Transitivity and the money pump.
Block, Walter E. ; Barnett, William, II
I. INTRODUCTION
The present paper is devoted to an examination of transitivity.
In section II we discuss the case for this concept, including the
"money pump," a reductio ad absurdum of the critique of
transitivity. Section III is devoted to a critique of this money pump.
We conclude in Section IV.
II. TRANSITIVITY
Transitivity of strict preference (1) may be denoted by equation 1:
(1) A > B; B > C; therefore, A > C.
If A represents 70 miles per hour, B is 60 miles per hour and C
stands for 50 miles per hour, or if A indicates 7 feet tall, B 6 feet
tall and C 5 feet tall, then (1) is unobjectionable. If each of the
first two constituent parts of (1) is true, and each is, then the truth
of the conclusion follows ineluctably. (2)
However, difficulties arise when the constituent elements of the
argument are not objective dimensions, but rather preferences.
Interpret (1), now, as follows: a given economic actor, Jones,
prefers an Apple to a Banana at time [t.sub.1], a Banana to a Carrot at
time [t.sub.2] and an Apple to a Carrot at time [t.sub.3]. In this
context, both the Austrians and the neo-classicals would accept the
veracity of (1). They part company, however, in their interpretation of
this statement. For the mainstream economist, this example of
transitivity is necessary, (3) at least if rationality is to be
preserved; for the praxeologist, in sharp contrast, it constitutes, only
one of several options, all of which may be characterized as
"rational."
Things become different when we contemplate (2); here, the
difference between the two schools of thought becomes even more stark.
(2) A > B ([t.sub.1]); B > C ([t.sub.2]); C > A
([t.sub.3]).
The reaction of the Austrian to (2) is a big "so what."
(4) These three separate and independent events occur at entirely
different times, (5) and, as a logical necessity, need have nothing
whatsoever to do with one another.
Matters are very different for the commanding heights of the
economics profession. Its reaction to (2) is that it bespeaks nothing
less than "irrationality" on the part of the person making
these three subsequent choices. Why? This is due to the fact that (2) is
an example of intransitivity, and that, as is well known, at least in
those quarters, is equivalent to irrationality.
Defenders of this viewpoint have three arguments to support it: 1)
the money pump; 2) the fact that indifference curves are compatible only
with transitivity, not its denial; 3) the claim that transitivity is
required for empirical research. Let us consider each of these in turn.
1. The money pump
According to this argument, (6) anyone who exhibited the choice
preferences depicted in (2) would be victimized (7) by a loss of his
entire wealth. This is interpreted as proof positive that intransitivity
is irrational.
How does this work?
Given (2), let us assume that Jones starts out with a C. Since he
prefers B to C, he would be willing to pay some amount, over and above
C, to attain a B. Stipulate that this amount is $1. So Jones is now the
proud owner of a B, and his dollar holdings are reduced by $1, after he
purchases a B with his C and $1 at [t.sub.1]. Next, since our economic
actor also regards A as preferable to B, and we are still assuming he
would be willing to pay $1 over and above a B in order to attain an A,
we posit that he does precisely that at [t.sub.2]. Now, he is in
possession of an A, but is minus a total of $2. Whereupon the third
trade occurs, at [t.sub.3]. Here, he relinquishes his hard earned (8) A
in favor of a C, since he now regards the C as higher in his ranking
scale than an A, so much so that he is willing to proffer yet another $1
in order to make this third commercial transaction. Thus, he arrives
precisely back at the point he started, with a C, only he has lost $3 in
so doing. This is supposedly the knockout blow against the Austrian
contention that there is nothing irrational about non-transitivity.
But it fails. Consider the following examples. First, Smith goes to
Harrah's gambling establishment. He loses $3, precisely the same
amount as Jones. Is Smith thereby rendered "irrational?" Not a
bit of it. Smith can "defend" himself, or at least his
"rationality" on the ground that he enjoyed the gambling
process itself, including the chance to come away from the tables a
winner, more than the $3 he lost. So, as with all commercial interaction
in the ex ante sense, although he is out of pocket by $3, he is not at
all "irrational." Rather, he benefited to the extent of the
difference between the $3 he paid, and the pleasure for him of gambling,
plus the ex ante prospect of wining, even though he knew that the house
odds were set against him.
