UK real national income, 1950-1998: some grounds for optimism.
Crafts, Nicholas
It has been claimed using the concept of the Index of Sustainable
Economic Welfare (ISEW) that there has been an absolute decline in
sustainable living standards in the UK since the mid-1970s. Revisions to
ISEW are proposed to make it more nearly a measure of utility-based real
national income. In particular, ISEW should be revised to take account
of much-improved life expectancy. Implementing any of the suggested
revisions reverses the finding of absolute decline while implementing
all of them results in a growth rate higher than that of real GDP per
head in the national accounts.
Introduction
Many of those interested in sustainable growth have taken a very
pessimistic view of recent UK experience. Douthwaite (1993, P. 3) states
that "economic growth has made life considerably worse for people
in Britain since 1955" and a widely quoted recent estimate has
claimed that for the past quarter century or so the Index of Sustainable
Economic Welfare (ISEW) has been in absolute decline in the UK (Jackson
et al., 1997). By contrast, economic growth as measured by the UK
national income accounts has been maintained throughout the postwar
period at a steady if not spectacular rate with an average growth rate
of real GDP/head at 2.5 per cent per year from 1950-73 and 1.8 per cent
per year from 1973 to 1998 (Maddison, 2001).
GDP is certainly not an adequate estimate of the level of
sustainable economic welfare but this also applies to the ISEW
adjustments to the national accounts, as critics have been quick to
point out. ISEW has a number of features which make it unacceptable. In
particular, the allowances that are made for environmental damage and
depletion of natural capital lack a sound theoretical foundation,
multiple-count the costs of climate change and exaggerate the value of
reductions in energy reserves, while the adjustments made for changes to
the distribution of income are not justified if the aim is to measure
the economy's productive potential in terms of ability to provide
future welfare (Neumayer, 1999).
The standard national accounts measure of national income is net
national product (NNP). The rationale for this was set out by Hicks (1939) as the maximum amount which can be consumed while maintaining the
capital stock intact. (1) Thus, investment expenditures to make good
depreciation are subtracted from GNP and national income is equal to
consumption plus net capital accumulation. In general, however, this is
not a measure of sustainable consumption. The most obvious reason for
this is that the national accounts only consider depreciation of
physical capital whereas a more general measure would need to include
depletion of natural resources and human capital. In a growing economy,
NNP per person needs still more refinement to reflect sustainable
consumption. On the one hand, more of gross product needs to be set
aside to maintain capital per head in the face of growing population. On
the other hand, technological progress permits consumption to be
sustained with somewhat lower capital per person.
But even with these refinements we do not have a measure of real
national income in terms of sustainable living standards; as Nordhaus
(2000) points out, for that income must be defined in utility terms.
Utility-based national income is the maximum amount that a nation can
consume while ensuring that members of all future generations can have
lifetime utility (be on an indifference curve) at least as high as that
of the current generation. It is clearly a net income concept in the
sense that the productive potential of the economy per person has to be
maintained by setting aside sufficient saving to permit utility levels
to be sustained in the face of capital depreciation, demographic
pressure and environmental damage. But Nordhaus (2000) also emphasizes
that it should also take account of life expectancy. The key point is
that the same annual NNP per person with long life should be recognised
as a higher living standard than that income with a short life.
This also implies that a particularly important omission from ISEW
is the improvement over time in life expectancy. This is very
unfortunate because the evidence suggests that people greatly value
reductions in risks of mortality and also because one of the most
dramatic achievements of the twentieth century was the rise in life
expectancy at birth to almost 80 years from a level about half that in
1870. As Eisner (1994, p. 105) remarked in his critique of the ISEW
methodology: "I do not share ISEW's reluctance to put a value
on human life; indeed, I should think it vital in any measure of
welfare".
This paper provides a revision of the ISEW estimates for the UK
undertaken with a view to making them more nearly approximate a
utility-based real national income measure. The next section explores
several revisions to the estimate of ISEW. These include removing the
adjustment for inequality, allowing for technological progress in
estimating sustainable consumption, eliminating the multiple-counting of
environmental damage, and assuming that the replacement cost of primary
energy consumption is constant rather than increasing steadily over
time. The growth rate for ISEW is computed for each of these variants
singly and also for all four revisions. The third section sets out the
evidence on improvements in life expectancy and the increase in lifetime
consumption possibilities. It goes on to consider the impact of an
imputation for improvements in life expectancy on the growth of
augmented real national income and of ISEW These imputations are based
on a methodology proposed by Nordhaus (1998) which is explain ed in the
appendix. Finally, the fourth section concludes that the claim that
sustainable economic welfare has been declining since the mid-1970s is
simply not plausible.
