Neither efficient nor animally spirited, but eventually adjusting: the stock market according to L.A. Hahn.
Bragues, George
1. INTRODUCTION
Until recently, the Efficient Markets Hypothesis (EMH) demonstrated
an impressive resiliency in the face of discordant events. It emerged
from the 1987 stock market crash only slightly bruised, though the Dow
Jones Industrial Average fell a record 22.6 percent in a single day when
the only news that might have possibly accounted for such a cataclysm
was a disagreement among industrialized nations about currency and
interest rate levels. Somehow, though it was left tottering, it managed
to survive the denouement of the late-1990's dot-com bubble. During
this bubble, the NASDAQ Composite Index nearly quadrupled in an eighteen
month period. Internet companies, such as eToys and TheGlobe.com, were
accorded multi-billion valuations despite generating limited revenues
and no profits. With the financial crisis of 2007-2009, however, it
seems that the EMH has finally succumbed. Here was a situation, after
all, in which a multitude of sophisticated analysts and investors,
operating in the world's leading financial institutions, grossly
overvalued the mortgage backed securities at the heart of the crisis and
systematically undervalued the risk in their portfolios, all the while
relying on models quantitatively constructed on the assumptions of the
EMH (Dowd and Hutchison, 2010).
Just as the crisis has revived Keynesian ideas in macroeconomics,
so it has led observers to revisit the sections of The General Theory of
Employment, Interest, and Money that address the behavior of securities
markets. There, Keynes (1964) compares the stock market to a giant
casino, describing investors as fundamentally driven by "animal
spirits," making decisions to buy and sell based on the estimated
direction of crowd psychology as opposed to the intrinsic value of
financial assets. Today, this Keynesian perspective is being taken up by
Behavioral Finance (BF), a school of thought that began percolating at
the margins of financial economics in the mid-1980's and which has
since dethroned the EMH of its monopoly status in the discipline to
become a formidable alternative. Based on the work of Amos Tversky and
Daniel Kahneman (1979, 1982), BF applies the findings of psychology to
explain price formation on securities markets. Opposing the EMH
presupposition of human beings as utility maximizing calculators, BF
sees the mind as inextricably swayed by emotions, feelings, social
influences, cognitive biases, and heuristics (Baker and Nofsinger, 2010;
Ackert and Deaves, 2010; Schleifer, 2004).
No doubt, BF offers a useful corrective to the EMH. Yet common
sense, in tandem with a bit of elementary logic, suggests that it cannot
fully account for market phenomena. If everyday observation amply
confirms that we are not cool logicians, it also reveals examples in
which people manage to overcome their biases and control their passions.
An investor is often enticed by greed to buy a penny stock touted on an
Internet newsgroup only to be brought back to reason by the realization
that the deal is too good to be true. What is more, markets surely do
regain their senses after bouts of extreme pessimism and optimism. And
while prices may not always be exactly right, it would be hard to deny
that, on occasion at least, certain securities, if not stocks in
general, are correctly valued. Yet if the human mind is the servant of
sub-rational forces, as BF seems to claim, these moments of rationality
are a puzzle. (1) If it is such a challenge to impartially reason, how
then do we manage to get things right from time to time?
This suggests we ought to explore the possibility of a middle way
between the EMH and BF. In search of this, we return to the writings of
Lucien Albert (L.A.) Hahn, a self-styled common-sense economist who
first gained notice with his Economic Theory of Bank Credit (1921). In a
career that traversed the worlds of academia and banking, Hahn attained
his greatest level of fame with The Economics of Illusion (1949), a
critique of Keynes, before laying out his own economic theory in Common
Sense Economics (1956). Since then, Hahn's work has been almost
forgotten; only two articles on Hahn come to sight in the scholarly
literature over the last twenty years (Selgin and Boudreaux, 1990;
Leeson, 1997).
Hahn's views on the stock market are set forth in the final
part of Common Sense Economics. Embarking from an Austrian understanding
of the business cycle and uncertainty, fleshed out with insights from
psychology, Hahn argues that stock prices result from a combination of
objective and subjective factors. On his account, the influence of mass
opinion and mental inertia over most people's psyches generates
sustained divergences from intrinsic values. Sooner or later, Hahn
observes, these distortions are corrected by the pull of the objective
facts in a process led by a few alert, independently minded investors.
In Hahn's analysis--which this paper finds has stood the test of
time--financial markets are neither perfectly efficient, nor animally
spirited, but eventually adjusting.
2. CURRENT THEORIES OF PRICE FORMATION IN FINANCIAL MARKETS
Anyone putting himself forward as a common sense economist must
have their views evaluated against not just the reigning academic
theories, but also the way in which the relevant practitioners
understand their own activity. Among stock market professionals, the
myriad of investing and trading strategies followed all belong to either
one, or a mix, of two approaches: fundamental analysis (FA) and
technical analysis (TA). The first is the more predominant and respected
of the two, though the second has gained adherents and stature over the
last two decades with the development of faster computers and increased
access to short-term trading opportunities. While most investors rely
exclusively on either one of the two methodologies, more than a few
combine them, typically by using FA to identify which stocks to purchase
or sell and then turning to TA in deciding when precisely to execute a
transaction.
FA insists that the best way to make investments decisions is to
analyze the financial data pertaining to a security. It states, too, the
necessity of accounting for industry and macroeconomic conditions that
impinge on a security's value, the marketability of the firm's
goods and services, as well as the quality of management. Thus,
practitioners of FA pore over a firm's balance sheet, its cash flow
statement, reported earnings and profit margins. They will evaluate how
a company's products stack up against the competition and whether
its strategy is adequately framed to boost profitability. They will
gauge the firm's profit potential and risk exposures at different
phases of the business cycle and ascertain whether it is part of an
industry that is in a speculative, growth, maturity, or decline phase.