Second, let us focus on equation (3). Here, we cut out the
middleman, C in this case, and view a simpler example.
(3) A > B ([t.sub.1]); B > A ([t.sub.2])
A = $100Cdn
B = $100US
What are the specifics? The Canadian and the U.S. dollar are
trading at par. Green, an American, wants to travel to Canada; he needs
Canadian currency. He starts out with B, in this case $100US. He prefers
A, which is in our example $100Cdn, so much so that he is willing to pay
$5US in order to obtain A. He makes this transaction at [t.sub.1], and
ends up with $100Cdn or A. (We are assuming a transactions cost of $5).
But, then, Green changes his mind about his trip to Canada. He decides
to call it off. The $100Cdn now does him no good. So, at [t.sub.2], he
trades his A back for U.S. currency, at the cost to him of another $5.
(9) Just as in the money pump story, Green ends up precisely where he
began, at B, which, here, is $100US. However, for his pains, he has had
to relinquish $10. This is irrational? Which of us, gentle reader, has
not gone through precisely this transition, (10) or at least one closely
analogous? If this is irrational, we are all irrational. Those of us, in
any case, who have ever changed our minds about value rankings.
What has happened here? It is simple. Green changed his rank
orderings between [t.sub.1] and [t.sub.2]. This led him to avail himself
of not one but two trades. Transactions are not free. (11) Our economic
actor utilized the market not once but twice; he was forced to expend $5
on both occasions. Each time he did so in a completely rational manner.
At [t.sub.1] he preferred A to B; at [t.sub.2] he made the reverse
evaluation.
That is, the apparent irrationality of the money-pump problem
arises because of a fundamental problem with neoclassical economics--its
failure to account for the fact that real individual human beings act in
real historical time, not in timeless neoclassical economic models. (12)
Of course, in an imaginary world in which an individual can engage in
truly simultaneous (13) acts of choice the money-pump would present a
major, perhaps fatal, problem for Austrian economics. However, in the
real world actual people necessarily act sequentially, not
simultaneously. And, of course, preferences can, and do, change through
time. That, of course, is why neoclassical economics assumes
individuals' preferences are stable, (14) in the face of constant
daily evidence to the contrary. It is interesting, is it not, that
neoclassical economics which claims to be an empirical science in which
theory is used to generate hypotheses, that are then tested against the
data, usually using very sophisticated econometric techniques, does not
test one of the fundamental assumptions used to develop its theory; to
wit: the stability of individuals' preferences and its offspring,
transitivity of preferences?
Let us consider this as a possible objection (15) to the foregoing:
"The author is right that losing money need not show irrationality,
but I don't think that this suffices to blunt the force of the
money pump argument. The argument is that someone with intransitive preferences will lose all his money through repeated trades. The claim
isn't that doing so will demonstrate that the person is irrational,
because all cases where money is lost show irrationality. Rather, the
claim is that the chooser won't be able to avoid an outcome, the
loss of all his money, which he may be taken not to want."
Suppose that someone lost all of his money in a casino. Would this
prove that he is irrational? Certainly not, at least not from an
Austrian perspective. Why should the difference between the loss of some
money, and all of it, be determinative? If spending some money in a
manner compatible with the economic actor's goals is rational,
there is no reason why doing so for all of it would not also be
characterized in this manner.
Of course, the economic actor "may be taken not to want... the
loss of all his money" In a sense this is certainly true. No one
wants to lose any of his money, let alone all of it. But the implication
of this critique is that it is irrational to go to a casino, gamble, and
then lose all of one's money. We find it difficult to reconcile
this with what we know of Austrian economics. Suppose, instead of losing
some or all of one's money on gambling, or via the money pump, or
by changing one's mind regarding a visit to Canada, a man spent it
on the proverbial "wine, women and song." Would this be
irrational? Not according to Kirzner (1973): "The man who has cast
aside a budget plan of long standing in order to indulge in the fleeting
pleasure of wine still acts under a constraint to adapt the means to the
new program. Should a fit of anger impel him to forgo this program as
well and to hurl the glass of wine at the bartender's head, there
will nonetheless be operative some constraint--let us say the control
required to ensure an accurate aim--which prevents his action from being
altogether rudderless."
