Rejoinder to Brooks on Coase and Demsetz.
Block, Walter E.
INTRODUCTION
Brooks (2007, p. 223) is quite correct when he asserts that
"for over one quarter of a century" Demsetz (1967, 1979, 1997)
and I (Block, 1977, 1995, 2000) have been involved in a debate
concerning "one small corner of the voluminous literature on the
Coase theorem." (1) While in the midst of these interchanges over
the years, for me, 1977-2000, I had often wondered why no one else had
jumped into this particular fray. With the appearance of Brooks (2007),
I need wonder no more. I am delighted to welcome Brooks to this
particular sandbox, and am comforted by his (albeit limited) support for
my position vis a vis that of Demsetz.
In section II we offer some background material to highlight the
various disputes; one, between Demsetz and me, and two, between Brooks
and me. Section III offers a critique of both of these scholars.
BACKGROUND
Before commenting on Brooks' contribution to the Block-Demsetz
debate, first, a bit of background. For Coase (1960), the fountainhead of this entire debate, two things are true. one, under a regime of zero
transactions costs, (2) it does not matter, at least for questions of
resource allocation, which of two contending parties gets the nod from
the court, in a property rights dispute. Suppose there is a manufacturer
(M) who pollutes the fields of a farmer (F). (3) There is a smoke
prevention device (SPD), which may or may not be utilized (that is the
resource allocation issue). This naturally devolves into four separate
cases, A, B, C and D, depending upon whether the court finds in favor of
one or the other, and based upon the costs of installing the SPC, versus
the costs to the farmer of allowing the pollution to continue, unabated.
In Table I, we indicate the winner of the court case by underlining
either the F or the M.
Let us now discuss each of these four cases.
In case A we posit that the farmer values the pollution free air at
$75, the SPD will cost $100 to install, and that the judge finds in
favor of the farmer. The law, then, gives the farmer the right to
require that the SPD be installed. However, it costs the manufacturer
$100 to do so and the farmer only benefits from this to the tune of $75.
There is room for a (costless) transaction, a bribe, here. The
manufacturer can pay the farmer, say, $90. The farmer, if he accepts,
will lose the $75 from the dirty air, but gain this payment of $90, for
a profit of $15. The manufacturer has to pay $90, but he gains the $100
he would legally otherwise have to lay out for the SPD, so he also gains
from the deal, in his case by $10. So, the SPD does not get installed,
even though the farmer won the right from the court to legally impose
this requirement on the manufacturer.
In case C we again posit that the farmer values the pollution free
air at $75, and that the SPD will cost $100 to install, but this time
that the judge gives the nod to the manufacturer. Will resources be
allocated to the utilization of the SPD? No. The farmer values the clean
air, only, at $75. It would cost $100 for the manufacturer to cease and
desist from polluting, employing the SPD. There is no way the farmer
could bribe the manufacturer into using the SPD for the sake of clean
air.
In cases B and D we reverse the benefits and costs. Now, the farmer
values clean air at $100 and it costs only $75 to attain this goal for
him, via the SPD. In case D, the judgment goes to the farmer; the
manufacturer cannot bribe the farmer out of insisting on his right to
the SPD, since it now costs less to install this device than the
benefits to be derived therefrom. So resources are allocated to the SPD.
In contrast, in case B the manufacturer is told by the court that he
need not install the SPD. However, it is advantageous to both that a
deal be consummated that will bring about that end. For the farmer
values the benefits to the tune of $100, and this is $25 more than the
costs to the manufacturer of installing this device ($75). If the farmer
pays the manufacturer to do so, even though the law does not require him
to engage in this act, the farmer can pay the manufacturer $90 to adopt
the SPD. The latter will gain this $90, minus the cost of the SPD of
$75, for a profit of $15. The farmer will gain $100, the value he places
on the clean air, minus the bribe of $90, for a gain of $10. (4)
In this analysis, we assume, heroically and arguendo, that all of
these figures, values, costs, are known with absolute certainty.
