Hegel, G.W.F. Lectures on the Philosophy of Art: The Hotho Transcript of the 1823 Berlin Lectures.
Wood, Robert E.
HEGEL, G. W. F. Lectures on the Philosophy of Art: The Hotho
Transcript of the 1823 Berlin Lectures. Introduction by Annemarie
Gethmann-Siefert. Edited and translated by R. Brown. Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 2014. xiii+ 508 pp.--After Hegel's death, his student
Heinrich Gustav Hotho took over his course on aesthetics. The standard
English translation by T. M. Knox of Hegel's Aesthetics: Lectures
of Fine Art is actually the version produced by Hotho in 1835 and
revised in 1842.
One hundred seventy-six pages of the current work are devoted to an
essay by Gethmann-Siefert on the 1823 transcript. There are forty-six
pages of glossary, bibliography, and index; the actual Hotho text is 263
pages. The Knox translation is 1,237 pages--which adds almost 1,000
pages to the 1823 lectures. The difficulty is sorting out what is
Hegel's and what is Hotho's.
Gethmann-Siefert notes that Hotho's views differed in
important ways from Hegel's and that he imposed his own views as
Hegel's in the text we have as the standard English text. Hotho
himself admits to "drastic interventions" in constructing the
1835 text. So we should go back to a direct transcription of
Hegel's lectures.
Hegel's several posthumously published works were based upon
his own notes and also, rather extensively, upon student notes. Student
notes also appear in some works Hegel published--Elements of the
Philosophy of Right and Encyclopaedia of Philosophic Sciences--in
smaller print as Zusdtze or additions. It is astonishing how much the
students were able to retain in their notes. Hotho especially is a
devoted scribe, hence the current edition based on his notes for the
1823 lecture series on aesthetics to get a relatively Hotho-free text
through Hotho's own scribal fidelity.
The first quarter of Gethmann-Siefert's introduction focuses
first upon the contemporary importance of Hegel's aesthetics. Some
view his phenomenological presentation and his sometimes revolutionary
insights into the nature of art as significantly more important than his
systematic approach; and, of course, some view it in the opposite
manner. The author attributes the difference in part to the sometimes
contradictory character of what Hegel has to say. (One wishes that she
had given some examples.)
Concerning the famous claim to "the end of art," she
notes that one should also speak of the "interminable future"
of art in Hegel's view. The qualification "in its highest
mission" should be added, for that mission is taken over by
revealed religion and the state, but art still has its future in them.
She goes on to delineate the genesis of the Aesthetics from the
four Berlin lecture courses in 1820-21, 1823, 1826, and 1828-29. Hotho
had also transcribed the 1826 lecture series (which is no longer extant)
and used it in his construction of the 1835 Hegel/Hotho text. Georg
Lasson's critical edition stopped with the General Part (which in
the Hotho transcription includes what later became the Particular Part,
that is, the epochs of art: symbolic, classical, romantic) and did not
include the Individual Part (individual art forms, called
"Particular Part" in the current work). In Lasson's work,
Hotho's additions are placed in parentheses.
Hotho admits that, in developing the Aesthetics, he had to go
beyond Hegel's expressed views to the system that it implied. In
his Encyclopaedia Hegel presented his system within which he lightly
sketched the main lines of his aesthetics. Poggeler suggests that Hegel
himself could have supported Hotho's more extensive efforts in this
respect.
In the second section, Gethmann-Siefert traces the genesis of
Hegel's views on aesthetic matters from the 1797 "The Oldest
System-Program of German Idealism" up to his Berlin lectures from
1821 on. In 1818 the first version of the Encyclopaedia contained the
sketch of aesthetics within the now emergent system and not yet
separated from religion. (Intriguingly, philosophy is presented in the
last version as the synthesis of art and religion.)
With that as background, the author examines the various notes
taken by students: she continues with a discussion of the Hotho
transcript reproduced in the current volume. She notes that, in this and
in his other transcripts, his "astonishing capacity for grasping
the sequence of thought in its essentials, and for reiterating it
precisely in individual points, can be established beyond all
doubt." The text is "reader-friendly, well- organized, and
elaborated in detail." Here Hotho adds only his own "concise
conceptual style."
In the third section the author notes that the four lecture series
"are already so essentially different from one another that we can
no longer speak of the aesthetics of Hegel." The 1828-29 series
particularly is "essentially reoriented." Hegel's use of
the systematic occurs "without overwhelming the phenomenon by the
concept," in the author's opinion a justified reproach made by
some against Hotho's two publications of the Aesthetics.
In a section on "The Systematics and the Formal Structure of
the Aesthetics," the author lists the charges against Hegel's
views: overwhelming history by the concept, classicism, conceptual
favoritism regarding the particular arts, and the thesis of the end of
art. She attributes them to Hotho's hand and sees Hegel himself as
"the non- dogmatic thinker of history." It would seem to be
difficult to square this with the Encyclopaedia system. However, the
author notes that Hegel "forgoes that direct approach for good
reason, favoring instead a 'thematic' presentation." He
grants to art "the mediation of a merely historical
being-consciousness of truth," "representing 'his own
time' and, in doing so, 'grasping in thought' the
decisive elements of the culture." "A phenomenological Hegel,
one who grasps the history of the arts, seems to win out over the
systematizer."