All this is done with a view to determining the security's
intrinsic value. Some try to arrive at this number by projecting future
cash flows and then discounting these to their present value. Most FA
practitioners, though, apply a valuation metric of some kind, most
commonly the price to earnings (P/E) ratio, against a group of
comparable securities. (2)
Clearly, FA assumes that financial markets are only sporadically
efficient. According to the bible of FA, Graham and Dodd's Security
Analysis, "market prices, like a stopped clock, are a correct
representation of value twice in an investor's day" (Cottle,
Murray, and Block, 1988, p. 26). However much information is now readily
available to investors, FA proponents say, the fact remains that it is
interpreted differently and that most observers fail to capture the more
subtle and revealing bits of data within an evolving composite view. Not
to mention that markets are subject to the oscillations of fashion,
which bring different industry sectors in and out of favor alongside the
waves of fear and greed that engulf the generality of stocks.
Diametrically opposed to FA, TA ignores all the financial,
industry, and economic data (Edwards and Magee, 2001). Instead, TA
focuses on the historical movement of prices and transactional volumes.
This price and volume data is depicted on charts, which practitioners of
TA examine for the presence of trends. Their modus operandi is to ride a
trend until it shows signs of changing, at which point they reverse
their market positions to exploit the new price move. To gauge these
trends, TA refers to a set of patterns, such as the head and shoulders
and pennant formations, in judging whether prices are consolidating
within the prevailing trend or are at a critical turning point. Trend
lines are drawn connecting significant high and low points, moving
averages calculated, and indicators (i.e., stochastics, relative
strength index, on balance volume) derived through a mathematical
transformation of price and volume data into directional barometers.
When asked to explain why charts are more instructive than financial
statements, TA's supporters aver that all fundamental information
relevant to a security--whether it be financial, economic, strategic, or
political--is already reflected in the price. Charts, too, are said to
disclose the historical reality that markets often trend. Or, to put it
in statistical terms, financial asset returns exhibit autocorrelation.
Finally, TA claims that the psychological laws governing human nature
mean that chart patterns inevitably repeat themselves (Murphy, 1986, pp.
2-4).
While the seeds of the EMH can be found as early as Louis Bechelier
(2006) and Alfred Cowles (1933, 1944), the theory came into prominence
with Eugene Fama (1970) and Paul Samuelson (1965) in the 1960's and
1970's. From the fact that investors compete to find the best
investment prospects, the EMH deduces that this search must equilibrate with the elimination of all misvaluations. For if any such exist,
investors will immediately exploit the arbitrage opportunity thereby
presented until their actions move prices until market value and
intrinsic value are equal. So long as information is readily accessible
and the barriers to trading are minimal, this no-arbitrage equilibrium
will be reached quickly in response to any changes in market conditions.
Rather than being a goal to which market forces are drawn and only
rarely achieved, as the Austrian economics tradition holds, equilibrium
is seen by the EMH in neo-classical terms as the ordinary state of
affairs (Boettke, 2010). As such, EMH asserts that stock prices reflect
all available information. In the weak version of the EMH, this claim is
restricted to information about historical prices, thereby rejecting TA.
As for FA, the EMH questions this in its semi-strong version, according
to which all publicly information about a company's financial and
economic situation is also encompassed in the stock price. There is also
a strong version of the theory that states that all relevant information
whatsoever, including that possessed by insiders, is assimilated into
prices, though hardly any EMH advocate subscribes to it. So other than
conceding an edge to insiders, the EMH claims that investors earn
returns, not by buying undervalued securities and selling (or also
shorting) overvalued ones, but by assuming non-diversifiable risk in
their portfolios (Malkiel, pp. 180-215).
Despite its portrayal of investors as emotional and biased, BF
admits this description does not apply to every single investor. A few
are rational. Having made this exception, BF gives itself a means of
solving the aforementioned puzzle of how to explain the periodic
episodes of reasonable valuations when passion and bad judgment is so
prevalent. Perhaps the elite corps of rational investors cancel the
effects of their irrational brethren by exploiting the latter's
mistakes? Indeed, the EMH invokes such arbitrage trading to deal with
the glaring fact that not everyone lives up to its assumption of utility
maximizing behavior. BF, however, declines this tack, arguing instead
that the rational face constraints on arbitrage. Once prices move away
from correct levels, no guarantee exists that the deviation will not
further widen and persist under the sway of irrational traders. Value
arbitrageurs thus expose themselves to the danger of having to carry a
losing position over a long period during which the intrinsic value of
the security undergoes an adverse change or paper losses grow to the
point of inducing financial stress. Recognizing this, rational investors
will either resist the urge to trade against the irrational, or perhaps
even try to join them for as long as they are in control of the price
movement, thereby reinforcing the divergence from correct values. As
Keynes originally put this BF claim: "Investment based on genuine
long-term expectation is so difficult to-day as to be scarcely
practicable. He who attempts it must surely lead much more laborious
days and run greater risks than he who tries guess better than the crowd
how the crowd will behave" (Keynes, 1964, p. 157).
Where BF goes beyond Keynes is in specifying the types of
individual biases that combine to mislead the crowd. To cite the more
notable findings, BF scholars conclude that investors, particularly
male, overestimate their investment abilities (the overconfidence bias);
they lag in updating their beliefs to new evidence (the conservatism
bias); filter information that corroborates their existing beliefs (the
confirmatory bias); surmise that runs within a series of events must
soon reverse (gambler's fallacy); deduce that a repeated occurrence
of events portends a larger trend (clustering illusion); and overly rely
on easily accessible memories or ideas in rendering probability
judgments (the availability bias). So too, BF observes that investors
are more sensitive to losses than to gains of the same amount of money,
overweight small probabilities and underweight large ones, and change
their decisions about the same probability scenarios when these are
framed differently (Barberis and Thaler, 2002; Shefrin, 2000).
