, technical and
littered with citations. The publisher's exclusive use of endnotes
makes the going tougher yet, as the reader constantly finds himself
flipping pages to find out to whom Braun is attributing a concept, to
what era the idea belongs or, indeed, since Braun uncovers the changing
thoughts of several authors over their lifetimes, to what specific work
of an author he is referring.
Adding to the difficulties are several chapters with only
tangential relevance to the subject at hand. Two sections of chapter 17
discuss, for example, monetary systems that separate money's
pricing and exchange roles (pp. 170-177). Chapter 19, dealing with the
role of the financial market, seems to not contribute anything to his
book than to bring the level down from an otherwise high standard by
stating, at length, the obvious: that financial markets intermediate
savings through loan and equity investments. Chapter 22, dealing with
the German financial crisis of 1873, seems an unlikely addition to an
otherwise theory-laden book. (One interesting yet inadequately explained
tidbit in this chapter is that dividend yields on German shares rose
throughout the boom [p. 242], i.e., at the same time as credit expansion
was relatively lowering interest rates. Since the rise in dividend
payout ratios runs against common sense and experience, it would be nice
if Braun could more thoroughly explain this paradox.)
Most readers will no doubt find many passages in the book to be
either confusing at best, or wrong at worst. For example, Braun takes on
the whole doctrine of opportunity cost analysis claiming that it
"creates costs where they do not exist--in decisions--and neglects
costs when they actually arise--in action" (p. 33).
I don't see much neglect by economists of the use of
opportunity costs in action. The corollary is that such costs must also
affect our decisions. Ask any first-year economics student what the cost
of Braun writing his book was and he will surely say "the value he
would give to the next-best alternative on which he could have spent the
time." In other words, opportunity cost in action. For the sake of
argument, let's assume Braun's next best use of his time was
to practice playing piano. On what basis did he decide to write the book
and thus not practice piano? Opportunity cost, of course. Since the time
commitment was the same and defined (let's assume) Braun's
only two options, he pursued the one he valued more highly (or what is
the same, had the lower opportunity cost).
Braun's chapters on the time-preference theory of interest
will meet the most resistance. Indeed, they are the places where this
reviewer found himself either lost or unable to agree with Braun's
reasoning. Mostly the troubles crop up early as he lays the building
blocks for his subsequent theory. Consider the following passage as a
case in point.
Everything one does must be called consumption because, apparently,
one wants to do it. Someone who saves an apple for next month does
not save at all. Instead, he consumes. He prefers the Apple in his
fruit bowl to the enjoyment of eating it right now. Hence, the
decision whether to eat the apple is not a decision between a
present a good and a future good. It is rather a decision between a
present good on the one hand--eating an apple--and a combination of
a present good and a future good on the other. (p. 21)
In short, Braun does not believe that the "value difference
between present and future goods" (p. 40) exists by necessity. For
him, it is not a praxeological law. On the one hand, sure, if we want to
start defining consumption as doing what one wants, then I have no
quarrel with Braun's argument. On the other hand, there are good
reasons to separate actions into productive and consumptive activities.
Menger's imputation theory of value makes it clear that the value
of higher-order (capital) goods can only derive from the value placed on
the utility of lower-order, or consumers', goods (Menger, 1871, pp.
55-67). Braun makes much use of the value and general price level of
consumers' goods later on, particularly in his look at the
purchasing power of money in chapter 16. If every good is a consumer
good, one wonders how these two chapters can be reconciled.
Braun states the traditional pure time-preference theory (PTPT) of
interest as one comparing present goods with future goods. He criticizes
Hulsmann's theory of interest on the same grounds, as "the
term 'future good' [is] a synonym for the [term]
'means'" (p. 51). Yet, while early Austrian-school
economists, e.g., Menger and Bohm-Bawerk, focused on the intertemporal
value spread between the same quality and quantity of goods, later
generations had a more nuanced approach.
By the time the pure time preference theory (PTPT) of interest
reached its full elaboration by Fetter (1914), a work which is absent
from Braun's otherwise very comprehensive reference list, it was
clearly based on a comparison of satisfactions equal in all but their
timing. To be sure, some of the earlier Austrian authors and especially
Bohm-Bawerk focus on the intertemporal value spread between present and
future goods that Braun attacks. (1) It is true to say that Fetter
considered that the rate of interest could only be embodied through one
specific good, i.e., money, since any capitalization of expected future
values could only be imputed to the present by means of a common
denominator (Fetter, 1915, p. 116). But the origin of time preference is
reckoned by the intertemporal value spread of wants expressed in money
terms. Nor is it true that Fetter's PTPT of interest is rooted in
psychological factors, as Braun (p. 17) suggests. Indeed, Fetter was
critical of Bohm-Bawerk's reliance on both psychological reasoning
and physical differences of goods, instead of value differences (Fetter,
1914, p. 127fn2).