The end of art thesis is founded on "structurally
distinguishing art's function as it varies across different
cultures." For Hegel art is both mirror and promoter of a given
cultural context. Classicism for him is not an evaluative concept but a
description of the function of art in the time surrounding Periclean
Athens. Hegel's model is not works of art but the function of art
within a given culture. In the Hotho transcript Hegel begins directly
with the phenomenon, the representation that there are works of art.
Only at the classical state is art capable of being the adequate content
of art. Revealed religion, announcing the infinite, means that art is no
longer able to be the adequate conveyer of its content.
In the Aesthetics, "the Ideal" is "the sensuous
appearing of the idea": in this the author claims "we see
Hegel's entire aesthetics brought to conceptual form."
However, she also speaks in the next paragraph of "the
contaminating definition of the ideal," attributing it to Hotho.
The 1823 series presents the General Part in greater breadth and
complexity than he did subsequently, but presents "virtually no
grounds for directly linking pure sensuousness and idea." Art is
"a way of making spirit aware of its interests," but "not
the highest way of expressing truth." Art is "the organ of the
soul, the manifestation of it." In art, sensory appearance through
the two ideal senses, seeing and hearing, is higher than everyday
appearance. Art is the "spiritualized sensuous" and the
"sensualized spiritual." But poetry "has cut itself loose
from merely sensuous material and has relegated that material to being
as its own sign." Transitioning into prose, art reaches its highest
level.
The third part of the Aesthetics, dealing with the individual art
forms, is considered a "phenomenology of art" where Hegel is
said to have "jettisoned the rigid dogmatism of his system of
absolute knowledge." Yet, the Encyclopaedia system "remains
the approach and foundation of the philosophy of art, and should also
serve for critiquing it."
The author points to changes in point of view in the 1826 lectures
where Hegel intensifies his engagement with the particular art forms,
only to have many of the views presented retracted in final lecture
series.
In treating the individual art forms, Hegel views architecture as
the work of a people in the service of the divinity which shows the
ethical bond that makes them a people. Epic displays as well the ethical
life of the people, with Homer and Hesiod giving the Greeks their gods.
Not simply beauty but more basically historical meaning is expressed,
especially in sculpture. Painting brings itself about as visibility
freed from natural three-dimensionality. In Christian times, the objects
treated as beautiful are the Madonna and Child as well as Maiy Magdalen.
Presentations of the Crucified are not considered beautiful. All forms
are intended to be useful in devotion; their presentation in museums no
longer serves that purpose. Music at its best serves the word, else it
can lead to self-indulgence in subjective feeling. Inwardness is best
portrayed in poetry.
There is tension between Hegel's and Hotho's assessments
of Dutch paintings. Hotho saw them as depicting "the commonplace,
inferior and nasty," while Hegel saw them as reaching "the
highest level of accomplishment in all of painting." They capture
the vitality and musicality of art. Regarding music, Hotho shows
"demonstrable improvement in the philosophical concept of
music," but restricts his praise to the classical, while Hegel saw
value also in entertaining forms of music such as that of Rossini. Opera
is presented as a Gesamtkunst which produces "genuinely beautiful
art in the modern world."
Poetry is "the most perfect art," "the universal,
all-embracing art, art ascended to the highest spirituality." Its
content is "universal humanity, the human heart in its
fullness." It is in large measure the art of the modern era. He has
Goethe and Schiller especially in mind, with Schiller as the greatest of
the modern poets whose work is no longer beautiful and Goethe still able
to produce beautiful art. Hotho's lectures give the highest place
to Goethe. For Hegel Goethe's Divan of East and West makes possible
thinking one's way into foreign culture. Hegel suspends his
judgment of the end of art by pointing to beautiful art in the modern
world.
The Hotho/Hegel Aesthetics exhibits frequent evaluations, praising
or condemning, which are not found in the lecture transcripts. Praising
the accuracy of Hotho's transcription, Gethmann-Siefert points to
"the astonishing discrepancy between their [the various
transcribers'] own notes and recollections, and the posthumously
published Aesthetics. Though the current translation of the 1823
transcript gives us a more accurate Hegel than the latter, nonetheless,
it doesn't give us the whole Hegel on aesthetics because his
thought went through various changes in the course of the four series of
lectures.
What we do have in the Hotho/Hegel Aesthetics is a rich development
from the somewhat bald assertions, especially on the individual
artforms, in the 1823 transcript. It is worthwhile from a scholarly
point of view to try to separate Hegel from Hotho, but in terms of
"the things themselves," the later work is more stimulating. I
suggest reissuing the Aesthetics under the joint authorship and
continuing to appreciate what it manifests.--Robert E. Wood, Institute
of Philosophic Studies, University of Dallas