The Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas: From Finite Being to Uncreated Being.
McDermott, John M.
THE METAPHYSICAL THOUGHT OF THOMAS AQUINAS: FROM FINITE BEING TO
UNCREATED BEING. By John F. Wippel. Washington: Catholic University of
America, 2000. Pp. xxvii + 630. $39.95.
Wippel examines the major themes of metaphysics: being and
non-being, matter and form, potency and act, substance and accident,
distinction and individuation, supposite and participation, God's
existence and analogy. He also develops a rational psychology and treats
the knowledge-faith relation. Nonetheless, this is not Everyman's
Introduction to Thomism. The laborious reading required of this text, as
W. traces the development of Thomas's positions through various
texts with copious and strictly argued paraphrases, would daunt any
philosophical novice. There is much repetition as W. points out
constants and changes; yet his remarks are generally careful and acute.
The reader is challenged and learns. With the book's heavy
concentration on textual analysis in chronological sequence, one might
be tempted to consign it to medieval scholars studying various aspects
of Thomas's doctrine. But the chapters are not isolated historical
studies; they compose a unified metaphysical vision.
Though W. is bound to Thomas's text, his metaphysics
determines the choice of texts studied, their interpretation, and
judgments about the success of Thomas's arguments. Fundamentally
W.'s Thomas is an Aristotelian, deriving all knowledge from the
senses. Surely there is an existential deepening; metaphysical knowledge
occurs only with a separatio, or negative judgment; multiple texts on
participation cannot be ignored; and the analogy of proportion, the
analogy of one to another, is considered fundamental (Thomas employed
proportionality only fleetingly in the De veritate). That act is not
self-limiting but must be limited by a receptive principle, provides the
basic structural principle in both essential and existential orders.
This thick-essence Thomism lays the foundation for the
interpretation of Thomas's proofs for God's existence: insofar
as the five ways rely on efficient causality, they are valid; the other
elements are not probative, and even the fifth way makes sense only if
finality is understood as the intention of the creative, efficient
Cause. (As external causes, efficient causes correspond to the clear
distinctions provided by Aristotelian abstraction, and such a
distinguishing defines the God-world relation, even in the causality of
freedom.)
Somewhat unusual may be W.'s insistence that in analogous
predication there is no single intelligible content (ratio) common to
all acts of existence, certainly not to God's infinite esse and the
creature's finite esse. But if esse is most actual, this
irreducibility of esse to any finite intelligibility threatens the unity
of knowing. If all concepts of essences are grounded in a concept of
being without a single ratio, can any unity be discovered for their
distinctive rationes? Since God's perfections are one with His
being, the common ratio in all pure perfections, realized in creatures
and applied to God, must likewise be denied. Admittedly the opposite
danger consists in reducing being's analogy to univocity--a very
difficult problem that no one has resolved. Perhaps W.'s
Aristotelian Thomism veers toward Przywara's Schwebe: analogy
involves an oscillation between sameness and difference, finite and
infinite, transcendence and immanence.
This intelligent, challenging book confronts various problems on
which Thomas wavered: e.g., is the quantity of signed matter responsible
for individuality determinate or indeterminate? But has sufficient
attention been given to Thomas's neo-Platonic heritage? Only one
text about the natural desire to see God's essence receives a very
transitory mention (533). After Hankey's God in Himself (1987) the
Summa theologiae's overall (neo-Platonic) structure cannot be
ignored: Broadly characterized, Thomas is horizontally Aristotelian,
vertically Dionysian. Does not Thomas allow for the soul's
self-awareness not mediated by reflection on a previous act of knowledge
(cf. ST 1, q. 76, a. 1 c; q. 87, a. 1 c)? The emanation of the faculties
from the soul's essence involves a resultatio, not a transmutatio,
i.e., an efficient cause (ST 1, q. 77, a. 6, ad 3; q. 7, a. 7, ad 1; cf.
1, q. 61, a. 1 c; 1-2, q. 18, a. 2, ad 3; despite W. 271-75). Does not
the innate desire for happiness, known confusedly but naturally,
indicate God's existence (ST 1, q. 2, a. 1, ad 1)? Would not such a
neo-Platonic emphasis revivify the finality of the fourth way? And how
does the concept of being result from the metaphysical separatio? If the
prephilosophical judgment of facticity does not attain metaphysical
being, how can metaphysical being be drawn out by a reflection on the
common sense's phantasm? It is not clear how beings participate in
esse commune, if esse commune "does not exist as such apart from
individual existents, except in the order of thought" (121). Beings
are also said to participate in God's esse (176-77). How is esse
commune related to (psum esse subsistens? W. may want to avoid having
all creatures participate directly in God's esse despite omne agens
agit sibi simile--a participation in the divine nature (esse) is
grace--but how can there be any participation in something that enjoys
no single ratio and does not exist separately? A thought esse cannot
supply the basis for a real participation.
A good book, but Thomists still have questions to discuss.
Pontifical College Josephinum, Columbus, Ohio
JOHN M.
MCDERMOTT, S.J.