3. HAHN'S CRITIQUE OF MARKET EFFICIENCY
L.A. Hahn wades into the debate about financial markets because it
illuminates the relationship between expectations and facts in economic
life--that is, the extent to which human subjectivity affects the
decisions that people make relative to the necessities imposed on
individual choices by the objective realm. Entranced by the prospect of
replicating the success of physics in the human realm, the dominant
streams of economics over the last two centuries--whether classical or
neo-classical--have tended to emphasize the determinative role of
objective variables in accounting for economic phenomena. The
mathematical techniques employed by orthodox economists, with all their
equations depicting a given state of affairs as a function of various
conditions, presuppose the priority of the objective over the
subjective. But this epistemological preference, Hahn points out, falls
afoul of the fact that businesspersons do not simply react to changes in
the economic data taking place now, but must form some estimate of what
shifts might occur in the future. This is because of the interval
existing between the initial decision to deploy resources in the
production of a good or service and the time it is ready for sale.
Between these two points, input costs might change, as may consumer
tastes and the competitive environment, either of which can
significantly affect the profitability of one's business projects.
With businesspersons thus compelled to become forecasters, as the
Austrian economists recognize (Mises, 1963, pp. 105-106), the subjective
factor assumes an influential role, precisely insofar as the future is
ultimately incomprehensible. From this it follows that the future cannot
determine anything in the present and that the mind is liberated to
conceive numerous scenarios in line with its psychological propensities.
That such expectations constitute the basic stuff of financial
markets is obvious from even the most cursory observation of trading
activity. When a company reports its earnings or the government releases
the latest employment numbers, it is not so much what the data itself
reveals that moves markets, but more so how the newly divulged
information compares to expectations. Record profits may be announced
and the unemployment rate fall dramatically, but stock prices may still
drop if the good news does not accord with forecasts. In evaluating the
efficiency of markets, the question thus becomes: do the expectations
have a tendency to be on the mark? Prediction errors are inevitable, of
course, but if these turn out to be normally distributed around realized
levels then the argument for market rationality is greatly strengthened.
It is precisely the contention of the EMH that the market's
forecasting mistakes are normally distributed. As such, the subjective
element in expectations is rendered mathematically tractable by the
application of statistical techniques. The result is that expectations
are objectified, so to speak, by virtue of being construed as a
mechanism reflecting the real probabilities of events. But if
expectations err universally and systematically, then human subjectivity
cannot be viewed simply as a mirror to the objective world, and must
instead take on the character of a truly independent cause of market
phenomena. This is exactly Hahn's point.
He establishes it, first, by presenting a straightforward model of
stock prices based on investor behavior. Noting that most individuals
who buy shares do so with the aim of earning dividends in the future,
Hahn infers the correct value of a stock as equal to the present value
of that projected income. Since people value a dollar more today than a
dollar to be had in the future, the present value of estimated dividends
must be a discounted at a rate corresponding to the passage of time
until their receipt. What Hahn thus arrives at is a discounted cash flow
(DCF) model of stock prices:
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
Where S is the stock price, D is the dividend amount, n is the
number of time periods over which dividends are being paid, while t
refers to the nth time period, and r to the discount rate. Assuming the
dividends are secure, this rate must equal the yield on long-term bonds,
for otherwise investors would have an incentive to switch between bonds
and stocks to whichever offered the higher return. Hahn does not spell
out what happens if the dividend payments are not as certain as the
bonds, but the obvious consequence is that the discount rate on the
stock will then contain a risk premium.
One might counter that investors actually focus on earnings, rather
than dividends, and that they often pin their hopes on selling at a
higher price than where they bought. Even so, as Hahn observes,
investors cannot really care about earnings per se, since they do not
necessarily receive them as income, but only insofar as these signal the
firm's capacity to eventually issue dividends. Investors intent on
capital gains must also concern themselves with dividends inasmuch as
the stock price can only rise if the prospect of their payment and
growth increase, as proxied by earnings (Hahn, 1956, p. 197). Given that
financial markets are not populated solely by short-term traders, the
latter will eventually have to deal with someone having a longer-term
horizon. Such an investor will not purchase shares from the short-term
trader, and help close the latter's position at a profit, unless
the outlook for dividends justifies the price (Hahn, 1956, p. 208).
Having put forward a DCF model, Hahn proceeded to test its
predictions of intrinsic value against market prices. By proceeding in
this fashion, Hahn anticipates the centerpiece of Robert Shiller's
(2000, pp. 184-190) brief against market efficiency. But unlike Shiller,
a leading figure in the BF school, Hahn did not use the model to
generate point estimates of the present value of future dividends,
probably because of the difficulty of forecasting those numbers the
further one goes out into the future. Another factor, arguably, is
Hahn's (1956) distrust of the mathematical methods that have come
to dominate economics: "the mathematical language of modern
economics has led many an economist to describe not so much what
actually happens but what possibly could happen ... any resemblance of
these descriptions and explanations to reality seems to me purely
accidental" (p. xi). Consequently, Hahn only uses the model as a
tool to interpret price movements.
The model thus tells us to expect stock prices to vary directly
with dividends and to move inversely with bond yields. During the
1929-April 1956 period that Hahn investigated, the corporate bond yields
that he used to represent the discount rate changed little from 1937
forward. Before then, stock prices accorded with changes in the bond
yield, with equities declining between 1929 and 1932 as corporate bond
yields rose, and equities increasing from 1933 to 1937 as yields fell.
Afterwards, stock prices movements can only be accounted for on the
basis of dividends. Here is how Hahn broke down the relationships amid
the bull and bear markets that took place:
Three of the sub-periods, covering 12 of the 26M years in
Hahn's data set (almost half), show the stock market behaving
irrationally. Once again foreshadowing Shiller's analysis, Hahn
goes further in discerning that, even when the two moved in the same
direction, prices were noticeably more volatile than dividends. An
objection might be raised here that this lack of correspondence exists
because investors follow earnings instead of dividends. Yet, as Hahn
notes, earnings and dividends generally move in tandem, just as one
would expect from the former serving as a proxy for the latter.