CRITIQUE
With this background, we are now ready to consider Brooks'
contribution to the Block-Demsetz debate. It is with regard to only one
of these four cases that Demsetz and I (and also Brooks and I) have any
dispute: B. Here, I supposed (in Block 1977, 1995 and 2000) that the
benefit to the farmer of that $100 was not in the form of money, or
objective goods that could serve as collateral, that would be sufficient
to finance the bribe of $90. Rather, I posited that this $100 of benefit
would take the form of pure subjective and psychic income. There is no
objective market-based value to the farm at all. Think of it in terms of
a single flower pot, or, if you will, a worthless rock (garden), (5)
which has great sentimental value to the "farmer," in that he
would not voluntarily part with it for anything less than that $100:
given the contrary to fact conditional that the "farmer" were
offered this amount of money for his flower pot or rock, he would have
declined. (6) While the "farmer" values his property to this
extent, he cannot sell it (no one else wants it), nor can he use it as
collateral to raise the money with which to bribe the manufacturer into
ceasing and desisting from his pollution activities.
What then? My conclusion then, Demsetz to the contrary
notwithstanding, and my conclusion now, Brooks to the contrary
notwithstanding, is that under these assumptions, this relatively
unimportant Coase theorem cannot stand up. (7)
Demsetz (1979, 1997), I fear, never really understood this point.
Although this must necessarily be speculative, I thought I knew why
Demsetz refused to see this remarkably simple point: Coase has won the
Nobel Prize, Demsetz himself is "Nobelabile," (8) and, in his
eyes, I am now and was then a complete non-entity as far as the
mainstream economics profession is concerned. Sadly, this is all too
true. How, then, could I not only criticize the two of them, my clear
intellectual betters, but actually succeed in showing them both to be
erroneous in a claim of theirs? I must have erred, and Demsetz set out
to show that this was indeed the case.
Why, in contrast, does Brooks reject my thesis? I think, although,
again, this can only be speculative, that this economist does full well
understand my position. He nevertheless gives several reasons for
rejecting it (at least in part). Let us consider each of them in some
detail, along with several other criticisms I articulate against this
author.
1. States Brooks (2007, p. 227),
The Coasian [sic] position, at least in terms of the strong and the
weak versions of the Coase theorem, is irreducibly a comparative
static exercise. Block's line of argument is akin to the position
that one can say something about changes to a market price by just
focusing on demand or supply independent of the other. And just as
statements about price involve an exercise considering the twin
blades of the Marshallian scissors, statements about the Coase
theorem involve a comparative static exercise where the variable is
the definition of property rights. If one were to follow Block and
focus on strictly one such scenario then all that one would learn
is that if the gardener does not have the pecuniary means to
protect her (sic) (9) property rights that the garden will wither and
die. But that's not a statement about the Coase theorem in either
its strong or weak form. One would still have to ask what would
happen to the allocation of resources or its normative content if
the property rights were allocated instead to the gardener in order
to complete a statement of the Coase theorem.
There are several difficulties here. It is remarkable that a
favorable reference to the "Marshallian scissors" should
appear in a journal devoted to Austrian economics, without, at least,
any reference to criticism from this source. This mainstream tool of
analysis has been so thoroughly debunked by praxeologists, (10) that it
is rather cavalier to rely upon it in this or any other manner.
As to the necessity of comparative statics, I am of two minds on
this. On the one hand, I wish to assert that what I have done, above, in
comparing my four scenarios A, B, C and D, is nothing but comparative
statics. Nor is this the first time I have put matters in this way.
Indeed, Block 1977, 1995 and 2000 is based on this way of looking at
this issue. My treatment in the present paper breaks no ground. It is
but a reiteration of what I have said before.
On the other hand, I wish to deny that if these four scenarios A,
B, C and D, do not constitute comparative statics, then there is no need
for them at all. Indeed, I go further, even if these four scenarios A,
B, C and D, do constitute comparative statics, there is still no need
for this mode of analysis. Rather, we can focus, solely, on situation B.
Here, the farmer loses the court case, and must
bribe the manufacturer if he wants to retain his flower pot in good
order. But, he simply lacks the wherewithal to make this payment, even
though he will benefit to a greater extent ($100) if he could but do so,
than the costs of gaining him this asset ($75).