In any case, if the economic actor is so worried about losing some
or all of his money, he can cease and desist from currency exchanges,
from gambling, and, get off the money pump. All he need do in any of
these cases is change his rank preference orderings. If he does not,
then this demonstrates (16) he prefers losing some or all of his money
to any other alternative.
2. Indifference curves (17)
Transitivity is not limited to strong preference; it also includes
weak preference, where A is preferred to B or there is no preference
between A and B (A and B are indifferent), where B is preferred to C or
there is no preference between B and C (B and C are indifferent), and,
thus, where A is preferred to C or there is no preference between A and
C (A and C are indifferent). A third type of transitive relationship is
one of pure indifference: there is no preference between A and B (A and
B are indifferent); there is no preference between B and C (B and C are
indifferent); and, thus, conclusion, there is no preference between A
and C (A and C are indifferent). This latter relationship is of
particular importance to neoclassical economists, as it underlies the
logic of their indifference curves; to wit, it can be used to
demonstrate that indifference curves can never cross, a mainstay of this
analysis.
For, if indifference curves did, perish the thought, cross, this
would logically imply the denial of transitivity. And that, simply,
cannot be borne. (18) To illustrate this point, consider Figure 1.
[FIGURE 1 OMITTED]
Here, (19) the consumer is indifferent between market baskets A and
B; we know this since both lie on indifference curve [U.sub.2]. But, he
is also indifferent between points A and C, since both comprise
different parts of indifference curve [U.sub.1]. By the "law"
of transitivity, things indifferent to the same thing are indifferent to
each other. Well, B and C both bear the relationship of indifference to
A. So, B and C must bear the same relationship to each other, namely,
indifference. But, as can clearly be seen in the diagram, B lies above
and to the right of C, and we are assuming we are in the realm where
more of a good is preferred to less. Thus, QED, indifference curves
cannot cross one another.
In the view of Hirshleifer, et al. (2005, p. 80): "By
transitivity, the consumer must therefore be indifferent between C and
B. But B represents more of both commodities than C. Since X and Y are
both goods, more is preferred to less, and the consumer must prefer B
over C. But these two implications contradict one another. So the
initial assumption is invalid: indifference curves cannot
intersect." (20)
But this goes too fast. If premises J and K contradict one another,
why do we so quickly assume that J is correct, and K incorrect? Yes,
crossed indifference curves and transitivity cannot both be true, they
do indeed contradict one another, but why does it follow that we accept
the latter and not the former? Why not invert matters?
As we have seen, transitivity is a week reed upon which to hang
anything, let alone indifference curve "analysis." If
transitivity fails, according to this logic, then so must indifference
curves. (21)
3. Empirical research (22)
Bradbury and Ross (1990) show a negative correlation between age
and transitivity "violations": children display fewer
intransitive choices as they grow older; adults exhibit hardly any. (23)
Hirshleifer et al. (2005, p. 71) comment on these findings as follows:
At very low ages, transitivity failures might arguably be due
to the limited reasoning abilities of young children. As
another possible explanation, what appear to be
intransitivities may only reflect that [sic] fact
that younger persons are still exploring their needs and
tastes ... Although the tabulated percentages of intransitive
choices steadily decrease with rising age, there is one
exception: the sudden sharp increase at age 13. Perhaps
the onset of puberty opens up new types of novelties
calling for exploration.
We have a far simpler explanation. (24) People sometimes change
their minds in their rank orderings of preferences. All of these choices
are made at different times. Thus, there is no anomaly to be explained.
Moreover, they change their minds in ways that are difficult if not
impossible to account for, given that they have free will. Given the
Hirshleifer account, however, all sorts of anomalies rise up: why is it
that adults, who are supposedly so much more "rational" than
children still defect from the transitive stance to the tune of 13
percent? Why that sudden jump at 13? Do not some children reach puberty
at 12 years of age? Yet they seem curiously unafflicted by the break in
the correlation that appears one year later.