Earnings, indeed, are more volatile, since corporate boards prefer to
keep dividend payouts steady knowing that profitability is subject to
gyration from one year to the next. Stock prices, as a result, track
earnings more closely.
Before we can affirm Hahn's conclusion that markets are
inefficient, we cannot forget that more than fifty years of additional
data has become available since he wrote. Let us see, then, how his
analysis has stood the test of time using his own interpretive method.
To this end, we employ the Standard and Poor's Composite Index (S&P 500) as our barometer of stock market performance, as well as
the dividends and earnings per share of its constituent firms. We follow
Hahn in adopting corporate bond yields as our proxy for the discount
rate, and, more specifically, those rated Aaa by Moody's. Below are
six charts depicting the S&P 500 index, dividends, earnings, and
corporate bond yields over the 1956-1968, 1968-1982, and 1982-2010 time
frames. This breakdown separates three broad trends that are discernible
between 1956-2010. The 1956-1968 interval saw the continuation of the
post-World War II bull market. From 1968 to 1982, the combination of
inflation and slower economic growth led to a sideways range in stock
prices. Between 1982 and 2010, the stock market experienced a
historically unprecedented bull phase from which it has been correcting
since 2000.
[FIGURE 2 OMITTED]
In Figure 2, it can be seen that dividends and stock prices broadly
tracked each other, though the latter exhibited more volatility, just as
it did in the 1929-1956 time frame that Hahn examined. This greater
volatility seems due to the fact that investors were swayed by the
vicissitudes of earnings.
[FIGURE 3 OMITTED]
At odds with the market's ascent is the steady rise in nominal
yields from 1956-1968 depicted in Figure 3. It is not out of the
question, of course, that the market's upward movement was
justified by the increase in dividends outweighing the higher discount
rates. Still, the climb in nominal rates was both significant--doubling
during the period--and persistent.
[FIGURE 4 OMITTED]
[FIGURE 5 OMITTED]
Beginning in 1968, stock prices (Figure 4) finally succumbed to the
increase in bond yields, as the longer term trend flattened with
shorter-term moves exhibiting a zig-zag pattern. As Figure 5 shows, the
ascent in yields continued into the early 1980s, helping account for the
generally lackluster performance of stocks that characterized the
period. Dividends trended higher during this period, even as the market
was essentially flat, though the ascent was sharpest after 1975 as
stocks began to show signs of re-establishing the secular uptrend. Once
again, stock prices were more volatile than dividends, with earnings
correlating more strongly with fluctuations in the S&P 500.
[FIGURE 6 OMITTED]
[FIGURE 7 OMITTED]
With figures 6 and 7 we see that the bull market from
1982-2000--interrupted by only three brief downturns in 1987, 1990, and
1998--was directionally in accord with both rising dividends and falling
nominal rates. Yet if the trend was justified, the slope of the price
move was much steeper than that of dividends, especially from the early
1990s to the 2000 high when the fall in corporate bond yields had
stabilized. Partly accounting for this, it is true, was the increasing
prevalence during the 1980s and 1990s of firms using available cash to
buy back shares in lieu of raising dividends. Even so, like dividends,
these share repurchases are generally funded out of earnings, and the
latter also rose at a slower pace relative to stock prices. Correcting
for these divergences, stock prices fell sharply from the 2000 high even
as dividends only gently declined. In 2007, the S&P index merely
approached its 2000 peak, even as dividends were establishing all-time
highs.
Imitating Hahn's method, the table below offers a closer look
of the 1956-2010 period, categorized by bull and bear markets. A bear
market is defined as occurring upon a minimum fall of 20 percent in the
daily closing price of the nominal S&P 500 index from an earlier
peak. A bull market takes place upon a minimum 20 percent rise in that
index from a low point. Yields are categorized as flat if there was a 50
basis point change or less during the bull or bear market in question.
Dividends, in turn, are designated as flat whenever a nominal rise was
canceled by inflation during the relevant period as measured by changes
in the US consumer price index.
Compared to Hahn's 1929-1956 analysis, fewer of the
subperiods--7 of the 21 intervals representing just under 9 of the 55
total years--exhibit stock price movements in violation of the DCF
model. In this instance as well, the inclusion of corporate yields
generated 4 inconclusive findings, though these only constituted
approximately 9 % years of the data set. Here, it should be kept in mind
that during the longest of the inconclusive periods, Oct. 1974-Nov.
1980, dividends only slightly rose after factoring in inflation, while
bond yields shot up. Dividends merely increased 1.9 percent in real
terms over that entire 6 year interval as compared to the 5.9 percent
equivalent figure that would have been expected had the average monthly
growth rate of dividends from 1956-2010 prevailed. More importantly, the
table above only takes the direction of the variables into account, not
their respective fluctuations. To repeat, stock prices were
significantly more volatile than the DCF model inputs, dividends in
particular, throughout the entire 1956-2010 time frame. And, again, the
upward slope in stock prices was noticeably more pronounced than that of
dividends (or even earnings) in 1990-2000. On balance, therefore,
Hahn's conclusion of market inefficiency on the basis of the
1929-1956 experience is borne out by the subsequent data.
4. THE INTERPLAY OF SUBJECTIVE AND OBJECTIVE FORCES
At the same time, it cannot be ignored that the market sometimes
gets it right and that, even when it does stray from intrinsic value, it
ultimately finds its way back. Hahn points out that the relationship
between dividends and stocks becomes much closer once the oscillations
created by bull and bear markets are diminished by smoothing prices
through the calculation of a moving average. Figure 9 checks to see
whether this is also the case for the 1956-2010 period using a 60 month
moving average of the S&P 500 index.
[FIGURE 9 OMITTED]
The correlation is indeed tighter, except that the price average
fails to track the dividend increases from 2003 to 2009. These reflect
legislation passed by the Bush Administration in 2003 that lowered the
taxation of dividends. While this change was subsequently extended to
2010, it was then set to expire in 2011 unless the U.S. government chose
to renew the extension, which it subsequently did for another two years.