Let me argue by analogy. Suppose someone were to make the following
claims:
E: 2 + 2 = 4
F: 2 + 3 = 4
G: 2 + 4 = 6
H: 2 + 5 = 7
I agree with E, G and H, but not with F. (11) Analogously, of the
four scenarios I mentioned above, I agreed with A, C and D, but not B. I
am at a total loss to understand why I cannot properly single out B and
F, in each of these two sets, and reject, only a single one of them,
alone. Why, pray tell, must I compare B to any of these others,
comparative statics wise, and ditto in this regard for F? Brooks (2007,
p. 227) avers that the comparative static analysis must take place with
regard to the definition of property rights, by which I suppose he
refers to the judge's decision regarding ownership or not, to
rights to clean air. But again, why not consider scenario B, all on its
lonesome, to make the claim that for the (zero transactions cost) Coase
theorem to be true, it must stipulate real values on the part of the
farmer, and not mere psychic ones?
2. Then there is the issue of the "strong" and the
"weak" versions of the Coase theorem. I confess I was then
unaware of this distinction. Now that this is no longer the case, I
confess I cannot see my way clear to appreciating its importance. Let us
allow Brooks to explain. He (2007, p. 224) defines the former version in
these words: "The strong version of the Coase theorem states that
if transactions costs are zero, then the allocation of resources will be
identical irrespective of the initial assignment of property
rights." Brooks (2007, p. 226) sees the "weak" version in
these terms: "if transactions costs are zero, then an efficient
allocation of resources will be achieved irrespective of the initial
assignment of property rights." Try as I might, I cannot see any
difference between these two statements; they appear to be paraphrases
of each other, and, pretty close paraphrases of each other at that. One
is in the passive voice, the other not, but for all that, it is
otherwise identical. I must reject any criticism of my work on this
subject on the basis of this "distinction." This distinction
seems to be made up entirely by Brooks. I can find no reference to it in
Coase (1960). Certainly, Brooks (2007) does not cite Coase (1960) in
this regard.
Of course, Brooks uses different words for these two versions. The
"strong" speaks in terms of identical resource allocation no
matter what is the court finding, and the "weak" on the basis
of efficient allocation of resources on this basis. But this is a
distinction without a difference. Why so? It is because for the
Coaseans, the efficient resource allocation is precisely the one that
ensues under the assumption of zero transactions costs, no matter how
the property rights are initially assigned by the judge.
3. Brooks (2007, p. 227, fn. 4) is unhappy with my distinction
between ex ante and ex post income effects. He notes that "It is
hard to see how the term ex ante income effect, which leaves out the
possibility of any change in real income, will be accepted by
economists, at least by those with a neoclassical bent who treat the
phrase income effect as shorthand for a parallel shift of budget lines
or equivalently a change in real income." Let me just say that I am
blissfully unmoved by the very strong possibility that mainstream
economists will not accept this nomenclature. (12) I was led to
introduce this terminology out of frustration that I could not get
Demsetz, a very intelligent and creative economist, to see that I
(Block, 1979) was not making the rather elementary mistake of failing to
realize that Coase (1960) full well appreciated that different judicial
decisions would indeed impact the wealth positions of contending
parties.
Here was another motivation of mine. Sometimes, in my classes, when
I am trying to get across a difficult point (heck, any point), and I do
not see the light bulbs going off on the top of the heads of my
students, I try to articulate it in an entirely different way, on the
ground that if one mode of expression will not do the trick, then
another might. It was entirely in this spirit that I introduced ex ante
and ex post "income effects." My thought was that if I could
but indicate to Demsetz that I full well saw his point, but he did not
see mine, then perhaps progress could be made in our intellectual
impasse. My means of doing so, ex ante and ex post "income
effects," was, admittedly, contrived, but all is fair in love, war,
and attempts to get that one millionth of an inch closer to the truth. I
was attempting to put my point in language Demsetz would understand. I
thought that "income effects" would break the ice. Of course,
"strictly speaking, the ex ante concept involves no income effect
at all" (Brooks, 2007, p. 227, fn. 4.) (13) That was precisely my
point. This ploy did not at all work for Demsetz, and it seems to have
failed, dismally, with Brooks as well. But I am not willing to
relinquish it on the basis of this sample of only two.