IV. CONCLUSION
Transitivity is an economic travesty. Its adherents simply do not
recognize, nor appreciate, that decisions can only be made one at a
time, and that people can change their rank order preferences from the
time that they make the first choice in a series to the time they make
the third. There is thus nothing irrational about non-transitive
preferences. If transitivity is needed for indifference curve (and
utility function) analysis, then so much the worse for indifference (and
utility function) curve analysis. (25)
REFERENCES
Anderson, William L. 2000. "Austrian Economics and the
'Market Test': A Comment on Laband and Tollison."
Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics 3, no. 3: 63-73.
Arrow, Kenneth. 1951. Social Choice and Individual Values,
Monograph 12. New York: John Wiley and Sons.
Ayer, Alfred J. 1952. Logic, Truth, and Language. New York: Dover.
Barnett, William II. 2003. "The Modern Theory of Consumer
Behavior: Ordinal or Cardinal?" Quarterly Journal of Austrian
Economics 6, no. 1: 41-65.
Barnett, William II, and Walter E. Block. 2008. "Economic
Singularism." Research in the History of Economic Thought and
Methodology 26-A: 15-30.
Black, Duncan. 1948. "On the Rationale of Group
Decision-Making." Journal of Political Economy 56, no. 1: 23-34.
Block, Walter. 1999. "Austrian Theorizing, Recalling the
Foundations: Reply to Caplan." Quarterly Journal of Austrian
Economics 2, no. 4: 21-39. Available at
http://www.mises.org/journals/qjae/pdf/ qjae2_4_2.pdf; errata:
http://www.mises.org/journals/qjae/pdf/ qjae2_4_9.pdf.
--. 2000. "Austrian Journals: A Critique of Rosen, Yeager,
Laband and Tollison, and Vedder and Gallaway." Quarterly Journal of
Austrian Economics 3, no. 2: 45-61.
--. 2003. "Realism: Austrian vs. Neoclassical Economics, Reply
to Caplan," Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics 6, no. 3:
63-76.
--. 2005. "Rejoinder to Caplan on Bayesian Economics."
Journal of Libertarian Studies 19, no. 1: 79-95. Available at
http://blog.mises.org/ blog/archives/003654.asp.
--. 2007. "Reply to Caplan on Austrian Economic
Methodology." Corporate Ownership and Control 4, no. 2: 312-326.
Bradbury, Hinton, and Karen Ross. 1990. "The Effects of
Novelty and Choice Materials on the Intransitivity of Preferences of
Children and Adults." Annals of Operations Research 23: 141-159.
Caplan, Bryan. 1999. "The Austrian Search for Realistic
Foundations," Southern Economic Journal 65, no. 4: 823-838.
--. 2001. "Probability, Common Sense, and Realism: A Reply to
Hulsmann and Block." Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics
4, no. 2: 69-86.
--. 2003. "Probability and the Synthetic A Priori: A Reply to
Block." Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics 6, no. 3: 77-83.
Carnap, Rudolph. 1950. Testability and Meaning. New Haven, Conn.:
Yale University Press.
Coase, Ronald H. 1960. "The Problem of Social Cost."
Journal of Law and Economics 3, no. 1: 1-44.
Davidson, Donald, John McKinsey and Patrick Suppes. 1955.
"Outlines of a Formal Theory of Value, I," Philosophy of
Science 22: 140-160.
Ebenstein, Alan. 2001. Friedrich Hayek: A Biography. New York:
Palgrave.
Feld, Scott L., and Bernard Grofman. 1990. "Voting in
One's Head as a Source of Nearly Transitive Individual Preferences
over Multi-Dimensional Issues." Annals of Operations Research 23,
no. 1: 257-263.
Gendin, Sid. 1996. "Why Preference Is not Transitive."
Philosophical Quarterly 46, no. 185: 482-488.