In view of the uncertainty that surrounded the duration of this policy,
the markets likely factored in the possibility of a return to the
previous tax treatment of dividends. "It must be borne in
mind," as Hahn (1956) rightly says, "that if any future change
is to lead to changes in the valuation of a share--or of all shares--it
must be expected to be permanent" (p. 200).
Given how the DCF model looks against a long-term moving average of
stock prices, Hahn concludes that objective reality ultimately acts as a
magnet drawing markets back from the errors of its shorter and
medium-term ways that continually recur because of the force of human
subjectivity. Usually, Hahn posits, a complete market cycle proceeds as
follows: bull markets emerge out of the depths of a bear market when
dividend yields are high as a result of a pervasive gloom leading
investors to expect further declines in earnings and dividends. That no
bargain hunters enter the marketplace to take advantage of the high
dividend yields, and thereby raise prices, only reinforces the negative
sentiment. This is what Hahn calls the exaggeration phase of the bear
market. The bull market commences as an adjustment phase of this
overextended move as indications slowly materialize that the economy is
on the mend and dividends are set to rise.
Then, the market enters a normal phase in which the investing
public is neither exuberant nor disconsolate about the future. Share
prices now merely obey the upward trajectory of dividends. But then
another exaggeration stage ensues in which the very fact that dividends
and earnings have been rising generates expectations that these will
continue to rise. Accordingly, stock prices move ahead of dividends. As
prices do not meet resistance from sellers, and short sellers shy away
from exploiting the excessive valuations signaled by the low dividend
yields, investors gain reassurance. Finally, a few alert investors
notice that the market's exalted levels are unsustainable. These
sell and prices start to reverse. As the general optimism fades, the
selling accelerates and we enter another adjustment phase that launches
a bear market. This, too, subsequently goes into a normal stage during
which prices decline in lockstep with dividends. With time, an
exaggeration phase to the downside transpires and the cycle starts
again. Throughout this entire sequence, Hahn adds, a mental inertia
operates that renders investors incapable of changing their outlook
until the evidence to the contrary becomes dramatically obvious. The
exaggeration phases, especially, become resilient to incongruous news
items as a result, helping explain how prices can diverge from intrinsic
value for extended periods. A graphic representation of this cycle is
given in Figure 10.
[FIGURE 10 OMITTED]
Embedded in this account of stock market cycles are a number of
psychological claims that show Hahn foreshadowing elements of BF. By
asserting that investors rely on recent trends in forming their
expectations, and thus project the recent past onto the future, Hahn is
alluding to what cognitive psychologists nowadays refer to as the
recency effect, which itself is a variation of the availability bias so
much talked about in the BF literature. The mental inertia, too, that
Hahn invokes is equivalent to the conservatism bias. When he proceeds to
outline the implications of his market theory to investing strategy, he
cites a third psychological trait, namely the individual's
subjection to mass opinion. "It engulfs not only those who easily
succumb to foreign influences but even those with normally detached
views and sober judgment. An almost superhuman effort is needed to evade
the influence of mass opinion" (ibid, p. 212). What this groupthink does, clearly, is to magnify the predominant trend that the Zeitgeist of
the period happens to be buttressing. Continuing in this Tocquevillean
vein, Hahn even suggests that the democratization of the stock market
enhances this dynamic, insofar as the widespread dissemination of prices
enables investors to quickly assess what the majority is thinking
(Tocqueville, 1969, pp. 254-259). Were Hahn alive to see the Internet,
and all the websites offering free quotes and news, he would surely have
concluded that it has augmented the mental dominance of the crowd.
Why, fundamentally, do these subjective factors, these human
thought processes, assume the role that they do in so often mispricing
securities? Why is it, in other words, that investors are incapable of
thinking about the markets in ways that avoid systematic errors? The
very thing, it turns out, that opens up the economic realm to the play
of subjective forces is that which conduces to market inefficiency: we
cannot know the future. The freedom from present exigencies that this
gives to act on the basis of our idiosyncratic predictions also dictates
our getting those wrong often. As Hahn correctly notes, if the future
could be known, then securities prices would immediately reflect that
information--a point that would later be stressed by EMH advocates. The
future would then effectively become the present and cease to exist as a
distinct temporal category. At best, according to Hahn, we can make
probability judgments about the near future. As to the distant future,
"it lies, shrouded in a mist, beyond the horizon of time"
(ibid, p. 203). Market practitioners acknowledge this, he insinuates, by
restricting the discounting of future developments to twelve
months--which surely does occur, if the predominance of one year
earnings estimates among stock analysts over longer-term forecasts is
any indication.
Even to the extent that an investor is able to make probability
judgments, these are not of the kind described as rationally utility
maximizing in the standard textbook treatments of finance. To be sure,
Hahn concedes that a stock price can, in theory at least, be viewed as
the summed value of various scenarios for the firm, each weighted by its
probability. For example, if there is a 30 percent that company PQR will, over the next year, report earnings that correspond to a share
price of $50, and a 70 percent chance its eventual income will be such
as to correlate with a $40 per share figure, then PQR stock will trade
at $43 (0.3 x $50 + 0.7 x $40). In reality, the number of scenarios is
greater than two and more complicated to delineate, so that the stock
price ends up at the point where the chances of it going up or down seem
to be equal, rather than whatever is dictated by the calculation of some
complex equation.
More critically, however, the probabilities imputed are not
mathematical in plotting the frequency of similar events in the past. In
the world of investing, there is no equivalent of a billion throws of a
die to consider, no large samples of essentially identical phenomena. As
Hahn observes, a market event taking place in one cycle is always
different, in some decisive respect, from an analogous occurrence in
another cycle. An analyst might note, for example, that the stock market
has experienced higher returns under Democratic presidents, as opposed
to Republican ones, but one cannot simply infer from this that the
pattern will recur. Not only were previous presidents of the same party
often distinctive in their ideological mindsets and policy approaches, a
multitude of other factors were driving stock prices--whose operation,
for all we know, may subsequently combine to overwhelm the relevance of
whether the White House is being occupied by a Democrat or a Republican.
