Kant, Hegel, and Habermas: reflections on "Glauben und Wissen".
Engelhardt, H. Tristram, Jr.
THIS ESSAY EXAMINES Immanuel Kant's (1724-1804), Georg
Friedrich Wilhelm Hegel's (1770-1831), and Jurgen Habermas's
(1929-) accounts of God and of the interplay of belief about God (1) and
philosophically justified knowledge. Hegel's account is central,
because he responds to Kant's critical position that sets the stage
for much of subsequent thought, including the context for Hegel's
essay and Habermas's lecture "Glauben und Wissen." (2)
The reflection on the death of God in Hegel's 1802 essay
"Glauben und Wissen" (3) lies at a turning point in the
Western intellectual appreciation of God. (4) This text is addressed
both in its own right and as essential for appreciating Habermas's
recent engagement with the idea of God. That Habermas names his lecture
after Hegel's essay provokes the question of how to compare the
authors' views concerning God, especially in their accounts of the
relation between theological and philosophical claims, that is, between
Glauben and Wissen. After all, Habermas engages the idea of God, even
though he admits the impossibility of a "renewal of a philosophical
theology in the aftermath of Hegel." (5) Although his assumptions
regarding the possibilities for "communicative action" are
more Kantian than Hegelian, yet his understanding of the role of God in
philosophy depends on the major shift in Western philosophical
understandings of God appreciated by Hegel in "Glauben und
Wissen."
From Kant through Hegel to Habermas, the concept of God and the
place of theological claims have been progressively deflated. This paper
shows why the idea of God and the theological images that after Kant and
Hegel remain for Habermas to use in his "Glauben und Wissen"
are insufficient to justify its proscription of human genetic
engineering. (6) This insufficiency in Habermas's arguments is due
to Kant's and, especially, to Hegel's foreclosure of
God's transcendence, His independent existence qua God, even as
they use the idea of God to serve moral and cultural goals. From Kant
and Hegel to Habermas, the dialectic between philosophy and her master,
theology (7), has led philosophy to master her master, rendering the
claims of theology subject to the claims and needs of philosophy.
Habermas is the inheritor of this history. The robust position that
natural theology possessed in the mid-eighteenth century was undermined
and recast by Kant so that God remained only to satisfy the needs of his
epistemology and morality. Religion was then philosophically
conceptualized by Hegel as Absolute Spirit understood
representationally, but only conceptually by philosophy. Philosophy has
the same content as God does for religion, though for Hegel categorized
in terms of thought, its philosophically justified truth) Then finally,
having been lodged within robust constraints of secularity, God is
invoked by Habermas as a heuristic resource for bioethics.
I
Given the accent on Hegel, a cardinal difficulty must be
acknowledged at the outset: any treatment of Hegel is complicated by the
circumstance that there are numerous competing accounts of what Hegel
really held his philosophical project to be. As Kreines aptly observes,
"Recent work on Hegel lacks consensus concerning the central
ambitions of his mature project in theoretical philosophy." (9) To
approach Hegel is to do so within one of the numerous denominations of
Hegel interpretations. Therefore, a confession of sectarian biases is in
order: I concur with Klaus Hartmann (1925-1991) that Hegel's mature
project was postmetaphysical, or as Hartmann's best-known article
in English puts it, "noumetaphysical." (10) This view holds:
that Hegel seeks to advance yet farther Kant's revolution against
pre-critical metaphysics.... Hegel denies all need to even conceive
of Kant's things in themselves, leaving no contrast relative to
which our own knowledge could be said to be merely limited or
restricted. That is, Hegel aims not to surpass Kant's restriction
so much as to eliminate that restriction from the inside. (11)
Hartmann's account, and that of many of his students, (12) is
in contrast to robustly metaphysical readings of Hegel that gave accent
to the surface character of Hegel's language, while discounting the
systematic focus of his arguments on rendering the transcendent
immanent. (13)
The interpretation forwarded is that Hegel intended to articulate
an intellectual standpoint from which to give an account of categories,
the most basic ways being can be for thought, which are at the same time
the most basic ways thought can apprehend being." It is from this
perspective that Hegel undertakes his meta-ontological reflections (15)
that order the categories of thought and being (understood as
coincident) from the least to the most self-explanatory category. Hegel
proceeds from Being, the category that is least self explanatory, to
Absolute Spirit, the category that is most self explanatory, namely,
thought thinking about thought thinking about being. This standpoint is
absolute in the sense of realizing the final rational standpoint, the
perspective from which philosophical reason explicitly asks its final
systematic questions and then answers them. (16) Faith for Hegel cannot
gesture to a reality that philosophical knowledge cannot compass, as it
can for Kant. There is for Hegel no standpoint that can be thought
beyond this standpoint. In this sense, this standpoint is absolute. So
understood, Absolute Spirit, the higher truth of God (that is, of God as
understood in religion and theology), is philosophy's standpoint.