ISEW revisited
In this section of the paper the definition of ISEW is reviewed and
criticisms are presented of the implementation of the concept. Revisions
are suggested to the ISEW methodology with a view to making it a better
approximation of utility-based real national income but, at this stage,
no adjustment is made for longer life expectancy. The empirical impact
of the proposed changes is set out so as to highlight the sensitivity of
ISEW to each of them.
The Index of Sustainable Economic Welfare (ISEW) is defined as
follows:
Personal consumption - losses from unequal distribution + domestic
labour services + non-defensive public expenditures + net capital growth
- defensive private expenditures - costs of environmental degradation -
depreciation of natural capital.
Table 1 reports a summary of the main elements of ISEW per person
for the UK on a consolidated basis for benchmark dates marking the
so-called 'Golden Age' in the early postwar period and the
subsequent period of slower growth. Components are signed according to whether they add to or subtract from ISEW. Row (1) is not part of the
total since personal consumption enters only after an adjustment for
inequality. The outstanding feature of table 1 is not a dramatic
slowdown in personal consumption growth after 1973 but rather that the
negative components become much larger. Included among these is the
impact of greater inequality of income in more recent years.
ISEW adjusts personal consumption to allow for its unequal
distribution using the Atkinson index which is defined as the equally
distributed income that would have delivered as much utility as the
actual total (inegalitarian) income. In this approach a parameter is
subjectively assigned to reflect the proposition that income is less
valuable to the well off. (2) This has many precedents in the context of
how policymakers of a particular degree of inequality aversion might
look at actual economic outcomes in terms of contemplating trade-offs
between equity and efficiency (Crafts, 1993). Nevertheless, in this
context, it confuses a dislike for growth which actually has favoured
higher income deciles with the potential to sustain consumption for all.
The ISEW inequality adjustment is not warranted in terms of the
definition of utility-based national income since the distribution of
income per se does not directly impact on the capacity for future
consumption (Neumayer, 1999).
The net capital adjustment is to allow for demographic growth by
only counting as net investment, and thus part of maximal consumption,
investment over and above that needed to maintain capital per head. This
is also consistent with utility-based national income but the
calculation is incomplete because it fails also to take account of
technological progress and thus exaggerates the amount of consumption
that needs to be foregone now to maintain future consumption standards.
ISEW has some similarities to utility-based national income in that
it starts from personal consumption measured in terms of the value
consumers assign to goods and services. It adds to this the value of
non-market work and some public spending on education and health.
However, a substantial part of public expenditure (for example, on law
and order and military activity) is seen as 'defensive', i.e.,
inputs into producing income that should not be regarded as final
consumption, and are therefore not included in ISEW, although part of
conventional GDP. Similarly, some private expenditures, for example
costs of commuting, are deducted from personal consumption as
'defensive'. In principle, leaving aside issues of
implementation, this all makes sense in terms of a utility-based
national income concept.
However, the notion that (an arbitrary fraction of) public
expenditure on education and health should be added in as
'non-defensive' is a highly imperfect way of taking account of
the value that this has to consumers. It would be much more appropriate
to incorporate the value that consumers place on the results of these
expenditures -- such as the consumption equivalent of the life
expectancy gains that they deliver. Not only is this undoubtedly a large
number but such an approach is already part of government policymaking if not national accounting. Thus, in the analysis of road-building
schemes the Department of Transport values an expected death averted at
about [pounds sterling]0.8 million and a working group at the Department
of Health (1999) proposed a value of [pounds sterling]2 million for a
death averted by reduction of air pollution risks.
Broadening of depreciation to include damage to the environment and
losses of natural capital is, of course, an essential ingredient in
addressing the deficiencies of traditional national accounts and moving
towards utility-based national income. Unfortunately, the methods
adopted by Jackson et al. (1997) are seriously flawed. Neumayer (2000)
notes that the correct way to value the environmental damage of a tonne
of carbon emissions is at marginal social cost which the ISEW
calculation quite reasonably takes to have been [pounds sterling]11.4 at
1990 prices in 1990. But then this amount is set aside not only in the
year of emission but in each subsequent year as well because the damage
is allowed to accumulate over time; as Neumayer points out this
procedure entails multiple-counting of the costs and is tantamount to
assuming an extraordinarily high present value of damage from emissions.