Gordon, David. 2003. "Book Review of Epistemological Problems
of Economics, by Ludwig von Mises." Mises Review 9, no. 2.
Hansson, Sven Ove. 1993. "Money-Pumps, Self-Torturers and the
Demons of Real Life." Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71:
476-485.
Hosseini, Hamid. 1990. "The Archaic, the Obsolete and the
Mythical in Neoclassical Economics. Problems with the Rationality and
Optimizing Assumptions of the Jevons-Marshallian System." American
Journal of Economics and Sociology 49, no. 1: 81-92.
Hempel, Carl G. 1970. Aspects of Scientific Explanation. New York:
Free Press.
Hirshleifer, Jack, Amihai Glazer, and David Hirshleifer. 2005.
Price Theory and Applications. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hoppe, Hans-Hermann. 2005. "Must Austrians Embrace
Indifference?" Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics 8, no. 4:
87-91.
Hulsmann, JOrg Guido. 1999. "Economic Science and
Neoclassicism." Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics 2, no. 4:
1-20.
Kaneko, Mamoru. 1975. "Necessary and Sufficient Conditions for
Transitivity in Voting Theory." Journal of Economic Theory 11, no.
3: 385-393.
Kaufmann, Felix. 1944. Methodology of the Social Sciences. Atlantic
Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press.
Kirzner, Israel M. 1973. Competition and Entrepreneurship, Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Laband, David N., and Robert D. Tollison. 2000. "On
Secondhandism and Scientific Appraisal." Quarterly Journal of
Austrian Economics 3, no. 1: 43-48.
Long, Roderick T. 2006. "Realism and Abstraction in Economics:
Aristotle and Mises versus Friedman." Quarterly Journal of Austrian
Economics 9, no. 3: 3-23.
Mas-Colell, A., M. Whinston, and J. Green. 1995. Microeconomic Theory. New York: Oxford University Press.
Mises, Ludwig von. 1949. Human Action: The Scholar's Edition.
Auburn, Ala.: Ludwig von Mises Institute, 1998.
Nagel, Ernest. 1961. The Structure of Science. New York: Harcourt,
Brace and World.
Nicolaides, Phedon. 1988. "Limits to the Expansion of
Neoclassical Economics." Cambridge Journal of Economics 12, no. 3:
313-328.
Pejovic, Svetozar. 2001. "Book Review of Timothy Roth, Ethics,
Economics, and Freedom." Journal of Socio-Economics 30, no. 4:
375-377.
Popper, Karl R. 1959. Logic of Scientific Discovery, New York:
Harper and Row.
--. 1969. Conjectures and Refutations. London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul.
Ramsey, Frank P. 1928. "Truth and Probability." In R. B.
Braithwaite, ed., The Foundations of Mathematics and Other Logical
Essays. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1950.
Rodrigues, Joao. 2004. "Endogenous Preferences and
Embeddedness: A Reappraisal of Karl Polanyi." Journal of Economic
Issues 38, no. 1: 189-200.
Rosen, Sherwin. 1997. "Austrian and Neoclassical Economics:
Any Gains from Trade?" Journal of Economic Perspectives 11, no. 4:
139-152.
Rothbard. Murray N. 1956. "Toward a Reconstruction of Utility
and Welfare Economics." In The Logic of Action, vol. I: 211-254.
Lyme, N.H.: Edward Elgar, 1997.
Sears, Francis W., Mark W. Zemansky, and Hugh D. Young. 1987.
University Physics, 7th ed. Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley.
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2006. Available at
http://plato.stanford. edu/entries/preferences/.
Stigler, George J. and Gary S. Becker. 1977. "De Gustibus Non
Est Disputandum." American Economic Review 67, no. 2: 76-90.
Thornton, Mark. 2004. "Does Academic Publishing Pass the Real
Market Test?" Public Choice 120, no. 1: 41-61.
Yeager, Leland B. 1997. "Austrian Economics, Neoclassicism,
and the Market Test." Journal of Economic Perspectives 11, no. 4:
153-163.
--. 2000. "The Tactics of Secondhandism." Quarterly
Journal of Austrian Economics 3, no. 3: 51-61.