Yet, for all its difficulties, the reader is duly rewarded for
trudging on.
Braun puts forward the idea that the only "difference between
saving and investing lies in the time dimension" (p. 55). In this
Braun makes a very important point. Savings are always in money terms
(or rather, income terms). Therefore, savings are always unconsumed
income. Investing is the act of converting this unconsumed income to a
claim to a future good (i.e., not consuming it). Thus, savings can only
have one dimension: a value dimension as per the value of the unconsumed
goods.
Investment is bidimensional: the value of the unconsumed
consumers' goods, and the duration of their tie-up.
The somewhat smallish early quibbles and marginal contributions
aside, the book gets really interesting in chapter 16 on "The Role
of the Purchasing Power of Money in the Business Sphere." In this
chapter, he draws heavily from Friedrich Weiser and Arthur Marget to
show that the purchasing power of money in terms of producers'
goods is not relevant to human action. Ultimately, Braun's argument
is just an extension of Menger's imputation theory of value. Since
all value derives from that places on consumers' goods, so too must
money's.
The reader should trudge his way through this book for two reasons.
First is the aforementioned explanation for why the purchasing power of
money must be defined in terms of consumers' goods prices, not
capital goods. (Though this is an ironic conclusion for Braun to make
given his doubts in the early part of the book as to whether it is even
possible to speak of anything other than consumers' goods. Perhaps
he should restate his theory so that the purchasing power of money is
only defined in terms of goods' prices, though this reviewer thinks
this would be a step backwards.)
Second, and more importantly, Braun resurrects the subsistence fund
doctrine. There is no doubt in this reviewer's mind that he is the
foremost authority on this bygone relic of Austrian business cycle
theory. This is unfortunate, not because I don't think Braun is up
to the task, but because it is such an integral aspect of business cycle
theory and completely neglected by modern writers. Braun takes the
reader through the historical development of the concept, and gives a
good overview of the difficulties that third and fourth generation
Austrian-school economists encountered when trying to "sell"
this aspect of their business cycle theory. While most sympathetic
economists emphasize Hayek's "loss" to Keynes and the
ensuing death knell of broad acceptance of Austrian business cycle
theory as due to ideological factors, after reading Braun's book an
equally defensible explanation arises. Hayek was unable to provide a
satisfying real resource constraint in his business cycle theory. In
part this was because of the difficulties in updating the subsistence
fund concept to the modern financial economy. Braun doesn't quite
get there, but he's definitely taken many steps in the right
direction.
REFERENCES
Bohm-Bawerk, Eugen von. 1889. Positive Theory of Interest. Spring
Mills, Penn.: Libertarian Press, 1959.
Herbener, Jeffrey M. 2011. "Introduction." In Jeffrey M.
Herbener, ed. The Pure Time-Preference Theory of Interest, pp. 11-58.
Auburn, Ala.: Ludwig von Mises Institute.
Fetter, Frank A. 1914. "Interest Theories, Old and New."
In Jeffrey M. Herbener, ed., The Pure Time-Preference Theory of
Interest, pp. 127-157. Auburn, Ala.: Ludwig von Mises Institute, 2011.
Fetter, Frank A. 1915. Economic Principles. New York: The Century
Co. Menger, Carl. 1871. Princples of Economics, James Dingwell and Bert
F. Hoselitz, trans. Auburn, Ala.: Ludwig von Mises Institute, 2007.
Strigl, Richard von. 1934. Capital and Production, Margaret
Rudelich Hoppe and Hans-Hermann Hoppe, trans., in Jorg Guido Hulsmann,
ed. Auburn, Ala.: Ludwig von Mises Institute, 2000.
David Howden (dhowden@slu.edu) is Chair of the Department of
Business and Economics and Professor of Economics at St. Louis
University, Madrid Campus, Spain.
(1) Bohm-Bawerk attributes the preference for present over future
goods as a tendency brought about by three complementary causes
(Herbener, 2011, pp. 31-34). First, since any present good can be
enjoyed by the owner until some future time, the value in the present
must necessarily be greater than that of the future (Bohm-Bawerk, 1889,
p. 266). Second, that "we systemically undervalue our future wants
and also the means which serve to satisfy them" (p. 268). Finally,
that "as a general rule," present goods are technologically
preferable to future goods as concerns their ability to satisfy wants,
and as a result must warrant a "higher marginal utility" than
future goods (p. 273).