Besides the lack of homogeneity in the slices of history, the brute fact
remains that too few of them are going to repeat themselves over an
investor's lifetime to enable him or her to depend upon the law of
large numbers.
Consequently, though the playing of chances that investing entails
means it can be likened to gambling at a craps table, no one can proceed
in the buying and selling of securities the way a casino does in
operating its games--that is, by continually playing across numerous
locations according to the same rules on the expectation that, over
time, the expected frequencies will assert themselves. Since his or her
number of plays is much shorter than that of a casino, an
investor's risk is significantly higher--the variance of their
potential outcomes is far greater--than what a historical sense of the
probabilities might suggest. This offers an explanation as to why the
risk models that Wall Street employed so spectacularly failed in the
recent financial crisis. Instead of reflecting the mistaken
specification of a normal distribution (Dowd and Hutchinson, 2010;
Triana, 2009; Mandelbrot and Hudson, 2006), or the input of insufficient
historical data, the problem lied in thinking that numerical
probabilities could even be assigned at all.
Here is how Hahn (1956) aptly puts it:
The case is comparable not to that of the bank in Monte Carlo,
which can and does rely on red and black turning up equally often
in the long run, but rather to that of the individual player, who
cannot know whether the ball will stop on red or on black. He has
to take his chance. He may be playing red ten times in succession,
although black may win ten times (pp. 204-205). (3)
Indeed, Hahn goes so far as to invoke David Hume's (1978, pp.
127-130) contention that probability assessments are subjective mental
acts. One simply feels inclined in favor of one outcome rather than
another, with the level of intensity felt varying roughly with the
preponderance of that outcome relative to other scenarios in one's
previous experience.
That brings us to the objective factors moving stock prices, by
which Hahn means all market relevant phenomena operating externally to
investor minds compelling their rational faculties towards similar
evaluations. Despite the thoroughgoing value subjectivism of Austrian
economics, Hahn nevertheless echoes that tradition in the objectivist
side of his theory. As we have seen, he argues both that stock prices
exhibit cyclical behavior and that, as per the DCF model, those prices
are a function of expected dividends and prevailing interest rates. Now
since dividends come out of profits, and these in turn fluctuate with
the vicissitudes of the economy, it follows that the generality of
stocks, though their long-term trajectory will follow secular trends,
are nevertheless affected by the business cycles that have been a
feature of capitalist economies since the 19th century. The upshot is
that the question of what objectively drives the stock market is
necessarily connected to the riddle of business cycles.
For Hahn, the puzzle here is figuring out why the demand for goods
and services sometimes runs below production and other times above it.
It is not that he thinks Say's law is wrong. When the business
cycle is viewed as a whole, demand and supply tend to balance. It is
just that Say's law does not prevail at all times. Finding
underconsumption (Keynesian) and overconsumption accounts of the
business cycle wanting, Hahn is brought to Knut Wicksell's (1936)
natural interest rate theory, which grounds the Austrian understanding
of business cycles. According to Wicksell, the free play of supply and
demand forces in the credit market work to establish the natural rate of
interest or, if you will, the market rate. However, the central bank,
with the commercial banks assisting, can exercise their monopoly power
over currency issuance to drive interest rates away from the natural or
market rate. Where the rate is higher than the market, fewer loans are
sought to finance consumption and investment expenditures, thus lowering
demand for goods and services. Prices fall and the economic activity
declines. Where the rate is lower than the market, more loans are sought
to finance consumption and investment, thus raising the demand for goods
and services. Prices increase and economic activity rises. Accordingly,
business cycles are the result of central bank policies.
It is very important to note, however, that Hahn supplements this
essentially Austrian account with a psychological theory influenced by
A.C. Pigou's (1929) Industrial Fluctuations. Hahn does so to
address an objection that would later be made by the rational
expectations school, namely that the central bank cannot take the
economy up and down, unless people err by not accounting for its
actions. Who would invest in a new capital project well into an upswing,
if they can see that the Federal Reserve is eventually going to raise
interest rates to stop the economy from overheating? Who is going to shy
away from a big investment amidst a slump if the central bank is
committed to a very loose monetary policy? In Hahn's view, such
mistakes can only be explained by a pro-cyclical psychological dynamic
in which people are carried by excitement in prosperous times and sunk
by pessimism in recessionary periods. His analysis of the subjective
forces operating in financial markets is meant to corroborate this
point.
Beyond influencing the level of profits, and hence dividends, that
stock prices incorporate, the central bank's activities obviously
impinge on the discount rate applied by investors to shares. Everything
else remaining equal, an easing of monetary conditions, by lowering the
discount rate, will raise stock prices and vice-versa. Hahn cites that
easing which takes place during a recession to explain how bear markets
manage to end even as everyone is pessimistic about the economy's
ability to generate profits and dividends. Once these begin to revive,
the bull market gains momentum, especially as the central banks keeps
interest rates from immediately jumping to ensure economic recovery. As
this bull phase matures, rates do begin to rise, with the central bank
less willing to accommodate increased credit demand, but the ascent in
profits and dividends outweighs the higher discount rate. The bull
market ends as interest rates continue to push higher, with the ensuing
bear market strengthening in the wake of falling profits and dividends.
All this, it must be said, is not much different from the story often
told in Wall Street and the City. But, as Hahn (1956) says, "the
world does not consist of economists who know and business men who
err" (p. 166).
5. CONCLUDING REMARKS
Using a DCF model of stock prices, Hahn maintains that the stock
market is inefficient, doing so on the basis of 1929-1956 data. Updating
his mode of analysis to the end of 2010, we substantiate his conclusion
that dividends are only loosely correlated with stock prices, even after
taking discount rates into account. In place of an efficient markets
model, Hahn describes the stock market as subject to recurring cycles in
which subjective and objective factors combine to set prices. Though the
subjective forces of psychology, consisting of mental inertia and
dependence on mass opinion, regularly take prices either above, or
below, levels dictated by the objective facts, the latter do act as a
magnet checking the movements of the former. The objective factors,
insofar as these reflect business cycles, are decisively influenced by
central bank practices of maintaining interest rates at non-market
rates.
