Moral Relativism, Moral Diversity, and Human Relationships.
Cahill, Lisa Sowle
By James Kellenberger. University Park, Penn.: Pennsylvania State
University, 2001. Pp. xi + 236. $35.
Kellenberger, a philosopher, seeks a middle position between
relativism and absolutism in ethics by redefining Kantian "respect
for persons" in terms of personal relationships. Engaging mostly
contemporary philosophical interlocutors, especially John Kekes (The
Morality of Pluralism, 1993), K. argues that relationships, taking
similar basic forms across cultures (friendship, marriage), are the
ground and standard of morality. Relationships between persons should
always embody basic equality. Yet personal relationships permit and even
require diverse particular forms and expressions in different
circumstances and cultural settings.
K.'s approach avoids the abstract and insubstantial content of
some neo-Kantian theories. He grants, with contemporary Aristotelian and
"natural law" thinkers, that there are basic human needs and
values that are universally recognized and even
"transcultural" (129): "a prohibition against murder, the
value of the family, and truth telling," "food," and
"love" (41), "justice, respect for human rights, and a
concern for human welfare in the face of deprivation or suffering"
(130). With Kekes, K. distinguishes between "primary" and
"universally human" values that "derive from a shared
human nature" (97), and "secondary" values provided by
traditions to concretize the primary values (98). For example, while
respect for life may be a primary value, traditions vary in their
specifications of the morality of killing. Variations in cultural
respect for and protection of values are due to the fact that a specific
practice in one culture may not have the same meaning for respectful
human relationships under different social contracts--for example, the
supposed willingness of Eskimo men to share their wives sexually with
others; the difficulty in bioethics of understanding what autonomy and
respect for privacy signify in the U.S. versus China; and the meaning of
female circumcision in African societies versus its apparent meaning to
Western critics.
While Kekes tends to read such variations as evidence of a
pluralism of objectively valid moralities, K. avoids adopting the term
pluralism or the terms relativism and absolutism. Yet he does grant,
with relativism, that there is "no single true morality," no
one absolute standard for moral lightness, or no one set of absolute
moral norms. He also grants, with "absolutism," that
"evil societies, evil personal values, or evil agreements,"
along with "evil social practices," can and should be
recognized and protested (183-84). With Kekes's
"pluralism," K. grants nevertheless that there are different
valid moralities at the level of specific practices. He maintains that
if we "appreciate that we always ought to treat persons as
persons" (213), we have both a basic standard of moral judgment
that can reject evil, and a way to understand and accommodate the
pluralism and qualified relativity of moral systems.
The book's style is clear, with frequent sign-posts and
summaries. It offers the reader an accessible tour of recent
philosophical forays into the problems attending theories about reliable
moral judgment in an age of postmodernism, multiculturalism, and
globalization. It shows that these problems are of nearly universal
interest in contemporary moral philosophy, and identifies many of the
nagging puzzles that must be faced by thinkers who seek a coherent
defense of moral objectivity today. The puzzles include how to arrive at
a truly universal list of basic values; what secondary values to
include; how to assign priorities among both primary and secondary
values; how to define a conception of the good life that can help
resolve the above questions; and how to resolve conflicts, especially
over views of the good life (155). In the end, it is not clear how
K.'s own theory differs significantly from more nuanced versions of
theories he rejects, or how it avoids the same problems.
In particular, K. notes that not all societies actually accept that
all persons are equal or should be treated as such. Yet he does not
resolve this problem, any more than the theories he rejects as
"absolutist" can show conclusively that there is an ideal
morality that should be shared universally. This is not necessarily a
fatal flaw. All the theories K. discusses converge on the idea that
there are some shared human values based on commonalities in human
nature, values that still look very different in different cultures.
This alone is evidence that fundamental universality and considerable
variability can coexist in ethics, whether or not all the theoretical
problems have been resolved.
Theologians, especially Catholic theologians, will wonder why human
nature and natural law traditions did not receive more than a five-page
treatment, and why the one resource for interpreting Aquinas was a 1950
book by the Anglican, Robert C. Mortimer. K. concludes--oddly, given his
own similar conclusion--that Aquinas "seems to allow a cultural
application or determination of meaning of the natural law," and
thus natural law's "force against relativism is
negligible" (66). Recent work on practical reason by authors such
as Daniel Westberg, Daniel Mark Nelson, and Pamela Hall bears
resemblance to K.'s idea that the concrete realization of values
can only be carried out and evaluated at the level of practical
relationships among persons and in communities.
LISA SOWLE CAHILL
Boston College