The depletion of non-renewable resources is also estimated
inappropriately. The concept employed is to estimate the replacement
costs of primary energy consumption. It might be argued that, in terms
of utility-based national income, a preferable approach would be to
calculate what proportion of the resource rents obtained from extraction
needs to be reinvested to sustain consumption when the non-renewables
are exhausted. This would clearly be a very small number relative to UK
GDP in any of our benchmark years (Vaze, 1996). Even if the replacement
cost approach is favoured, however, the implementation by Jackson et al.
(1997) is not acceptable because it uses a high value of a barrel of oil
equivalent ($75 in 1988) and assumes that costs are rising steadily at 3
per cent per year. As Neumayer (2000) points out, the life expectancy of
proven reserves of non-renewable energy sources is long, solar energy is
the obvious replacement and its costs can be expected to fall over time
as technology advances.
The remainder of this section examines the implications of revising
four of the objectionable components of ISEW identified above, namely,
the inequality adjustment, the net capital formation estimate, the
long-term environmental damage estimate, and the replacement costs
assumed for consumption of non-renewable energy resources. A revised
ISEW is presented in table 2, in which each of these components has been
amended.
Table 3 reports the rate of growth of the revised ISEW per person
together with the rate of growth that would result if each of these
amendments was carried out separately.
The first row of table 2 simply removes the inequality adjustment
and enters personal consumption from the national accounts unaltered.
When this is done, the consumption figure for 1998 increases
considerably more than that for 1973. As table 3 shows, on its own this
is sufficient to render the growth rate of ISEW per person positive in
the 1973-98 period, albeit at a small number. This may seem a
surprisingly large impact but, as has been widely remarked, UK income
inequality rose dramatically in the late twentieth century (Atkinson,
1999).
The second amendment in table 2 in row (4) incorporates an
adjustment for technological progress into the net capital formation
estimate. Ex post, the extent to which output has increased independent
of growth in factor inputs can be approximated by the measurement of
total factor productivity growth (TFP) in a growth accounting
methodology. Estimates for the UK since 1950 can be found in Crafts and
O'Mahony (2001); these show that TFP growth was close to 1.25 per
cent per year in both the pre- and post-1973 periods. How much the
capital accumulation requirement is alleviated by this productivity
improvement depends on the elasticity of output with respect to capital
stock growth. Estimates for the UK suggest that this is about 0.3
(Oulton and Young, 1996), i.e., if 3 per cent more output per year is to
be obtained the capital stock has to rise by 10 per cent.
Based on the estimates of depreciation of physical capital in
O'Mahony (1999) and of the net capital stock in the national income
accounts, the situation would have been as follows in 1998. With a
capital stock of about 3.2 times GDP and a depreciation rate of 6.3 per
cent about 20 per cent of GDP would need to be invested. With trend TFP
growth of 1.25 per cent and an output to capital elasticity of 0.3,
however, the capital stock can fall by about 4.2 per cent without
reducing sustainable consumption. Thus the reinvestment requirement is
only 2.1 per cent of the capital stock or about 6.7 per cent of GDP.
When allowance is made for population growth at the 1973-98 rate of 0.2
per cent per year, this translates into a permissible fall of 3.5 per
cent in the capital stock and an investment requirement of 9.0 per cent
of GDP. Thus, since in 1998 18.64 per cent of GDP was invested, an extra
9.64 per cent could have been consumed on a sustainable basis.
Similar calculations were made for 1950 and 1973, in each case
taking the previous period as a guide to reinvestment needs. For 1973
TFP growth was taken to equal that of 1950-73 and for 1950, the interwar
period of 1924-37, as defined by Matthews et al. (1983), was used. When
these revised estimates of net capital accumulation over and above the
amount needed to sustain consumption are added to ISEW in row (3) of
table 3, once again this amendment on its own is enough to place
post-1973 growth performance in a very different light. The original
estimate of -0.6 per cent per year goes to +0.8 per cent.
Two revisions to the ISEW environmental damage estimates have been
made in row (6) of table 2. First, damage is valued at marginal social
cost in the year of the emissions and the damage no longer accumulates
as in Jackson et al. (1997) and, second, marginal social cost is assumed
to increase over time at 2 per cent per year throughout the postwar
period, as in Neumayer (2000). The data for emissions are retained as in
the original ISEW. The outcome is a much lower deduction for pollution
and environmental damage in row (6) of table 2 for 1973 and, especially
for 1998, than in the corresponding entry in table 1. Row (4) of table 3
shows that this boosts the growth rate quite considerably in both
periods. It also underlines Neumayer's finding that assuming a
steadily rising marginal social cost of environmental damage is not
sufficient to generate a declining ISEW from the 1970s.