(1) Our use of such nomenclature stems from Stanford (2006).
(2) The truth of the premises is entirely separate from the
validity of the argument. Even if the premises are false, the
transitivity relationship can still constitute a valid argument. For
example, consider these claims: 7 > 8, 6 > 7, therefore 6 > 8.
All three statements are false, yet the argument is a valid one: the
conclusion follows logically from the premises.
(3) This may well be the single exception where conventional
economists veer from their otherwise very strong adherence to
empiricism. Here, then, they are acting as praxeologists, but the
deductive method is no guarantee of success. It, too, can fail, as in
the present case; this method provides no warranty against logical
error.
(4) States Mises (1998), p. 430 (emphasis added by present
authors):
The advantages and disadvantages derived from cash holding are
not objective factors which could directly influence the size
of cash holdings. They are put on the scales by each individual
and weighed against one another. The result is a subjective
judgment of value, colored by the individual's personality.
Different people and the same people at different times value
the same objective facts in a different way. Just as knowledge
of a man's wealth and his physical condition does not tell us
how much he would be prepared to spend for food of a certain
nutritive power, so knowledge about data concerning a man's
material situation does not enable us to make definite assertions
with regard to the size of his cash holding.
We owe this citation to our Loyola University colleague Stuart
Wood. As for cash holdings, also as for apples, bananas, carrots and
indeed, all else. See also Barnett and Block (2008); for an alternative
view, see Stigler and Becker (1977).
(5) States Mises (1998), p. 103: "The attempt has been made to
attain the notion of a nonrational action by this reasoning: If a is
preferred to b and b to c, logically a should be preferred to c. But if
actually c is preferred to a, we are faced with a mode of acting to
which we cannot ascribe consistency and rationality. This reasoning
disregards the fact that two acts of an individual can never be
synchronous." We owe this citation to Gordon (2003).
(6) Ramsey (1928a), p. 182; Davidson et al. (1955); Hansson (1993).
See also http:// www.answers.com/topic/preference.
(7) Hirshleifer, et al. (2005), p. 71, go so far as to accuse the
so-called victimizer of this little exercise of being a "clever
swindler."
(8) Hard traded, that is.
(9) It matters not whether this is in US$ or Cdn$, they trade at
par; but to keep things simple, we assume that he pays $5US for each of
his two transactions, or $10 for the both of them.
(10) This is why department stores have return policies: people
change their minds.
(11) Coase (1960).
(12) Models in which a time index is attached to some variables in
order to allow the variables to change value in accord with some
predetermined relationship to "time" have nothing to do with
real historical time. An example of such simplistic models is one in
which the value of some variable, say labor (L), at any point in
"time" in a growth model is given [L.sub.t] =
[L.sub.0][e.sup.kt], [L.sub.0] is the initial value of L at 0, and k is
the (constant) continuous growth rate per continuous period, t. Models
with such features can be found in virtually any issue of the American
Economic Review in the last few decades.
(13) See Sears, et al. (1987), p. 958, for a fascinating account of
why simultaneity is highly problematic in physics, too. See also in this
regard the mathematical concept "cone of light":
http://www.phy.syr.edu/courses/modules/LIGHTCONE/ introduction.html.
(14) According to Pejovic (2001) (emphasis added): "The basic
assumptions of neoclassical economics include unbounded rationality,
exogenously determined and stable preferences, exogenerously [sic]
determined technical knowledge, maximizing behavior, and market
equilibrium." See Nicolaides (1988); Hosseini (1990); see also
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Neoclassical_economics.
In the view of Rosen (1997), p. 147 (emphasis added):
... having observed choices in different price and income
configurations, we can invert the process and infer what
those underlying preferences must have been, as long as
preferences are reasonably stable and the source of variation
is sufficient to achieve identification.
Many Austrians hold to the view that quantitative empirical work in
economics is infeasible or uninteresting because the world is
changing so much that "behavioral relationships" inherently
are unstable and it is fruitless to estimate them. An
unwillingness to pursue the consequences of "given conditions"
greatly limits the empirical scope and consequences of Austrian
economic theory. The paucity of quantitative empirical work in
the Austrian tradition accounts for why so few Austrians are
found in the professional economics community today.