By arguing that financial markets are inefficient, Hahn ends up on
the side of investment practitioners who subscribe to either FA or TA as
well as the academic school, BF, most reflective of the conventional
wisdom in the financial community. His more precise stance, though, with
respect to these three approaches comes to sight in the personal
investing counsel that he draws from his theory of the stock market.
While agreeing with BF that psychological variables create divergences
between stock prices and rational prices, and while sympathizing with FA
that market values do not always equal intrinsic values, Hahn's
proposed strategy is surprisingly aligned with TA. Granted, Hahn does
not refer to trend lines, moving average crossovers, head and shoulder
formations, or any of the other constructs of TA. In the one instance he
does allude to TA, he is dismissive. This happens when he briefly
discusses the Dow theory, a century old concept that seeks to identify
the market's current trend by comparing movements in the Dow Jones
Industrial Average to those of the Dow Transportation Average (Rhea,
1932). Hahn contends the Dow theory has proved to be of limited use and
that its value is negligible in any case because it is widely known.
That said, Hahn figures that the optimal strategy is to buy shares
at the intersection of the exaggeration phase of the bear market and the
adjustment phase of the incoming bull market. Here, the wise investor
must go against mass opinion, which is overwhelmingly pessimistic at
this stage when the subjective forces of psychology are in control. From
here, though, one must become willing to travel with mass opinion. For
the wise investor is then supposed to hold on to their shares as the
subjective element is brought back to objective reality. Furthermore, he
or she is to maintain their position afterwards when the two diverge
again as the bull market reaches its most enthusiastic phase. This is,
of course, the moment in which one must again oppose mass opinion. Thus,
the wise investor sells (or short sells), and stays out (or remains
short) throughout the normal stage of the bear market when the objective
and subjective orders are reunited once again, only re-entering (and
covering) when these two diverge at the exaggeration phase of the bear
market. "Thus it is as wrong always to oppose the prevailing
tendency as it is always to follow it. In a nutshell, the right rule is:
first against the tendency, then with it, and finally against it"
(Hahn 1956, p. 214). Heeding this advice, one will spend quite a bit of
time following the trend, precisely as TA counsels. Even Hahn speaks of
the change in trend occurring over a "moment" (ibid.). Yet it
must be conceded that Hahn does not think such changes can be
scientifically predicted. To this extent, and only to this extent, is
Hahn in accord with EMH.
REFERENCES
Ackert, Lucy F., and Richard Deaves. 2010. Behavioral Finance:
Psychology, Decision-Making, and Markets. Mason, Ohio: South-Western,
Cengage Learning.
Bachelier, Louis. 2006. Louis Bachelier's Theory of
Speculation. Mark Davis and Alison Etheridge, trans. Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
Baker, H. Kent and John R. Nofsinger, eds. 2010. Behavioral
Finance: Investors, Corporations, and Markets. Hoboken, N.J.: John Wiley
and Sons.
Barberis, Nicholas, and Richard Thaler. 2002. "A Survey of
Behavioral Finance," National Bureau of Economic Research Working
Paper. Available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=327880.
Bloomfield, Robert. 2010. "Traditional versus Behavioral
Finance" in H. Kent Baker and John R. Nofsinger, eds, Behavioral
Finance: Investors, Corporations, and Markets. Hoboken, N.J.: John Wiley
and Sons.
Boettke, Peter J. 2010. "What Happened to Efficient
Markets?" The Independent Review, 14, no. 3: 363-375.
Cottle, Sidney, Roger Murray, and Frank Block. 1988. Graham and
Dodd's Security Analysis. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Cowles, Alfred. 1933. "Can Stock Market Forecasters
Forecast?" Econo metrica 1: 309-324.
--. 1944. "Stock Market Forecasting," Econometrica 12,
no. 3: 206-214.
Dowd, Kevin & Hutchinson, Martin. 2010. Alchemists of Loss. New
York: John Wiley and Sons.
Fama, Eugene. 1970. "Efficient Capital Markets: A Review of
Theory and Empirical Work," Journal of Finance 25: 383-417.
Fernandez, Pablo. 2001. "Valuation Using Multiples: How Do
Analysts Reach Their Conclusions," IESE Business School Working
Paper. Available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=274972.
Keynes, John Maynard. 1964. The General Theory of Employment,
Interest, and Money. San Diego: Harcourt.
Hahn, Lucien Albert. 1921. Economic Theory of Bank Credit.
Publisher unknown.
--. 1949. The Economics of Illusion. New York: New York Institute
of Finance.
--. 1956. Common Sense Economics. New York: Abelard-Schuman Ltd.
Hume, David. 1978. A Treatise of Human Nature, 2nd ed. Peter
Nidditch, ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kahneman, Daniel, and Amos Tversky. 1979. "Prospect Theory: An
Analysis of Decisions under Risk," Econometrica 47: 313-327
Kahneman, Daniel, Paul Slovic, and Amos Tversky. 1982. Judgment
under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases. New York: Cambridge University
Press.
Leeson, Robert. 1997. "Influence (or the Lack of It) in the
Economics Profession: The Case of Lucien Albert Hahn," History of
Political Economy 29, no. 4: 635-638.
Malkiel, Burton. 2007. A Random Walk down Wall Street. New York:
W.W. Norton.
Mandelbrot, Benoit, and Richard L. Hudson. 2006. The Misbehavior of
Markets: A Fractal View of Financial Turbulence. New York: Basic Books.
Mises, Ludwig von. 1963. Human Action: A Treatise on Economics. San
Francisco: Fox and Wilkes.
Murphy, John. 1986. Technical Analysis of the Futures Markets. New
York: New York Institute of Finance.