Finally, in row (7) of table 2 a more modest, constant replacement
cost for non-renewable energy sources has been assumed in the light of
the long lifetime of energy reserves and the prospect in time of
economical solar energy. An alternative would be to make adjustments in
line with the user cost method of El Serafy (1989) but the data for such
calculations does not exist for the whole postwar period. In any event,
it is clear that once the escalation factor in the replacement cost
calculation made by Jackson et a!. (1997) is removed the increasingly
large deductions for this item over time evaporate since consumption of
primary energy from non-renewables in terms of millions of tonnes of oil
equivalent fell from 212.7 in 1973 to 203.2 in 1998 (DTI, 2001). Row (S)
of table 3 shows that this revision on its own is also capable of
raising the growth rate of ISEW per person significantly in both periods
and once again the finding of negative growth post-1973 disappears.
Two main messages arise from this exercise. First, as has been
noted along the way, making any one of these revisions removes the
finding of declining sustainable economic welfare since the mid-1970s.
Given that there is a strong case for making all these revisions, this
suggests that the original declinist claims are completely lacking in
robustness. Second, if all these revisions are implemented, then, as
table 3 shows, the end result is that ISEW per person grows faster
throughout than real GDP per person. The estimates of 2.8 per cent per
year in 1950-73 and 2.3 per cent per year in 1973-98 in row (6) of table
3 compare with 2.5 per cent and 1.8 per cent for real GDP per person in
the same periods.
Incorporating improved life expectancy into national income
Table 4 reports estimates of life expectancy for the benchmark
years 1950, 1973 and 1998. The most commonly used measure is life
expectancy at birth which rose by more than eight years for both genders
over the whole period. It is also of interest, however, to consider the
average life expectancy of the population (which reflects its age
structure) as it is relevant to the expected future consumption of those
currently alive. (3) This rose by somewhat less than life expectancy at
birth. Nevertheless, between 1950 and 1998 this increased by between
14.5 and 21.7 per cent depending on which year is chosen as the base for
age-weighting. (4)
It was pointed out earlier that ISEW fails to take account of the
high value that people place on the reductions in mortality risks which
have been very important achievements of government health expenditure
as well as private initiative. This section illustrates how this
omission might be rectified both in principle and in practice.
A device familiar from elementary microeconomics, namely the
indifference curve diagram, can be used to illustrate the basic idea of
incorporating life expectancy into measures of living standards. The
representative person whose preferences are mapped in chart 1 is assumed
to regard both longer life and income as goods.
Each indifference curve maps combinations of life expectancy and
income which are regarded as equally preferable; a move to a higher
indifference curve represents a rise in standard of living. A person is
observed initially at point A on curve [U.sub.1] and subsequently at
point B on [U.sub.2]. Income as conventionally measured has risen from
[Y.sub.1] to [Y.sub.2]. However, to maintain a [U.sub.2] living standard
with the original life expectancy requires an income of [Y.sup.*.sub.2].
Thus, the gain from longer life is equivalent to an income gain of
([Y.sup.*.sub.2]-[Y.sub.2]) and the gain in real income is
([Y.sup.*.sub.2]-[Y.sub.1]) rather than ([Y.sub.1] - [Y.sub.1]).
Confining our attention to money income, as would be the approach of the
national income accounts, would omit part of the welfare gain. This
approach would measure the increased income from longer life expectancy
by the consumption-equivalent of the greater longevity, as in chart 1.
Nordhaus (1998) set out a method of operationalising an estimate of
growth of utility-based national income that takes account of mortality
risks. This values improvements in life expectancy by taking the change
in the population-weighted average of age-specific mortality rates
multiplied by the estimated value of a death averted. This can either be
taken as constant at all ages or, probably more appropriately,
age-weighted. The formal basis of this is given in the appendix.
The starting point here is to review estimates of the 'value
of a statistical life', the term used in British policymaking
circles for the value of a death averted. This is defined as the total
price that the population is willing to pay to reduce its expected death
toll by one.
Thus if 60 million people are each willing to pay 1.667 pence for a
public health improvement that saves one life, the value of a
statistical life is [pounds sterling]1 million. 1.667 pence is then the
value placed by the average person on this reduction of the mortality
rate by 1 per 60 million.
