Sweet, Kristi E.: Kant on Practical Life: From Duty to History.
Wilford, Paul T.
SWEET, Kristi E. Kant on Practical Life: From Duty to History.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013. xi + 223pp. Cloth,
$90.00--Sweet's work contributes to a growing trend in Kant
scholarship that recognizes "Kant's practical thought must be
taken account of as a whole, perhaps even as a unity. " Identifying
the ground of such unity in "the animating desire of reason for the
unconditioned, understood in the practical context as human
freedom," Sweet argues that reason's demand for the
unconditioned "animates, authors, governs, and organizes the
various aspects of [Kant's] practical thought." While Sweet
states that "the broadest insight gained from addressing the unity
of Kant's practical philosophy from the perspective of the
unconditioned is a re-envisioning of the relationship between individual
moral goodness and the state, religion, and history, namely,
community," there are five interrelated and provocative theses that
undergird this "re-envisioning": (1) Kant's concept of
the will entails that "reason is not only lawgiving but at the same
time end-setting." (2) "The capacity to set our own ends is
what defines our humanity." (3) Kant's
"deontological" commitments "require
'teleological' aspects in order to be actualized." (4)
"Practical reason's demand always takes shape in relation to a
given conditioned." (5) Practical reason's actualization
requires that I continually "take what is--the context and
conditions of finitude in which I find myself--and work to bring it into
accord with what ought to be. "
The basis of Sweet's argument lies in the complex relation
between theory and practice in Kant's systematic account of
reason's structure, powers, and limitations. More specifically, the
point of departure for her inquiry is Kant's suggestion that since
theoretical reason suffers the "peculiar fate" that "it
is destined to ask questions that it does not have the power to
answer," reason necessarily turns to praxis in its pursuit of the
unconditioned. In the Introduction, Sweet provides a brief but excellent
adumbration of this argument. Sweet first highlights how, in the
Transcendental Dialectic of the first Critique, reason is
"characterized by a kind of striving, how reason's demand for
the unconditioned takes shape in relation to nature (as what is
conditioned), and how reason demands an unconditioned causality
(freedom) that is the cause of the whole of what is (world)." She
then proceeds to show that although theoretical reason's ambitions
to grasp the unconditioned or the absolute (that is, "an ultimate
reason that accounts for the whole of what is") are stymied by
reason's "intractably dialectical relation with nature,"
reason in its practical application "has the causality actually to
bring forth what its concept contains" (KrV A328/B385). That is,
"practical reason can bring about through its own activity what
reason seeks in striving for the unconditioned: an unconditioned
totality." Thus whereas theoretical reason's "only
consolation is self-discipline in the form of critique, practical
reason's dialectic is transformative; it leads reason out into the
world in an effort to remake nature in its own image."
The book's six chapters trace the course of this
transformative dialectic from its origin in individual moral action to
its culmination in the formation of a "moral world as the totality
of the ends of reason." Each chapter focuses on a stage of
"practical reason's evolving demand for the
unconditioned," illustrating how "at each moment in the
dialectic, a new, deeper, or broader demand arises that increases the
scope of what we must do to attain moral goodness." That is, Sweet
shows how reason finds itself at each stage of this dialectic
dissatisfied with the persistent influence of nature (the conditioned)
and is driven to pursue ever more encompassing and totalizing projects
in an attempt to overcome said influences. Thus, the book progresses
from "duty in individual acts" (chapter one) to the
cultivation of virtue "as a state of the will (a self over
time)" (chapter two), to the pursuit of the highest good (chapter
three), which connects the individual's pursuit of autonomy in the
face of natural incentives (that is, the natural desire for happiness)
with the externalization of morality in end-directed action that
endeavors to remake the world "in reason's image."
Chapters four and five then, show how enacting such a "moral
world" requires the reformation of "our natural relations with
others with regard to the use of both our external and our internal
freedom," that is, the formation of republican political
institutions and the promotion of "the ethical community."
Sweet's final chapter explores how reason, given "the
intractable influence of nature," is lead to reconsider its
relation to nature and to develop an account of nature as purposive, as
actually contributing to (rather than frustrating) reason's own
ends "through culture and history."
Having persuasively argued for the coherence of Kant's
practical thought, Sweet concludes by raising the unsettling prospect
that practical reason might also be subject to "its own kind of
peculiar fate," since its satisfaction is perpetually
"deferred to the domain of the possible." With these closing
reflections, Sweet directs the reader back to Kant's argument that
reason must turn from the theoretical to the practical in order to
satisfy its longing for the unconditioned. It is a testament to the
philosophic integrity of Sweet's work that it concludes by spurring
the reader to reconsider the essential premise of her inquiry.--Paul T.
Wilford, New Orleans, Louisiana.