Buford, Thomas O.: Know Thyself: An Essay in Social Personalism.
Weigel, Peter
BUFORD, Thomas O. Know Thyself: An Essay in Social Personalism.
Lanham, Md.: Lexington Books, 2011. xix + 121 pp. Cloth, $85.00--Know
Thyself examines finding self-knowledge amid modern suspicion of ideas
and institutions, while arguing why previous accounts fail. The author
first critiques historical accounts, before grounding personal and
social identity in relational triads of I-Thou-It and then assessing the
limits of social personalism.
The ambitious thesis is "social personalism can best provide
for self-knowledge" among all previous philosophical accounts and
other personalist ones. Personalism sees "the key to understanding
reality, both social and natural, is Person" as viewed in practical
life. The Delphic imperative to know thyself (gnothi seuton) means
discerning what you are, what you are to be, and what you are to do.
This discernment includes knowing one's past, present, and future
interrelations with others, nature, and society. But "suspicion
penetrates into the sinews of our culture," weakening confidence in
its ideas and institutions. Modern social systems lack solidarity or
authority. They fluctuate between disintegrative individualism and
dehumanizing collectivism. The center no longer holds.
The first and second chapters assign to various Western
philosophical and theological tendencies much of the blame. Ancient and
medieval hierarchical systems defined gnothi seuton by one's place
within tiered social and ontological orders, such as in an aristocracy
or the great chain of being. Creation, purpose, and authority rest in an
otherworldly God or Platonic forms, not persons and practical life. (The
reviewer notes that the Western concept of person significantly
originated as a theological one.) The author thinks that Greek and
scholastic philosophy became entranced with rationalist categories as
abstractions (being, cause, identity) divorced from lived existence. The
Renaissance tendency to "[put] primacy on the [individual]
will" was paired with skeptical Cartesian philosophy to yield the
isolated, "monadic," classical-modern self caught between
dyadic oppositions--mind/body, consciousness/other, self/world, and
individual/collective. Kantian subjectivism and scientific materialism
similarly fail to bring self-knowledge. The author sees these same
unworkable historical paradigms undergirding much present-day philosophy
and its failures.
The third through the sixth chapters pose an alternate "master
narrative" of interpersonal trust suffusing triadic structures that
recall Buber's "I, Thou, It." "It" invokes the
whole environment from physical habitat to events, personal aims, and
shared norms. Members bring their myriad potentialities to the triad.
One recognizes that all knowledge, belief, and concepts originate and
transmit through social trust. Persons and societies develop in webs of
freely chosen obligations and loyalties. This narrative, which the
author claims "completes all other [previous] narratives," is
inherently moral. Western thought obscured but never lost sight of these
triadic trusting relations. Even philosophical argumentation rests on
trust and free assent, not by seeking the grail of pseudo-mathematical
certitude. The author believes social solidarity and due care for others
is restored by recognizing that interpersonal trust founds all
individual development and all societies. Thus, self-knowledge emerges
in concerted awareness of dynamic potentialities in the myriad I-Thou-It
triads of practical living. The concluding seventh and eighth chapters
address the third part of gnothi seuton, asking what we are to do. The
author invokes the metaphor of dancing as representing self-knowledge as
a "creative finding" of trusting I-Thou-It interpersonal
relations. That is, individuals flourish by identifying their proper
environments and relations, while "creatively finding [i.e.,
dancing] a good performance within the social structures,"
including finding one's place and work. Attention to the personal
restores solidarity and trusting authority in primary religious,
economic, political, familial, and educational institutions.
But is such trust in trust sufficient? The author holds the
personal world as the "Creator" and choreographer of the
dance, but he recognizes that coherence and trust break down.
Life's disasters bring doubts of meaninglessness. In the face of
Lisbon and Auschwitz, the mystery of evil and suffering "cannot be
dispelled, but it can be cornered." In the end, the author notes
that suspicion penetrates even to the core of what the author affirms as
this "most complete" narrative.
Even sympathetic readers may wonder if such narrative thoroughness
has been achieved. Specialists of the historical periods and figures
surveyed might hope for different and possibly more subtle assessments
than the ones offered. Some readers will note how personalist themes
have been joined with and possibly enhanced by more traditional
philosophical and theological positions. Mounier and Wojtyla, for
instance, think persons realize their true potential in ontological and
spiritual orderings. Still, the author develops his positions with
assiduous care. He periodically recapitulates for clarity. Both
specialists and simply curious persons will find the work a
thought-provoking read. Readers will likely find the approach to persons
richer than often seen in contemporary anglophonic philosophy. The
author also treats personalist themes in Trust, Our Second Nature and
has coedited a noted anthology, Personalism Revisited: Its Proponents
and Critics.--Peter Weigel, Washington College