A recent survey of the international evidence on the value of a
statistical life concluded that a good rule of thumb is that it is
around 120 times GDP per person. For the UK the best guess was a
multiple of 132 times per capita GDP with a range from 101 to 154
(Miller, 2000). The same survey found that results of studies for
countries at a wide range of income levels over the recent past appear
to be consistent with an income elasticity for this value of about 1 or
slightly less. The best guess proposed by Miller (2000) is about twice
the value adopted by the Department of Transport in 1988 for the cost
benefit analysis of road schemes and subsequently increased in line with
growth of real GDP per person. It is, however, consistent with the
review of the evidence in Jones-Lee (1989) and the suggestion in a
recent government report that for involuntary risks (such as those
resulting from air pollution) an appropriate value might be two or three
times higher than that used for road deaths averted (Department o f
Health, 1999).
The best guess of a multiple of 132 times GDP/person would imply
the following calculation for the years 1950-98. As reported in table S
below, the population-weighted average reduction in the mortality rate
was 7229 per million persons and real GDP per person in 1998 at 1995
prices was [pounds sterling]13,055 (ONS, 1999; Maddison, 2001). The
value of a statistical life is taken to be (132 x [pounds
sterling]13,055) = [pounds sterling]1.72 million. The decline in
mortality in this period is then estimated to be worth 1.72 x 7229 =
[pounds sterling]12,434 per person.
There is some evidence that the value of a statistical life is not
constant across all ages but tends to be higher in the middle of the
life span than in infancy or old age. Murray (1996) suggests weights
with which to calculate an age-weighted value of a death averted; the
weighting is very similar to that proposed in Department of Health
(1999). For the years 1950-98, as reported in table 5, this would give
an age-weighted value of a statistical life of [pounds]1.15 million and
a decline in mortality worth 1.15 x 7229 = [pounds sterling]8313 per
person. The lower valuation reflects the relatively greater falls in
mortality for older age groups.
Table 6 reports the results of implementing the Nordhaus
methodology for measuring the contribution of gains in life expectancy
to the growth of real national income per person in the UK. It uses
calculations similar to those of table 5 to create 'best
guess' imputations for improved life expectancy to be added to
conventional real GDP per person growth in order to create a first
approximation to the growth rate of real utility-based national income
per person. The methodology is implemented separately for each period.
As noted above, there is a wide range of estimates of the value of a
statistical life. Based on the range of 101 to 154 times GDP per person
reported in Miller (2000), lower and upper bound estimates for the
estimates in column (5) would be 3.1 and 3.45 per cent per year for
1950-73 with 2.35 and 2.9 per cent for 1973-98. Clearly, the imputations
for lower mortality are quite sizeable.
In the first section it was argued that a major weakness of ISEW is
its failure to acknowledge the value of reduced mortality risks. This
omission can be addressed by incorporating into the revised ISEW of
table 3 the estimates of life expectancy gains already made in table 6.
At the same time, it is now clearly appropriate to remove from ISEW the
positive component assigned on the basis of public spending on education
and health. These expenditures can be regarded as inputs which may have
a payoff in raising life expectancy, or indeed, TFP but should not be
seen as final consumption goods valued on the basis of willingness to
pay.
As one would expect, inclusion of the gains from rising life
expectancy makes a substantial further difference to ISEW per person.
Compared with table 2, table 7 shows growth rising from 2.8 to 4.0 per
cent per year in 1950-73 and from 2.3 to 3.1 per cent per year in
1973-98. Once welfare gains from an improved mortality environment are
taken into account, the revised ISEW calculation suggests growth of real
GDP per person substantially underestimates rather than overestimates
growth of utility-based real national income per person.
The policy implications of these results are intriguing but
unclear. Much more needs to be discovered about the costs and benefits
of interventions that would potentially reduce mortality, cf. Department
of Health (1999). Nevertheless, the possibility that arises is that
rethinking our concept of national income in utility terms would lead to
a different view of the growth implications of alternative fiscal
strategies, for example, in terms of the choice between lower taxes and
higher public health expenditures.
Conclusions
Conventional national income accounts do not provide estimates of
sustainable economic welfare nor of utility-based national income. It is
important to recognise that there are biases that go in the direction of
under-estimation as well as over-estimation. Yet most critics seem to
have proposed adjustments that are intended to justify claims that
economic growth, at least in the recent past, is simply an illusion, an
artefact of the statistics.