If Brooks does not relish my distinction between ex post and ex
ante income effects (I thought it was rather clever) I react to his
between the "strong" and the "weak" Coase theorems
in a similar manner. To me, it is a primordial, undeniable,
praxeological claim that if the farmer does not have the wherewithal
with which to bribe the manufacturer in case B; if his only
"wealth" consists of the psychic income enjoyment of his
flower pot, then this claim of Coase's (scenario B) cannot be
maintained. No twisting or turning on the part of Brooks or Demsetz can
gainsay this elemental fact.
What I was trying to do, then, with my totally contrived concept of
the ex ante income effect, was to demonstrate to Coaseans and
Demsetzians that this was a null set. This phraseology constituted my
attempt to demonstrate the utter failure of the (pet rock)
"farmer" to bribe the manufacturer into ceasing his pollution.
It was intended as nothing more than a heuristic device to that end.
O.K., it failed. Demsetz did not see it, and Brooks misinterprets this
as well. I am completely open to other pedagogical devices for
clarifying this point.
4. But Brooks has another arrow in his quiver, the claim that there
is something wrong with, or untoward about, the farmer having no income
whatsoever. Brooks (2007, p. 228, n. 5) plaintively asks, "Just how
such a poor farmer meets her [sic] land taxes or buys any inputs in the
market is something of a mystery. Consequently, though the garden may
not have any explicit value on the market, it is hard to imagine a
farmer who cannot muster any market income from her [sic] other
assets." But this is not exactly cricket. I (Block, 1977, 1995,
2000) was engaged in abstracting from the real world in my attempt to
see if resource allocation is truly invariant to court decisions
regarding property rights in the zero transactions cost world. The issue
of "other income" or "realism" simply does not arise
in that context. The world of zero transactions costs is, par
excellence, an abstraction from reality. In order to provide a reductio
ad absurdum, as I was attempting to do with regard to Coase and Demsetz,
one must, perforce, accept the premises of the model. This is precisely
the exercise I was engaged in. for Brooks to come along and object to
the lack of realism is to drop the Coasean context I was adopting,
arguendo.
Let me take another crack at this. Consider case A, where the
manufacturer bribes the farmer who just won the court case into allowing
him to pollute, despite the court decision to the contrary. The
assumption here is that the manufacturer finances his bribe of $90 out
of the cost savings of not being required to install the SPD, with a
price tag of $100. "Other income" simply does not enter into
the picture. It is this model that I was attempting to address, that I
was required to address if I wanted to launch a reductio.
One mistake, perhaps, I made with Demsetz was in not trying to say
the same thing in many, many different ways. Let me not make the same
error, now, with Brooks. Accordingly, I now attempt to make this point
using alternative verbiage. Brooks asks, how can the farmer not finance
the bribe with these additional funds, given that he gains so much
psychic income from the possession of the flower pot? There must be some
other wealth available to the farmer; how else does he (14) eat, sleep,
breath, continue to live? This, it might be thought, is a reasonable
position to take. However, it lies completely outside of the logic of
the debate Demsetz and I have entered into, if only for the purposes of
discussion. Here, the means through which the bribe is to take place
stems from the benefits to be derived by the loser in the court case,
not "other income." My point is that if these benefits are
merely psychic, not objective, then they cannot finance any
rearrangements of resource allocation. Demsetz thinks I confuse this
with an income effect. But other income on the part of the farmer never
arose in our deliberations because it lies entirely outside of the scope
of the Coasean model. For Brooks to raise it in this context constitutes
a category mistake. It is as if two people were debating the merits of
cars, and a third party interjects that a motorcycle, or better yet a
sailboat, is preferable to either. Well, it may well be so; but this
point lies out of the realm of the debate over rival automobiles.
However, I am grateful to Brooks (2007, p. 228, n. 5) for
strengthening my argument against Demsetz by noting that for it to work
I need not assume zero wealth on the part of the farmer. I could do
this, instead, by "allowing the farmer's market income to be
anything less than [Y.sub.3] - [Y.sub.0]." I regard this as a real
contribution of Brooks'.
5. Speaking of this way of putting the matter, Brooks (2007) places
great reliance on indifference curve analysis. When I was young and
foolish, I, too, resorted to this sort of thinking (Block, 1995, 2000).
