Yanofsky, Noson S.: The Outer Limits of Reason: What Science, Mathematics, and Logic Cannot Tell Us.
Weigel, Peter
YANOFSKY, Noson S. The Outer Limits of Reason: What Science,
Mathematics, and Logic Cannot Tell Us. Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press,
2013. xiv + 403 pp. Cloth, $29.95--The author explores "what
science, mathematics, and reason tell us cannot be revealed" by
examining the limits of language, logic and identity, mathematics and
infinity, computing technology, and science and cosmology. The author, a
computer scientist, wants to focus on how scientists and mathematicians
approach problems of knowledge, rather than how philosophers and
epistemologists do. The book's philosophical outlook leans
positivistic. Its length and range of topics suggest just giving summary
highlights here.
Chapter one anticipates the main themes. The first sentence claims
"a civilization can be measured" by the progress of "its
science and technology" because, as the author assumes, areas like
art, literature, politics, and morality "do not build on
themselves." Chapter two explores the limits of language in
self-referential paradoxes such as the liar's and Russell's.
Chapter three on "Philosophical Conundrums" treats Zeno's
paradoxes, emphasizing the limits of logic. The author sees ongoing
philosophical disagreement over the Ship of Theseus problem as reason
for his "extreme nominalism," where objects' identities
and classifications are all in our mind as collections of sensations
associated with names. He considers thinking that concrete objects
possess identities and categories an ideology of extreme Platonism, an
odd choice of label given the historical range of positions and issues
here. (The author, to his credit, mentions he did not consult a robust
range of sources here.) Elsewhere, and without obvious reasons, he finds
that our "sense of beauty, wonder, ethics, and values" are
"beyond reason and defy rational explanation."
Chapter four explains counterintuitive ideas about mathematical
infinity "central to modern science," covering Cantor's
work and whether mathematics and geometry are "discovered" or
invented. Chapters five and six consider the tasks computers "can
and cannot perform." He explains Turing's Halting Problem and
interestingly how limits in computing strikingly affect other types of
inquiry.
Chapters seven and eight explore limits and philosophical
perplexities in the physical sciences. Yanofsky covers chaos theory,
which studies systems where small differences in input yield widely
divergent results (butterfly effect). Experimental paradoxes in quantum
mechanics suggest to some physicists that the observer's own
consciousness actively determines certain quantum outcomes. Some see
these paradoxes as further implying a universe of significantly mind- or
observer-dependent features, which collapses the very idea of scientific
laws. Critics note that experimental choice affecting which quantum
properties systems display need not warrant that consciousness itself
determines it. If ideas made things, observes one philosopher, everyone
would be an Einstein. Current well-known interpretations of quantum
mechanics the author critically surveys and assesses as proving
unsatisfactory. But quantum oddities and spatiotemporal paradoxes in
relativity challenge the limits of science and ordinary intuition.
In chapter eight, Yanofsky sees Hume's problem of induction
striking "at the core of science." He then examines why
mathematics and geometry map the world so well. Since a deity explaining
the world's intelligibility is "unsatisfactory" for
nonbelievers, scientists prefer "less metaphysical ...
testable" explanations. Discussion segues to the anthropic
principle. Originally only a selection principle for cosmologies, one
basic version states that the fundamental conditions of the universe
must be such as to "permit the existence of intelligent human
observers," since there are such observers. Some read it (more
strongly) as implying finality or a Creator. Others in rejoinder posit
the multiverse (ours as one of many) in order to argue that conscious
life is still due to blind chance. The author ably surveys several
positions on "our fine-tuned universe," concluding that we
"simply do not know" the explanation.
Chapter nine returns to mathematics and logic as "the language
of reason." Galois theory treats why certain math problems cannot
be solved. Discussion winds down (appropriately) with Godel's
incompleteness theorem; indeed, its applications are still debated. The
concluding chapter observes that systems often impose limits on
themselves. Language paradoxes stem from its self-referential
capacities. The author sees reason's basic character as revolving
around the principle of noncontradiction and striving for truth. Reason,
he concludes, remains an inferentially limited tool.
Yanofsky allows that some prefer a more multifaceted conception of
reason, with philosophers emphasizing wisdom and understanding in
contrast with the book's stated formal and empirical emphases.
Though not a trained philosopher, he offers some balanced and informed
assessments; others could use more nuance or speculative caution,
perhaps aided by looking into broader sources. A strength of the book is
its considerable information on limits, perplexities, and current
progress in logic, math, physics, and computing. One normally has to go
to multiple books for this kind of information. Stanley Jaki covers
similar themes as a philosopher of science, notably in The Limits of a
Limitless Science and Other Essays.--Peter Weigel, Washington College