Thinking, Fast and Slow.
Howden, David
Thinking, Fast and Slow
Daniel Kahneman
London: Allen Lane, 2011, 499 pp.
How rational are humans? Many important implications hinge on this
seemingly innocuous question hinge, for not only economists, but all
social scientists. In Thinking, Fast and Slow, psychologist and
recipient of the 2002 Nobel memorial prize in economics (alongside
Vernon Smith), Daniel Kahneman, gives a summary view of the question. At
first glance the book seems to be an overview of Kahneman's
lifework, but upon closer inspection it offers much more. Kahneman
synthesizes the research of the past forty years to give the reader a
more or less complete answer to the question: how rational are we? He
also explains the special cases where humans resort to alternative
heuristics in their decision-making.
The thick book is split into five parts. Part I provides the reader
with the view, today more or less accepted in psychology circles, that
the brain has two systems to aid it making choices. System 1 includes
the automatic and instinctive reactions that we rely on (without knowing
it) for many natural responses. We often cannot explain the reasons for
a choice when system 1 is operative. System 2 forms our mind's
controlled operations, the ones we exercise that we typically associate
with reasoning.
Parts II and III cover interactions and conflicts that these two
systems have with each other, and the cognitive biases that result. When
scientists propose that humans act rationally, what they have in mind is
that all decisions are undertaken by system 2--reasoned, deliberated,
and correct given the facts at hand. As research now makes clear, system
2 is not always operative, even when we think it is. Kahneman provides
the reader a great service by not only outlining this point, but also
describing the conditions that make our minds favor relying on system 1,
such as when we are tired, overconfident, or when our mood is relaxed or
upbeat.
Parts IV and V are where the book gets interesting for the
economist. In these sections the reader is served an array of ways in
which biases enter and skew our decision-making. In part IV Kahneman
outlines what choices we can expect to see individuals make when they
are prone to biases. In part V he gives the reader the model he thinks
social scientists should invoke when discussing rationality.
How applicable is this alternative model of "rationality"
that Kahneman puts forward? Before answering the question, reflect upon
the state of affairs that existed when Kahneman was a young scholar at
the Oregon Research Institute in Eugene, Oregon, during the early 1970s.
At that time it was becoming increasingly self-evident to psychologists
that humans were neither fully rational nor completely selfish. Consider
his astonishment upon discovering for the first time that his
neighbors--the economists--use an economic agent that is "rational,
selfish, and [whose] tastes do not change" (p. 269). The contrast
between homo economicus and real humans would provide the springboard
from which Kahneman launched his life's work, focusing on biases in
choice.
Recognition of such "irrational" biases would later give
rise to the two types of economic agents popularized by Richard Thaler
as "Econs" and "Humans." Unlike their Econ
counterparts, Humans have a System 1 and are subsequently open to
cognitive biases. Yet, as much as this economist agrees with the
conclusions that led Kahneman to develop an alternative to Econs, he
cannot agree with all of the rationales. That humans seem to fit poorly
into a fully rational model of man seems evident, yet some of the listed
cognitive biases seem misplaced.
Take two examples provided by Kahneman. In explaining that effort
is greater when trying to avoid a loss than making a gain, Kahneman
cites a golf study. Golfers are more successful putting for par
(avoiding a loss) than for birdie (securing a gain), and this is taken
by Kahneman as evidence that we exert more effort to avoid a loss than
to earn a gain. Yet this study seem to lack an important ceteris paribus condition--any putt for birdie has a one stroke advantage in getting to
the pin and the resultant shot must be easier, thus increasing its
success rate.
In another example, Kahneman gives the reader a choice between two
bets:
Bet A: Toss a coin. It is comes up heads you win $100, and if it
comes up tails you win nothing.
Bet B: Get $46 for sure.
When asked between the safe and riskier bet, safety prevails and
those questioned regularly choose the safer bet B. This is one of
various similar examples that Kahneman gives to argue that we are not
fully rational (or at least not utility maximizing) when making even
simple choices. It is also the base example that led Amos Tversky and
him to develop Prospect Theory--the idea that choices are evaluated
based on the potential gain or loss a decision creates, rather than the
final outcome.
Yet important problems exist with these structured scenarios. For
example, the statistics that result from these games are meaningless
outside long series of repeated trials. The reason B is preferred to A
is clear if one considers that the expected payoff of A will only obtain
under repeated trials--something precluded in the game as played. If the
game is structured to allow only a single bet, there are two possible
payoffs--nothing or $100--and either is as likely as the other. The
bettor given such a choice is uncertain as to what the expected payoff
is--uncertain in the sense that he cannot quantify what the outcome will
be: it could be nothing, but it could just as easily be $100. The one
thing that he will be certain of, however, is that the payoff from a
single bet will not be $50. As such, the choice is not a binary one
between a risky yet expected value of $50 and a certain $46, but between
the certain bet and the perceived likelihood (and expected utility) of
gaining nothing or $100.
In his conclusion, Kahneman treads in what he realizes are
controversial waters when he advocates for libertarian paternalism.
Market-oriented ideals err, according to him, because of their
over-reliance on agents' system 2 functions, while ignoring those
circumstances when system 1 takes over. In this he falls prey to his own
cognitive bias--this one in thinking his own preferred ends are superior
to those of others.
Kahneman feels that for ends that are "socially
beneficial," such as high savings rates, governments can positively
nudge their citizens in the right direction by properly incentivizing
them. This reviewer is not so sure. The apparent pretense of knowledge
is in knowing what end is preferred. While an increased savings rate is
fairly innocent, what if the government decided that increased home
ownership would enhance social welfare, and that policies should be
designed around this end. We have already seen how that act played out
during this recession, and I am sure that readers can think of other
policies equally well intentioned that could go awry.
In conclusion, this reviewer cannot help but feel Kahneman goes too
far with his use of system 1 in advocating the use of Humans over Econs.
While many agree that there are problematic aspects with economists
using an overly rational Econs model of man, replacing this with a
frequently biased Humans model seems equally dangerous. While humans may
not be natural statisticians, they are capable of reasoning facts in
many circumstances. If the economist is to use Humans as a model, he
must also accept that this change will allow for only special theories
to be sought after. Without a general model for how humans act
irrespective of time or place, the economist will be resigned to
developing specialized theories, cognizant of the biases and errors
their subject commits under specific conditions. This approach seems
unwarranted.
A more fruitful, if difficult approach lies in recognizing that
humans are rational within the confines placed on them. Attention would
be better directed not on irrationalities qua cognitive biases, but
rather on constraints that act as common denominators limiting all
actions--the limited and imperfect knowledge set available. That this
limited knowledge involves both the data necessary to make a choice and
also the cognitive ability to decipher some results of these choices
allows for the results that Kahneman outlines in Thinking, Fast and
Slow, while still maintaining a general theory of rationality. Such an
approach, in distinction to Kahneman's and other behavioral
economists', allows for economics to remain a science with
universal validity, without getting sidetracked down spurs that relate
to specific theories, with limited applicability outside the realm of
their own constraints. Cognitive biases do a good job at illustrating
shortcomings of an overly-rational homo economicus, but fail to provide
a better alternative.
David Howden
David Howden (dhowden@slu.edu) is chairman of the Department of
Business and Economics, St. Louis University--Madrid Campus.