Meier, Heinrich. The Lesson of Carl Schmitt.
Simpson, Peter
MEIER, Heinrich. The Lesson of Carl Schmitt. Translated by Marcus
Brainard. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2011. xxiv + 210 pp.
Paper, $25.00--One might be forgiven for thinking this book written by
Leo Strauss. It has the obliqueness and indirection of Strauss, and its
(unspoken) thesis is the Straussian nihilism that philosophy and faith
are unfounded choices. Philosophy cannot refute faith because it begs
the question against faith by assuming reason is superior. Faith cannot
refute philosophy because it begs the question against philosophy by
assuming faith is superior. One just has to choose. This thesis, which
goes by the name of fideism, is false. Faith without reason is absurd,
even for the believer, and reason without faith is unfulfilled, even for
the philosopher. Ancient philosophers, at least, did not think
philosophy sufficient to grasp the whole; ancient believers too did not
think faith is believable without sufficient reason. Meier can only
assert his fideist thesis about faith by quoting modern Protestant
theologians. Catholics, at least, are not fideists because fideism has
been condemned as a heresy by the Church. If Schmitt was a fideist, he
was not a true Catholic, and since he thought himself a true Catholic,
he must have failed to understand himself. Meier gives no evidence for
the charge.
At the center of Schmitt's thinking, says Meier, is political
theology, by which Meier means politics understood from the unargued
assumption of faith. The thesis is novel to the extent that Schmitt is
often presented as adopting the view that at the center of politics is
the opposition of enemy and friend. Meier shows that behind that
opposition lies a more fundamental claim about the truth of faith, and a
more fundamental opposition, that between Christ and Antichrist. Schmitt
had an abiding concern with the katechon of 2 Thessalonians 2.6-7 where
Paul speaks of the one who "holds" the Antichrist from
arriving.
The Church Fathers interpreted the katechon as the Roman Empire.
Schmitt speculated that there might be more than one katechon, whether
at the same time or at different times. But he was concerned to support
the katechon, whatever it was. What is the katechon now? Not liberalism
which, because it is political and not theological, marginalizes faith
and removes it from the political sphere; for Schmitt, politics has to
be political theology because it can leave nothing out. But it leaves
nothing out because it orientates politics to theology and so to the
role of the katechon--the one who holds back the ultimate enemy who is
Antichrist.
Schmitt is notorious for being a supporter of National Socialism.
Meier deals with the question at length, including Schmitt's
antisemitism. But anti-semitism is a word that obfuscates. It cannot
mean anti-Jew because Christ and the entire early Church were Jews. The
Church still today includes Jews among its members. The Nazis too, at
least at the beginning, supported the Church. Further, the Nazis did not
persecute the Jews called Karaites. They persecuted the Jews connected
with the Talmud (which Karaites reject). The founding premise of the
Talmud is that Christ is not the Messiah. One cannot be a Talmudic Jew
and a Christian, but one can be some other sort of Jew and a Christian.
Meier leaves these facts obscure.
He also leaves obscure the possibility that if Schmitt was focused
on the katechon he was focused on National Socialism as perhaps the
katechon of his own time. National Socialism claimed, after all, to be
the Third Reich, successor to the First Reich, and the First Reich was
the Holy Roman Empire that the Church Fathers identified with the
katechon. The Third Reich, as Schmitt could not fail to realize, failed
to be the katechon. It ended in mass murder. But then all the
protagonists of the Second World War were mass murderers. The Soviet
Communists (not a few of whom were well known at the time to be Talmudic
Jews) were mass murderers from the beginning. The Allies became mass
murderers when they insisted on unconditional surrender, since they
engaged in mass murder (the blanket bombing of German cities, the atomic
bombing of Japan) to enforce unconditional surrender.
Meier's book is about Schmitt to the extent that it analyzes
all his writings. It is, in this respect, an invaluable source-book for
exploring the nature and development of Schmitt's thought. It is
not about Schmitt to the extent that it is pressed into the service of
Straussian fideist propaganda. But the unreason in Meier's book
seems to be on Meier's part, not Schmitt's. For instance,
Meier takes for granted that to believe in the resurrection is a matter
of faith and not of reason. Schmitt, as a good Catholic, could not have
believed such a thing. That the man Jesus of Nazareth rose from the dead
is not a matter of religious faith but of historical fact. It is as well
established a historical fact as that Caesar crossed the Rubicon. What
is a matter of faith is that the man Jesus of Nazareth is the Second
Person of the Trinity. Meier does not understand Schmitt's faith (a
further sign of which is his misleading discussion of the doctrine of
original sin). To reject faith for philosophy without understanding
faith is hardly rational.--Peter Simpson, City University of New York.