Brand-Ballard, Jeffrey. Limits of Legality: The Ethics of Lawless Judging.
Rice, Charles E.
BRAND-BALLARD, Jeffrey. Limits of Legality: The Ethics of Lawless
Judging. Oxford University Press, 2010. xi + 354pp. Cloth, $65.00--Prof.
Jeffrey Brand-Ballard, of the Trachtenberg School of Public Policy and
Public Administration at George Washington University, opens this
challenging book with a hypothetical prosecution in California under the
federal Controlled Substances Act for medical use of marijuana (which is
legal under California law). A Supreme Court precedent requires the
federal district judge to uphold the prosecution because the federal law
preempts the California law. But the judge "believes that medical
marijuana should be legalized. Therefore ... he ignores the law and
dismisses the indictment." An instinctive reaction might be to say
that the judge violated his oath and moral obligation to uphold the law.
But is that necessarily true? This book confronts that issue in detail.
The author concludes that debates about the role of judges in
obviously and gravely unjust legal systems, as in Nazi Germany, might be
thought to have little relevance to democratic systems, "in which
the law does not promote such horrors ... Few commentators assert that
judges are morally permitted to disregard laws that require only
moderate, rather than extreme, injustices." But Brand-Ballard
disagrees. He argues that "judges are sometimes ethically permitted
to deviate from the law in order to avoid results that are only
moderately unjust. Writers have not developed general theories of
judicial lawlessness," he says, "that apply to reasonably just
systems." He raises the issue: Do "judges sometimes have the
moral right, and moral reasons, to disregard clear legal mandates, and
not only when the law is extremely unjust?" "I argue," he
says, "that judges have moral reasons--albeit defeasible ones--to
deviate from the law whenever it requires them to reach results that are
otherwise objectionable on moral or policy grounds."
Brand-Ballard raises questions that are not often addressed:
"Even the laws of reasonably just societies inflict injustices ...
[E]ven a law that is itself just can mandate unjust results in
particular cases." He concludes that, "judges are morally
permitted to deviate from the law in such cases, which arise in all
realistic legal systems." He goes so far as to say: "My
position entails, for example, that a federal judge is not necessarily
obligated to uphold a ban on late-term abortions even if it has been
proven constitutional. But my position also entails that a judge is not
necessarily obligated to invalidate such a ban even if it has been
proven unconstitutional. Such a position risks offending everyone but I
am prepared to take that chance." That is why this is an
interesting book.
The author distinguishes between judges disregarding
"horizontal precedents" of the same court or a court on the
same level and "[d]ecisions that deviate from vertical precedent
[which] are almost universally regarded as unlawful. My question is,
when are they also unethical?" His answer: Not always.
"My project will strike some readers," he says, "as
a labyrinthine defense of judicial activism." The author's
argumentation, regrettably, is labyrinthine in the intricate categories
and distinctions he marshals to support his thesis. But that thesis is
worthy of consideration.
Regrettably, the author does not utilize the relevant analyses on
the unjust law of Thomas Aquinas, who rates only one footnote in the
book. Instead, we are left to rely on the author's own assertions
of principle. "Individuals in a state of nature have several
rights--to life and liberty, at least. They have negative duties such as
the duty not to kill other people and positive duties such as the duty
to care for dependent children, to keep promises, et cetera. The details
are not important ... The duties and rights that concern me are duties
of nonmaleficence, samaritan rights, and rights o f justice. These
duties and rights are elements of common morality and are recognized by
most major moral theories, including deontology, contractualism,
indirect consequentialism, and virtue ethics." But, to put it
simply, "Says who?" What is the content of these rights and
duties? And where do they come from? Do they come, as Aquinas and the
Declaration of Independence say, from God? Or from the mind of the
author? We are left to our own speculation because God did not even make
the index in this book.
Brand-Ballard distinguishes, "between invalidating legal rules
and deviating from valid legal rules." He defends, not
conclusively, his theory from the charge of "judicial
activism." His position would have been more persuasive if he had
deployed appropriate metaphysical and objectively moral bases for his
position. Nevertheless, he raises, subject to the limitations of his
method, questions we too often ignore: Are judges robots? Embodied
computers? Or morally responsible beings subject to a higher law than
that of the state? When are they morally obliged to do justice, as they
sec it, rather than mechanically to follow the letter of the enacted
law? This book is a serious analysis of the problem.--Charles E. Rice,
Notre Dame Law School.