But, in my dotage, I have finally achieved wisdom on this subject. I now
see this tool of mainstream economic analysis as a snare and a delusion.
There is no room in proper economics for "indifference." (15)
Human action requires preferring, and setting aside. So, I leave that
part of Brooks' paper for others to analyze.
6. Brooks (2007, p. 229) attempts to "clarify" my and
Demsetz's position. He states: "As I wish to focus the
discussion, at least for the moment on the implications of
Demsetz's discussion, I sidestep Block's argument and assume
the factory owner will accept as payment the farmer's psychic
income."
I find this troubling. Let me say loud and clear, I am as willing
as the next person to accept posits for argument's sake; I am a
keen devotee of the arguendo ploy. I stand second to no man in my
appreciation for contrary-to-fact conditionals. However, moderate that I
am on this issue as well as on all others, this goes too far. The whole
point of psychic income is that by its very essence it cannot be used to
pay other people. Psychic income is the sort of income that of necessity
can only be enjoyed by its owner, not by anyone else. Thus,
contemplating the farmer bribing the manufacturer by giving him some of
the former's psychic income is no less than a logical howler. It is
as if someone were to attempt to draw a veritable square circle, and, to
add insult to injury, put it up for sale.
It is on the basis of this sort of "analysis" that Brooks
(2007, p. 229) is able to conclude,
Cast in these terms Demsetz appears to be correct in claiming that
Block's argument is nothing more than a playing through of the
income effects: Although the final allocations differ across the two
scenarios, the two different social outcomes are socially efficient. And
psychic income effects can be easily incorporated into the analysis and
appear as the difference between the budget constraints B2 and B1.
My response? "Appears to be correct," nothing. Why so
modest? Under these assumptions, Demsetz is indeed entirely correct, and
I am totally in the wrong. The zero transactions cost Coasean theorem is
without flaw, at least it has none I am able to discern. But this
devastating knockout blow of my contribution to this debate comes at the
cost of denying my very criticism. I have said before and I now say
again, if the income of the "farmer" consists of no more than
his psychic income, which by the very nature of things cannot be used to
finance a bribe in case B, then the simple Coase theorem is wrong, and
subject to my criticisms of it. However, if we accept the square circle
type notion that subjective enjoyment of one person can be given to
another in the form of payment, (16) then of course Coase, Demsetz and
Brook are in the right, and I am in the wrong. It is as if I am arguing
with someone over simple mathematics. I claim 2 + 2 = 4. The other
person defines 2 as equal to 3. Then, of course I am wrong. The correct
statement is then 2 + 2 = 6. The statement (Brooks, 2007) "The
maximum amount of psychic income that the farmer is willing to pay, to
avoid the loss in utility from the destruction of the flower
garden..." is a non sequitur. Much more sensible is Brooks'
(2007, p. 230) view "In the absence of cold hard cash the factory
owner will not install the equipment and the garden will wither and
die." And, as can be imagined, I am in entire accord with
Brooks' (2007, p. 231) declaration that "Block is entirely
correct in mounting his claim that Coase's argument falters when
the lack of wealth intrudes on the ability to bargain in the market for
property rights." However, left unsaid is how someone can
"bargain in the market for property rights" in the absence of
"cold hard cash," when one has only psychic income.
7. I now arrive at what I consider Brooks' (2007, p. 231) best
contribution. It is so good that I take the liberty of quoting it in
full:
It is perhaps instructive to ask how the opponents in the debate
may have been misled in their handling of the(ir) analysis....
There is a long and valid tradition in demand and supply analysis
that, in the absence of any marginal external effects, it is not
efficient to allocate resources to those individuals whose demand
lies to the right of the market equilibrium quantity. Over such
quantities the amount individuals would pay for the goods at the
margin is less than what it would cost the collectivity to produce
and provide them. It is worth reminding ourselves that a demand
curve is, of course, an instantiation of willingness to pay that is
backed by purchasing power. The marrying of willingness and ability
to pay is so ingrained in the language of economics that one often
hears statements just about willingness to pay--it being understood
that that expression of desire is synonymous with how much the
individual is able to pay. In doing so economics is the discipline
that marries the passions and preferences of individuals--the world
of philosophy--with the limits of just what is feasible--the stuff
of engineering and science. Seen in this light it is perhaps not
surprising that Demsetz would respond that Block's psychic income
case was nothing more than an income effect and did not represent a
new challenge to the Coasian [sic] position at least in its weak
guise. If the farmer did not have enough effective purchasing power
to convince the factory owner to install the pollution equipment,
then just as individuals with demand to the right of the
equilibrium quantity should not receive goods, the farmer should
not receive the right to acquire a garden.