The best known of these exercises for the UK is the ISEW proposed
by Jackson et al. (1997). Close examination of this index suggests that
the claim of declining sustainable economic welfare that its authors
make is not robust. Any one of several revisions justified in this paper
would remove this finding. If all the revisions suggested here are
adopted, the result would be that, throughout the postwar period, the
growth of real GDP per person in the UK turns out to be a considerable
under-estimate of utility-based real national income per head.
Further revisions to ISEW may well be desirable if it is to become
a closer approximation to utility-based national income, some of which
may well make for less optimistic conclusions. For example, rather than
simply deducting public expenditure on defence and law and order from
GDP it might be desirable to attempt an estimate of the consumption
equivalent utility losses from rising crime risks and personal
insecurity. Nevertheless, such further revisions will need to be
substantial if they are to rehabilitate the hypothesis that sustainable
economic welfare in the UK has declined in the recent past.
APPENDIX
An individual has a stream of expected income and faces a constant
real interest rate equal to the mortality adjusted rate of time
preference (p + [mu]) where [mu] is the set of mortality rates and the
survival function is exponential. This person chooses an annuity that
yields constant consumption, c = [c.sup.*], through his/her lifetime.
The value of this consumption stream is
V=u([c.sup.*])/([rho] + [mu]) (1)
so that the trade-off between consumption and mortality is
dV /d[c.sup.*] = u'([c.sup.*) /([rho] +[mu]) (2)
dV/d[mu] = u([c.sup.*] / [([rho] + [mu]).sup.2] (3)
[dc.sup.*]/du = -u([c.sup.*])/[u'([c.sup.*])([rho] + [mu])]
(4)
Normalising by setting u'([c.sup.*]) = 1, i.e., a unit of
utility is worth one extra unit of the consumption good, and by setting
the pure rate of time preference to zero gives
[dc.sup.*]/d[mu] = -u([c.sup.*])/[mu] (5)
This implies that a uniform change in mortality rates at every age
will produce a welfare change equal to the number of years of life times
the goods value of life.
The mortality approach in Nordhaus (1998) which is implemented in
this paper to obtain utility national income values improvements in life
expectancy by taking the change in the population weighted average of
age specific mortality rates multiplied by the estimated value of a
death averted, i.e., by using a generalisation of(S).
An alternative approach based on life-years is also set out in
Nordhaus (1998). The economic value of improved health is equal to the
population-weighted increase in life expectancy times the value of an
additional life-year. The main problem with this approach lies in
estimating the value of a life-year. There is no obvious way to do this
and any solution relies on strong assumptions. A simple way to proceed
is to suppose that the value of a statistical life applies to a male
aged 40 with no discounting. In 1998 this implies that the capital value
of [pounds sterling]1.72m is spread over 36.6 years (male life
expectancy at 40) implying a capital value of [pounds sterling]46,995
per life year which is equivalent to a flow of [pounds sterling]1284 per
year. The 1998 population-weighted increase of life expectancy of 7.8
years between 1950 and 1998 would be worth [pounds sterling]10,015,
somewhat smaller than the [pounds sterling]12,434 in table 5 using the
mortality approach. If, however, the discount rate is assumed to be
greater than zero, the value of a life-year might increase markedly, cf.
Nordhaus (1998).
Table 1
Components of ISEW ([pounds sterling] 1995 per person)
1950 1973 1998
Personal consumption 2960 4904 8246
Inequality adjusted consumption 2716 4524 7064
(+)
Household labour services 1153 1788 2755
(+)
Public health and education 108 233 439
(+)
Net capital 0 535 0
(+)
Consumption deductions 368 790 2054
(-)
Pollution & environmental damage 1022 1825 2908
(-)
Natural capital depreciation 445 1194 2447
(-)
Total 2142 3271 2849
Growth rate (% p.a.) 1.9 -0.6
Sources: derived from Jackson et al. (1997), see text. Consumption
deductions are the sum of their columns I, J, K, L and M; pollution &
environmental damage are the sum of their columns N, O, P, T and U;
natural capital depreciation is the sum of their columns Q, R and S.
1998 estimates extrapolated from 1996 estimates in original.
