Conscience and Community: Revisiting Toleration and Religious Dissent in Early Modern England and America.
Bradley, James E.
Conscience and Community: Revisiting Toleration and Religious
Dissent in Early Modern England and America. By Andrew R. Murphy.
University Park: The Pennsylvania State University Press, 2001. xxii +
337 pp. $45.00 cloth.
The history of the idea of religious toleration seems to be
particularly susceptible to teleological interpretations of progress;
the pressure for finding an "inevitable" development toward
liberty has afflicted not only Whig historians of the past, but many
political scientists of the present as well, particularly proponents of
modern liberal theory. Nevertheless, it is striking that within the last
decade, political scientists like Chris Laurson and Cary Nederman, and
now in the present study, Andrew R. Murphy, are in a position of
admonishing historians to take the historical context of toleration
seriously and to reckon realistically with setbacks and reversals in the
long history of the idea. Murphy sets out to challenge three
interrelated myths, the first two of which are deeply embedded in the
way that many scholars have interpreted the historical materials of the
seventeenth century.
The first myth is the idea that religious toleration is
self-evident and that antitolerationists were narrow minded or merely
self-interested, seeking to preserve their own power. By construing
religious toleration as a natural right, political scientists in
particular have failed to reckon with the political cut and thrust of
past events. The second myth argues that religious toleration is a
product of skepticism or unbelief, whereas in fact, the arguments in the
English-speaking world relied almost exclusively on Christian
assumptions. The more well-known arguments of John Locke, for example,
had all been anticipated in the 1640s and 1650s in the writings of
sectarian, but nevertheless, genuinely Christian thinkers. The third
myth pertains to the modern debate concerning the natural extension of
religious liberty to current issues surrounding gender, race, and
ethnicity. About a fifth of the book (parts of chapter 1, and all of
chapters 7 and 8) is given to a critique of modern liberal theory and a
defense of a modus vivendi understanding of toleration, but that topic
will be subordinated in this review.
Murphy utilizes a comparative historical method that investigates
the contexts and controversies of three North American colonies in
relation to developments in seventeenth-century England. A lengthy
chapter on religious dissent in Massachusetts Bay Colony and Rhode
Island examines the thought and practice of Anne Hutchinson, the
Quakers, and Roger Williams. The author gives considerable attention to
the social and political theory of the Puritan clergy and magistrates in
order to show how the characteristic Protestant understanding of grace
and its appropriation by individuals was not incompatible with strong
communal authority. Murphy underlines the cogency of antitolerationist
views by a sympathetic handling of covenant theology and contractarian
thinking; such views, he argues, were completely compatible with
enforced uniformity. The author's insistence that the question of
order and the security of life and property is historically prior to the
matter of religious pluralism helpfully contextualizes the truly
disturbing claims of the dissenters who sought to be tolerated. While
they enforced religious uniformity, Puritan magistrates denied that they
were persecuting others for the sake of conscience, and it was in
combating this line of argument that the dissenters appealed to a more
subjective, inward understanding of conscience that could only be
influenced by persuasion. The difficulties that the dissenters had in
finding a secure basis for order in Rhode Island suggest that toleration
was not a clear harbinger of the future. Hence, the political and social
order in the new world receives almost as much attention in
Murphy's account as the innovative ideas of Hutchinson and
Williams.
Chapters on the English civil wars and the Glorious Revolution
emphasize the religious, indeed specifically Protestant, nature of the
arguments for toleration. However, while the arguments were grounded
primarily in religion, they did not gain acceptance by the force of
their inherent logic: rather these ideas were prevalent in the New Model
Army, and the limited extent to which they did prevail is attributed
more to victories on the battlefield than to public debate. Here, as
well, those who opposed toleration on religious and political grounds
are given due weight, and one finds a fine appreciation for the
Anglican's use of scriptural arguments, particularly ones drawn
from the Old Testament. A balanced discussion of the theological,
philosophical, and political arguments for toleration shows how
skepticism about infallible knowledge was compatible with a good deal of
traditional Christian belief. In an age of pervasive providentialism,
profound skepticism was certainly rare, and where it was found, it could
as easily be linked with arguments for authoritarianism as for
tolerationism. (A useful, short section on Thomas Hobbes demonstrates as
much.) In addition to the increasing emphasis on the subjectivity of
religious belief, the pragmatic point that drew attention to the
peaceful exercise of toleration in Holland was one of the more
persuasive arguments. In keeping with recent research on the Act of
Toleration, Murphy emphasizes the limited nature of its provisions and
insists that there is little new in the actual arguments for and against
toleration in the 1670s and 1680s. The compromises that flowed out of
1689 allowed Nonconformists and Catholics to live largely unmolested,
but this arrangement was not the result of published treatises or public
debate; the modus vivendi emerged through a complex combination of
unintended consequences derived from human miscalculation and error.
Perhaps the most innovative chapter of the book examines the schism
of George Keith in the Quaker colony of Pennsylvania (1692-93). Murphy
offers us a fresh understanding of the inherent problems of governing a
seventeenth-century colony under the conditions of a relatively generous
policy of toleration, even when (or perhaps particularly when) the
governors are Quakers. This case study has the effect of reinforcing one
of the book's main contentions, namely, that liberty of conscience
in this era was quite modest in its claims; it extended to the easing of
civil sanctions for dissenters, but it did not entail the
disestablishment of religion, not even among the Society of Friends.
Penn's own views are illumined by comparison with the earlier
thought of Roger Williams. Penn, for example, relied more on the concept
of the ancient constitution than earlier writers, and the toleration of
Catholics in early Pennsylvania was notable. But no one, not even Penn,
was prepared to go as far as George Keith, a malcontent who compared the
exercise of power by Quakers to "rank popery." The Keithian
debacle amply shows how difficult it was for even the most advanced
thinkers of the age to find a purely civil basis for governmental
authority. The movement toward religious toleration was anything but
inevitable.
Murphy's use of comparative history to illumine the slow,
uncertain development of toleration goes a long way in helping us
understand the perennial tensions between the claims of individual
conscience and a community's need for stability and order. Written
from the perspective of political science, this balanced and
well-nuanced account not only serves to correct some of the more
ahistorical elements in modern liberal theory, it lends a new and
exciting relevance to even the most narrow historical investigations
into the religion of the seventeenth century. Ironically, such
investigations are relevant today precisely because of their historical
nature.
James E. Bradley Fuller Theological Seminary