But the important policy lesson underlying Block's argument is that
it can be a meaningful exercise to decouple willingness to pay from
ability to pay....
I concur enthusiastically. This is a far better explanation of
Demsetz's unwillingness or inability to see my point than the one I
had long entertained: intellectual arrogance. I am very grateful to
Brooks for enabling me to see this matter so clearly, at long last.
CONCLUSION
According to Brooks (2007, p. 232): "The reality is that when
the farmer has a garden but no pecuniary income to protect that garden
then the actual use value of the garden will be destroyed when the
property right is assigned to the factory owner." This is as good
as a summary of my entire contribution to my debate with Demsetz. Brooks
agrees. I thank him for this support.
Of the two Coase theorems, the one dealing with the zero
transactions cost world, and the one addressed to the real world, the
latter is by far of greater importance. But the former, too, offers
great interest to the economist. Demsetz and I have strived mightily to
determine whether this one is correct or not. The present paper has
examined Brooks' contribution to this literature. My claim is that
there is nothing in my previous contribution to it that has to be
revised because of this new entry. I continue to maintain that when
psychic income is taken into account, it by no means logically follows
that in the made up world of zero transactions costs, the judicial
decision will not determine resource allocation. It will, and not
because I have failed to take into account the income effects mentioned
by Coase, a la Demsetz. Nor, even, because I have not utilized
comparative statics, as claimed by Brooks.
REFERENCES
Block, Walter. 1977. "Coase and Demsetz on Private Property
Rights," The Journal of Libertarian Studies: An Interdisciplinary
Review 1, no. 2: 111-115.
--. 1995. "Ethics, Efficiency, Coasean Property Rights and
Psychic Income: A Reply to Demsetz," Review of Austrian Economics
8, no. 2: 61-125.
--. 1996. "O.J.'s Defense: A Reductio Ad Absurdum of the
Economics of Ronald Coase and Richard Posner," European Journal of
Law and Economics 3: 265-286.
--. 1999. "Austrian Theorizing, Recalling the Foundations:
Reply to Caplan," Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics 2, no. 4:
21-39.
--. 2000. "Private Property Rights, Erroneous Interpretations,
Morality and Economics: Reply to Demsetz," Quarterly Journal of
Austrian Economics 3, no. 1: 63-78.
--. 2003a. "Private Property Rights, Economic Freedom, and
Professor Coase: A Critique of Friedman, McCloskey, Medema and
Zorn," Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy 26, no. 3: 923-951.
--. 2003b. "Realism: Austrian vs. Neoclassical Economics,
Reply to Caplan," Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics 6, no. 3:
63-76.
--. 2005. "Rejoinder to Caplan on Bayesian Economics,"
Journal of Libertarian Studies 19, no. 1: 79-95.
--. 2006. "Coase and Kelo: Ominous Parallels and Reply to Lott
on Rothbard on Coase," Whittier Law Review 27, no. 4: 997-1022.
--. 2007. "Reply to Caplan on Austrian Economic
Methodology," Corporate Ownership & Control 4, no. 2: 312-325.
Block, Walter, William Barnett II and Gene Callahan. 2005.
"The Paradox of Coase as a Defender of Free Markets," NYU Journal of Law & Liberty 1, no. 3: 1075-1095.
Block, Walter, Christopher Westley and Alex Padilla. Forthcoming.
"Internal vs. External Explanations: A New Perspective on the
History of Economic Thought," Procesos De Mercado: Revista Europea
De Economia Politica.
Brooks, Michael. 2007. "Toward a Clarification of the
Block-Demsetz Debate on Psychic Income and Externalities."
Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics 10, no. 3: 223-233.
Caplan, Bryan. 1999. "The Austrian Search for Realistic
Foundations," Southern Economic Journal 65, no. 4: 823-838.