Table 2
A revision of ISEW ([pounds sterling]1995 per person)
1950 1973 1998
Personal consumption 2960 4904 8246
(+)
Household labour services 1153 1788 2755
(+)
Public health and education 108 233 439
(+)
Net capital 105 612 1259
(+)
Consumption deductions 368 790 2054
(-)
Pollution & environmental damage 675 757 547
(-)
Natural capital depreciation 420 590 572
(-)
Total 2863 5400 9526
Growth rate 2.8 2.3
Sources: see text. Rows (1)-(3) and (5) are as in table 1. The
assumptions for the net capital entry in row (4) are as follows: for
1950, expected population growth was assumed to be 0.3 per cent, TFP
growth 0.7 per cent, and the capital to GDP ratio was 1.8; for 1973,
expected population growth was 0.5 per cent, TFP growth 1.25 per cent,
and the capital to GDP ratio was 2.6. The pollution and environmental
damage entry in row (6) removes the cumulative component and assumes
marginal social costs of carbon emission were [pounds sterling]13.86 in
1990 and grew at 2 per cent per year from 1950-90. The natural capital
depreciation in row (7) uses a constant replacement cost per tonne of
oil equivalent non-renewable energy consumption of [pounds sterling]136;
it should be noted that the higher this constant figure is assumed to be
the higher is the growth rate of revised ISEW in each period.
Table 3
Growth rates of ISEW variants (% per year)
1950-73 1973-98
Original ISEW 1.9 -0.6
No inequality adjustment 1.9 0.4
Revised net capital 1.8 0.8
Revised environmental damage 2.4 0.8
Revised natural capital depreciation 2.6 0.8
All 4 revisions 2.8 2.3
Sources: derived from table 2.
Table 4
Years of life expectancy, 1950, 1973 and 1998
1950 1973 1998
At birth
Females 71.2 75.5 79.8
Males 66.2 69.2 74.9
Population average
1950 age structure 40.4 42.6 46.3
1973 age structure 39.9 43.0 45.7
1998 age structure 35.7 39.9 43.5
Average as ratio of 1950
1950 age structure 1.056 1.147
1973 age structure 1.077 1.145
1998 age structure 1.117 1.217
Sources: derived from Annual Abstract of Statistics, various issues.
Table 5
Value of decline in the mortality rate ([pounds sterling]1995)
Value of death
averted
([pounds sterling]1995m)
Fall in Un- Age-
death rate weighted weighted
1950-98 7229 1.72 1.15
Value of lower
mortality per person
([pounds sterling]1995)
Un- Age-
weighted weighted
1950-98 12434 8313
Sources: based on mortality approach of Nordhaus (1998) as described in
the text, col (4) = col (1) x col (2) and col (5) = col (1) x col (3).
The age -weights based on Murray (1996) in col (3) are as follows: 0-4:
0.3; 5-14: 1.0; 15-34: 1.5; 35-44: 1.3; 45-54: 1.1; 55-64: 1.0; 65-74:
0.7; 75-84: 0.5; 85 and over: 0.4. Montality rates and and population
weights from Mitchell (1988) for 1950 and ONS (2000) for 1988.
Table 6
Imputations for improved life expectancy in real national income
Real Mortality Adjusted Traditional Adjusted
GDP/head imputation GDP/head growth growth
([pounds sterling] (% p.a.) (% p.a.)
1995)
1950 4755
1973 8408 1606 10014 2.5 3.3
1998 13055 5587 18642 1.8 2.5
Sources: Derived using methodology and sources as in table 5, see text.
The mortality imputation uses age-weighted mortality gains.
Table 7
Incorporating mortality gains into revised ISEW, 1950, 1973 and 1998
1950 1973 1998
Revised ISEW 2863 5400 9526
(+)
Mortality imputation n/a 1606 5587
(+)
Public health & education 108 233 439
(-)
Total 2755 6773 14674
Growth rate (% p.a.) 4.0 3.1
Sources: Revised ISEW from table 2; mortality imputation as in table 6;
public health and education from table 1.
NOTES
(1.) This definition is in general not correct for a growing
economy in which net investment is taking place, see Sefton and Weale
(1996).
(2.) It would be more appropriate, data permitting, to make such an
adjustment on the basis of the present discounted value of lifetime
consumption. The inequality of income at a point in time does not take
account of life-cycle effects.
(3.) It is also the basis of the life-years approach to estimating
the value of reductions in death rates, see the appendix.