Pigou, Arthur C. 1929. Industrial Fluctuations, 2nd ed. New York:
A.M. Kelley.
Samuelson, Paul. 1965. "Proof that Properly Anticipated Prices
Fluctuate Randomly," Industrial Management Review 6: 41-49.
Schleifer, Andrei. 2004. Inefficient Markets: An Introduction to
Behavioral Finance. New York: Oxford University Press.
Selgin, George A., and Donald J. Boudreaux. 1990. "L. Albert
Hahn: A Precursor of Keynesianism and the Monetarist Counterrevolution," History of Political Economy 22, no. 2: 261-279
Shefrin, Hersh. 2000. Beyond Greed and Fear. Boston: Harvard
Business School Press.
Shiller, Robert J. 2000. Irrational Exuberance. New York: Broadway
Books.
--. 2010. Online Data. Available at
http://www.econ.yale.edu/~shiller/ data.htm.
St. Louis Fed. 2010. Economic Data. Available at
http://research.stlouisfed. org/fred2/series/AAA?cid=119.
Stowe, John D., Thomas R. Robinson, Gerald E. Pinto, and Dennis W.
McLeavey. 2007. Equity Asset Valuation. New York: John Wiley and Sons.
Triana, Paolo. 2009. Lecturing Birds on Flying: Can Mathematical
Theories Destroy the Financial Markets? New York: John Wiley and Sons.
Tocqueville, Alexis de. 1969. Democracy in America. George
Lawrence, trans. Garden City, New York: Anchor Books.
Wicksell, Knut. 1936. Interest and Prices: A Study of the Causes
Regulating the Value of Money. London: Macmillan and Co.
(1) Describing BF's position as one in which the human mind is
said to be, "the servant of sub-rational forces" is no
exaggeration. BF proponents often refer to the impact of cognitive
biases as "systematic" rather than episodic or occasional (for
example, see Barberis and Thaler, 2002, p. 11). The sheer number of
biases and empirical deviations from the EMH put forward by BF advocates
also suggest they view the influence of the irrational as being
pervasive. BF advocates, too, resist the EMH description of the evidence
mustered against market rationality as a collection of mere anomalies.
Thus, Richard Thaler, a leading spokesman for BF, hopes for a future in
which the discipline of finance will no longer be divided between the
supporters and detractors of rational choice theory. "In their
Enlightenment," he says, "economists will routinely
incorporate as much "behaviour" into their models as they
observe in the real world."(Thaler, cited by Bloomfield, 2010, p.
36). In other words, the irrational side of human nature will be
acknowledged as a universal cause of human conduct.
(2) Pablo Fernandez (2001, pp. 2-3) surveyed equity analysts at
Morgan Stanley Dean Witter and found that more than 50 percent used the
P/E ratio, well above the slightly more than 30 percent applying the
EV/EBITDA (Enterprise Value divided by Earnings before Interest, Taxes,
Depreciation, and Amortization) metric. For a comprehensive treatment of
share valuation can be found in Stowe, Robinson, Pinto and McLeavey
(2007).
(3) What Hahn basically describes here is the distinction that
Ludwig von Mises (1963, pp. 107-115) drew between class and case
probability. Class probability refers to situations in which all the
factors relevant to the production of numerous events sharing a set of
characteristics are known. The probability that this set, or class, will
occur can be mathematically calculated. Falling under this category are
the chances of a seven arising from the throw of two dice. Case
probability, by contrast, deals with circumstances in which some, but
not all, of the causal variables are known and the event in question
cannot be classified within a class. The event is unique and its
probability is, therefore, not subject to a mathematical determination.
Hahn, like Mises, places the game of investing under the heading of case
probability.
George Bragues (gbragues@uoguelph.ca) is Assistant Vice-Provost and
head of the business program at the University of Guelph-Humber,
Toronto, Ontario.
Table 1. Stock Prices vs. Dividends, 1929-April 1956
Time Period Dividends Corporate Stock Markets
Yields Prices vs. Model
1929-1932 Down Up Down Consistent
1933-1937 Up Down Up Consistent
Up Flat Down Not Consistent
1942-1946 Flat Flat Up Not Consistent
1946-1949 Up Flat Down Not Consistent
1949-1952 Up Flat Up Consistent
Jan 1953-Sep 1953 Down Flat Down Consistent
1953-Apr 1956 Up Flat Up Consistent
Source: (Hahn, 1956, pp. 193-195)
Table 8. Stock Prices vs. Dividends and Yields, 1956-2010
Time Period Dividends Corporate Stock Markets
Yields Prices vs. Model
Jan 1956-Jul 1957 Flat Up Up Inconsistent
Jul 1957-Oct 1957 Up Flat Down Inconsistent
Oct 1957-Dec 1961 Up Flat Up Consistent
Dec 1961-Jun 1962 Up Flat Down Inconsistent
Jun 1962-Feb 1966 Up Flat Up Consistent
Feb 1966-Oct 1966 Up Up Down Not Conclusive
Oct 1966-Nov 1968 Flat Up Up Inconsistent
Nov 1968-May 1970 Flat Up Down Consistent
May 1970-Jan 1973 Down Down Up Not Conclusive
Jan 1973-Oct 1974 Flat Up Down Consistent
Oct 1974-Nov 1980 Up Up Up Not Conclusive
Nov 1980-Aug 1982 Flat Up Down Consistent
Aug 1982-Aug 1987 Up Down Up Consistent
Aug 1987-Dec 1987 Up Up Down Not Conclusive
Aug 1987-Mar 2000 Up Down Up Consistent
Mar 2000-Sep 2001 Down Down Down Not Conclusive
Sep 2001-Jan 2002 Up Flat Up Consistent
Jan 2002-Oct 2002 Flat Flat Down Inconsistent
Oct 2002-Oct 2007 Up Down Up Consistent
Oct 2007-Mar 2009 Flat Flat Down Inconsistent
Mar 2009-Dec 2010 Down Flat Up Inconsistent