--. 2001. "Probability, Common Sense, and Realism: A Reply to
Hulsmann and Block," Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics 4, no.
2: 69-86.
--. 2003. "Probability and the Synthetic A Priori: A Reply to
Block," Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics 6, no. 3: 77-83.
Cordato, Roy E. 1989. "Subjective Value, Time Passage, and the
Economics of Harmful Effects," Hamline Law Review 12, no. 2:
229-244.
--. 1992a. "Knowledge Problems and the Problem of Social
Cost," Journal of the History of Economic Thought 14, no. 2:
209-224.
--. 1992b. Welfare Economics and Externalities in an Open-Ended
Universe: A Modern Austrian Perspective, Boston: Kluwer.
Demsetz, Harold. 1979. "Ethics and Efficiency in Property
Rights Systems" In Mario Rizzo, ed., Time, Uncertainty and
Disequilibrium: Explorations of Austrian Themes. Lexington Mass.: D.C.
Heath and Co.
--. 1997. "Block's Erroneous Interpretations,"
Review of Austrian Economics 10, no. 2: 101-109.
Fox, Glenn. 2007. "The Real Coase Theorems," Cato Journal 27, no. 3: 373-396.
Gelernter, David. 2008. "Feminism and the English
Language," The Weekly Standard 13, no. 24.
Hoppe, Hans-Hermann. 1993. The Economics and Ethics of Private
Property: Studies in Political Economy and Philosophy. Boston: Kluwer.
--. 2005. "Must Austrians Embrace Indifference?"
Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics 8, no. 4: 87-91.
Hulsmann, Jorg Guido. 1999. "Economic Science and
Neoclassicism," Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics 2, no. 4:
1-20.
Krecke, Elisabeth. 1996. "Law and the Market Order: An
Austrian Critique of the Economic Analysis of Law," Journal des
Economistes et des Etudes Humaines 7, no. 1: 19-37. In Robert W. McGee,
ed., Commentaries on Law & Economics, 1997 Yearbook.
Laidler, David. 2003. "The Price Level, Relative Prices, and
Economic Stability: Aspects of the Interwar Debate." Working paper,
available at http://www.bis.org/publ/work136.pdf.
Levin, Michael. 1984. "Comparable Worth: The Feminist Road to
Socialism," Commentary, September.
--. 1987. Feminism and Freedom. New York: Transaction Books.
North, Gary. 1990. Tools of Dominion: The Case Laws of Exodus.
Tyler, Tex.: Institute for Christian Economics.
--. 1992. The Coase Theorem, Tyler, Tex.: The Institute for
Christian Economics.
--. 2002. "Undermining Property Rights: Coase and
Becker," The Journal of Libertarian Studies: An Interdisciplinary
Review 16, no. 4: 75-100.
Rosen, Sherwin. 1997. "Austrian and Neoclassical Economics:
Any Gains from Trade?" Journal of Economic Perspectives 11, no. 4:
139-152.
Rothbard, Murray N. 1982. "Law, Property Rights, and Air
Pollution," Cato Journal 2, no. 1. Reprinted in Walter Block, ed.,
Economics and the Environment: A Reconciliation. Vancouver: The Fraser
Institute, 1990.
Stringham, Edward. 2001. "Kaldor-Hicks Efficiency and the
Problem of Central Planning," Quarterly Journal of Austrian
Economics 4, no. 2: 41-50.
(1) For an explication of this issue, see Fox (2007).
(2) In my view, both the zero and the very high transactions costs
scenarios are aspects of the Coase theorem. However, I acknowledge that
the second, dealing with the real world of positive transactions costs,
as opposed to the hypothetical case of zero transactions costs, is by
far the most important of the two. Demsetz and I disagreed on both of
these Coase theorems. But, since Brooks only comments on the former, I
will confine my remarks to that one scenario.
(3) I was tempted to say that there was a property rights violator,
the polluting manufacturer, who victimized the farmer with his
trespassing smoke particles. But this would be very much out of keeping
with the Coase-Demsetz ethos. For them, who is the rights violator, and
who is the victim, depends totally not on property rights as conceived
of by libertarians (Rothbard, 1982; Hoppe, 1993), but rather on the
basis of a calculation of whether GDP will be raised or lowered
depending upon which side is supported by the court. That is, these
representatives of Chicago School law and economics do not accept
private property rights at all.