(4.) This comparison allows alternatives to the methodology for
valuing improvements in mortality that is set out in this section. If it
is assumed that planned per capita consumption is constant and there is
no discounting, life expectancy is also the value of lifetime utility as
a multiple of instantaneous utility. The ratios of the life expectancies
reported in table 4 represent the multiples of the 1950 level of utility
with 1950 survival probabilities which would be attained with 1973 or
1998 survival probabilities. This can then be valued using an assumed
utility function. I am indebted to an anonymous referee for this
suggestion.
REFERENCES
Atkinson, A. B. (1999), 'The distribution of income in the UK
and OECD countries in the twentieth century', Oxford Review of
Economic Policy, 15(4), pp. 56-75.
Crafts, N. F. R. (1993), 'Was the Thatcher experiment worth
it? British Economic Growth in a European context', in Szirmai, A.,
van Ark, B. and Pilat, D. (Eds), Explaining Economic Growth, Amsterdam,
North-Holland, pp. 327-50.
Crafts, N. F. R. and O'Mahony, M. (2001), 'A perspective
on UK productivity performance', Fiscal Studies, 22, pp. 271-306.
Department of Health (1999), Economic Appraisal of the Health
Effects of Air Pollution, London, The Stationery Office.
Department of Trade and Industry (2001), Digest of UK Energy
Statistics, London, The Stationery Office.
Douthwaite, R. (1993), The Growth Illusion, Dublin, Lilliput Press.
Eisner, R. (1994), 'The index of sustainable economic welfare:
comment', in Cobb, C. W. and Cobb, J. B. (Eds), The Green National
Product, London, University Press of America, pp. 97-110.
EI-Serafy, S. (1989), 'The proper calculation of income from
depletable natural resources', in Ahmad, Y.J., EI-Serafy, S. and
Lutz, E. (eds), Environmental Accounting for Sustainable Development,
Washington DC, World Bank, pp. 10-18.
Hicks, J. R. (1939), Value and Capital, Oxford, Clarendon Press.
Jackson, T., Marks, N., Rails, J. and Stymne, S. (1997),
Sustainable Economic Welfare in the UK, 1950-1996, Guildford, Centre for
Environmental Strategy.
Jones-Lee, M. W. (1989), The Economics of Safety and Physical Risk,
Oxford, Blackwell.
Maddison, A. (2001), The World Economy, A Millennial Perspective,
Paris, OECD.
Matthews, R. C. O., Feinstein, C. H. and Odling-Smee, J. C. (1983),
British Economic Growth, 1856-1973, Stanford, Stanford University Press.
Miller, T. (2000), 'Variations between countries in values of
statistical life', Journal of Transport Economics and Policy, 34,
pp. 169-88.
Mitchell, B. R. (1988), British Historical Statistics. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Murray, C. J. L. (1996), 'Rethinking DALYs', in Murray,
C. J. L. and Lopez, A. D. (Eds), The Global Burden of Disease,
Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press, pp. 1-98.
Neumayer, E. (1999), 'The ISEW -- not an index of sustainable
economic welfare', Social Indicators Research, 48, pp. 77-101.
--(2000), 'On the methodology of SEW, GPI and related
measures: some constructive suggestions and some doubt on the
'threshold' hypothesis", Ecological Economics, 34, pp.
347-61.
Nordhaus, W. D. (1998), 'The health of nations: Irving Fisher and the contribution of improved longevity to living standards',
Discussion Paper No. 1200, Cowles Foundation.
--(2000), 'New directions in national economic
accounting', American Economic Review Papers and Proceedings, 90,
pp. 259-63.
Office for National Statistics (1999), Economic Trends Annual
Supplement.
--(2000), Population Trends, 99.
O'Mahony, M. (1999), Britain's Productivity Performance
1950-1996, London, National Institute of Economic and Social Research.
Oulton, N. and Young, G. (1996), 'How high is the social rate
of return to investment?', Oxford Review of Economic Policy, 12(2),
pp. 48-69.
Sefton, J. and Weale, M. R. (1996), 'Real national
income', National Institute Economic Review, 155, pp. 90-97.
Vaze, P. (1996), 'Environmental accounts -- valuing the
depletion of oil and gas reserves', Economic Trends, 510, pp.
36-45.
Nicholas Crafts *
* London School of Economics, Department of Economic History.
e-mail: n.crafts@lse.ac.uk. This paper was originally prepared for the
conference, 'Why Economic Growth? The meaning and measurement of
GDP', Kingston University, August 2001. I have gained from
criticism by the participants. I am grateful to Eric Neumayer for
helpful comments and access to his data. An anonymous referee made
helpful suggestions that improved an earlier draft. I am solely to blame
for all errors.