For support of Rosen, see Laband and Tollison (2000); also see
rejoinders to Rosen by Anderson (2000), Block (2000), Thornton (2004);
Yeager (1997, 2000).
(15) This objection was suggested to us by a referee of this
journal.
(16) Rothbard (1956).
(17) For a mainstream defense of indifference, see Caplan (1999,
2001, 2003); for an Austrian critique, see Block (1999, 2003, 2005,
2007), Hoppe (2005), Hulsmann (1999).
(18) Who says that modern mainstream economics is purely an
empirical science? Not so, not so. Just as the Austrians do, the
neoclassicals adhere to praxeological insights, albeit incorrect ones in
this case; for example, transitivity. They do not at all embrace
philosophical notions of falsifiability (Carnap [1950], Ayer [1952],
Popper [1959, 1969], Hempel [1970], Nagel [1961], Kaufmann [1944]) as
far as transitivity is concerned. Rather, they see this doctrine as one
of apodictic certainty. If so, then in Friedman's notion, whenever
two neoclassical economists disagree about matters of indifference, or
transitivity, or any other matter that they regard in a non empirical
manner, they can only engage in a fist fight with each other. States
Friedman (see Long [2006], p. 19; Ebenstein [2001], p. 273): "That
methodological approach, I think, has very negative influences.... [It]
tends to make people intolerant. If you and I are both praxeologists,
and we disagree about whether some proposition or statement is correct,
how do we resolve that disagreement? We can yell, we can argue, we can
try to find a logical flaw in one another's thing [sic], but in the
end we have no way to resolve it except by fighting, by saying
you're wrong and I'm right." The obvious rejoinder is
that mathematicians and logicians rarely resort to fisticuffs over
matters of this sort, and therefore neither are praxeologists compelled
to do so.
(19) Hirshleifer (2005), diagram 3, p. 80; we owe this citation to
David Schap.
(20) We owe this citation to David Schap. (The nomenclature has
been slightly changed regarding the identification of the points on the
indifference curve map.)
(21) Also at risk for neoclassical economics are utility functions
for a preference relation can be represented by a utility function only
if it is complete and transitive. See on this Mas-Colell (1995), p. 9.
We owe this point to Patrick McAlvanah. Also see Gendin (1996).
(22) Nick Sanchez has alerted us to the fact that there is an
extensive literature in decision science indicating that transitivity is
normally violated in many experiments; for example, Bradbury and Ross
(1990). Chuck Anderton has pointed out to us that the game "rock,
paper, scissors" violates transitivity (see:
http://andreality.wordpress.com/2007/03/04/transitivity/;
http://newbricks. blogspot.com/2007/07/tipping-point-concept-of-non.html) and that voting can also do so. See on this latter point Arrow (1951),
Black (1948), Kaneko (1975), and Feld and Grofman (1990).
(23) Ages (percentage of intransitive choices made): 4(83), 5(82),
6(82), 7(78), 8(68), 9(57), 10(52), 11(37), 12(23), 13(41), adults(13).
(24) Where, oh where is Occam's Razor when we need it?
(25) For more on problems with utility function analysis, see
Barnett (2003).
Walter E. Block (wblock@loyno.edu) and William Barnett II
(wbarnett@loyno.edu) are Harold E. Wirth Eminent Scholar Endowed Chair
and Professor of Economics and Chase Distinguished Professor of
International Business and Professor of Economics, respectively, at the
Joseph A. Butt, S.J. College of Business, Loyola University New Orleans.
The authors would like to thank the following people for raising these
issues, commenting on earlier drafts of this paper and inspiring us to
write about this issue: Patrick McAlvanah, Scott Kjar, John Carter, Nick
Sanchez, David Schap and Sid Genden. None of them are responsible in any
way for our views. Indeed, they are our sharpest critics. We also thank
a referee of this journal for helpful suggestions regarding an earlier
version of this paper. All remaining errors are of course the
responsibility of the authors.