(4) In Table II we indicate whether or not resources are allocated
to the SPD, and whether or not a bribe takes place, in the cases A, B, C
and D.
(5) Or "pet" rock.
(6) In the extreme, we can suppose that the "farmer"
would not accept any amount of money for his holdings, even an infinite
sum.
(7) As I see matters, the relatively more important Coase theorem
pertains to the real world case of high transactions costs, where the
author advises the judge to rule in favor of the party who, in the zero
transactions costs world, would have determined resource allocation. I
see this as a horrid public policy recommendation, subject to all sorts
of weird reductios ad absurdum. See on this Block, 1977, 1995, 1996,
2000, 2003a, 2006; Block, Barnett and Callahan, 2005; Cordato, 1989,
1992a, 1992b; Fox, 2007; Krecke, 1996; North, 1990, 1992, 2002;
Rothbard, 1982, 1990; Stringham, 2001.
(8) "Papabile" refers to one of the cardinals of the
Catholic Church who has a reasonable chance of becoming the next pope.
In like manner, "Nobelabile" refers to an economist with a
plausible probability of being awarded the next year's Nobel Prize
in economics.
(9) Hey, I was the one who started this entire line of discourse
(Block, 1977). There was no "her" involved at all, throughout
this entire debate, until Brooks (2007). Rather, there were two males:
the polluter and the pollutee. From whence sprang this feminization? On
this see Gelernter (2008).
(10) See on this
http://www.googlesyndicatedsearch.com/u/Mises?hl=en&submit.
x=0&submit.y=0&q=Marshallian%20scissors
(11) Who says Austrian economists can't do math?
(12) Indeed, it is a rarity that many of them even read much of
Austrian output. And, when they do, it is usually in a condescending
manner. See on this Rosen, 1997; Laidler, 2003. For a more general
commentary on mainstream economists' reaction to praxeological
economics, see Block, Westley and Padilla, forthcoming.
(13) Brooks, 2007, p. 227, n. 4, attributes these words to
"(Block 2000, p. 69)," but my words there are not exactly the
same as he attributes to me. He really should be more careful. Quotation
marks are supposed to indicate exact words.
(14) Brooks would say here, instead, "she." But I see no
justification for catering to the whims of Marxist feminists. See on
this Levin, 1984, 1987. I am surprised to see this sort of thing in the
pages of the Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics.
(15) See on this Block, 1999, 2003b, 2005, 2007; Caplan, 1999,
2001, 2003; Hoppe, 2005; Hulsmann, 1999.
(16) There is of course a poetic sense in which the manufacturer
can be paid off via the psychic income of the "farmer": if the
former enjoys the enjoyment of the latter. Or, to put this in
neoclassical terms that would be appreciated by Coase, Demsetz and
Brooks, if the psychic enjoyment of the "farmer" enters into
the utility function of the manufacturer, in a positive direction. But
this has nothing to do with my criticism of the zero transactions cost
Coase theorem, nor with my long running debate with Demsetz. There, the
bribe of payment consisted of something of objective value, namely
money.
Dr. Walter Block (wblock@loyno.edu) is Harold E. Wirth Eminent
Scholar Endowed Chair and Professor of Economics at the Joseph A. Butt,
S.J. College of Business, Loyola University, New Orleans.
Table I
A Farmer Manufacturer
Value $75 $100
Bribe Yes ($90 from M to F)
SPD Used? No
Wealth Analysis -675 $100
+$90 -90
$15 +10
B Farmer Manufacturer
Value $100 $75
Bribe Yes ($90 from F to M)
SPD Used? Yes
Wealth Analysis $100 $90
-$90 -$75
$10 $15
C Farmer Manufacturer
Value -$75 $100
Bribe No
SPD Used? No
Wealth Analysis -$75 $100
Both F+M $100-$75 = $25
D Farmer Manufacturer
Value $100 $75
Bribe No
SPD Used? Yes No
Wealth Analysis $100 -$75
Both F+M $100-$75 = $25
Table II
SPD Gets Used?
Yes No
Bribe Occurs? Yes B A
No D C