In this interpretation, Absolute Spirit, Hegel's higher truth or
philosophically complete appreciation of the standpoint of God, is
nothing more than philosophical thought, "the self-thinking Idea,
the truth aware of itself." (17) To put matters a bit more
provocatively, those reading this paper are for Hegel God, or at least
the higher truth of God, by participating in the standpoint within which
thought thinks about thought thinking about being. The result is a
thoroughgoing immanentization of the transcendent that has wide-ranging
implications for the understanding of God, as well as of theological
claims, for Hegel and for those after him. Hegel crucially recasts the
relationship of faith and knowledge.
II
Before turning to Hegel's "Glauben und Wissen,"
Kant's critical views regarding God must be noted, because they
form an important element of the intellectual background against which
Hegel wrote in 1802. Kant contributes to the metaphysical death of God
for Western philosophical reflection, as well as to a radical deflation
of theological claims, all the while still pointing to the noumenal place vacated by the lack of philosophical acknowledgement of the actual
existence of God. In the preface to the second edition of Critique of
Pure Reason, Kant notes that there are two kinds of knowledge. "The
first is reason's theoretical, the second its practical
cognition." (18) The first compasses that which is within the
bounds of possible experience, the second involves that which is
integral to moral action. Kant also distinguishes doctrinal faith or
belief from moral faith or belief. It is the second, namely moral
belief, that can support a kind of practical knowledge. As Kant puts it,
For here [with moral faith] there is an absolute necessity that
something must occur, viz., that I comply in all points with the
moral law. Here the purpose is inescapably established,
and--according to all the insight I have--only a single condition
is possible under which this purpose coheres with the entirety of
all purposes and thereby has practical validity, viz., the
condition that there is a God and future world. (19)
Kant has stepped away from the metaphysical knowledge claims of the
traditional, natural theology still widely accepted on the Continent at
his time. He has also anchored trustworthy belief in the conditions for
moral action. His goal is to recast the relationships between belief and
knowledge, between Glauben and Wissen, in great measure by changing the
very meaning of knowledge and belief.
As already noted, even at the end of the Enlightenment, the special
metaphysics of natural theology still had a place in many intellectual
circles, as well as generally in the academy. (20) Metaphysical
knowledge was generally taken to be robust and well founded. Kant frames
his critical views in a Western European context that, until the French
Revolution and its consequences for Central European culture, had
largely taken the existence of God for granted. Even the first French
Republic came officially to affirm the existence of a deistic God. (21)
Kant represents a complex and radical break from this intellectual and
cultural framework. On the one hand, Kant is convinced that he has shown
the impossibility of natural theology as traditionally understood. On
the other hand, Kant wants to use the idea of God, but without affirming
the actual existence of God: a theme that surfaces with important
variations in Hegel and Habermas. That is, Kant argues that one cannot
have theoretical knowledge either of God's existence or of
God's nonexistence, but one can nevertheless invoke God for
epistemological and moral purposes, thus preserving a place for ultimate
orientation. In this fashion, Kant seeks critically to alter the meaning
of knowledge and belief, of Glauben and Wissen.
Kant's eschewal of an affirmation of God's actual
existence is not in tension with his probable background beliefs, if, as
Manfred Kuehn indicates in his biography of Kant, "Kant did not
really believe in God." (22) The possibility of God, shorn of any
actual affirmation of the existence of God, continues to perform
important functions for Kant. Kant affirms the idea of God and the
practical postulate of the existence of God because he wants to
reconstruct his lifeworld prior to his Copernican turn, including the
epistemic and moral integration that that lifeworld took for granted
through its reference to God as the unity of being and morality. First,
as a matter of epistemological necessity, Kant holds that we need an
idea of God to warrant proceeding as if reality will always be
intelligible, coherent and unified in its particulars. Second, as a
matter of moral necessity, Kant holds that we need to affirm God's
existence so that we can coherently act holding that morality should
always trump prudential concerns. Third, he also invokes God in a
fashion that allows him to treat morality as unitary (that is, to reject
the possibility of moral pluralism). God as a logical possibility to be
thought, but not to be known or held to exist as an object of
philosophical knowledge, lies beyond the horizon of the immanent and in
the realm of the transcendent, but still does essential service.
The epistemic engagement of God as a regulative idea, as an element
of theoretical knowledge, but not as an object of theoretical knowledge,
is developed in the appendix to the transcendental dialectic of the
First Critique, where the idea of God functions to direct empirical
investigation to its greatest unity and scope.
Finally ... (as concerns theology), we must regard whatever may
belong in the context of possible experience as if this experience
amounted to an absolute unity that were nonetheless dependent
throughout and were always still conditioned within the world of
sense. Yet whatever belongs in that context must be regarded by us
at the same time as if the sum of all appearances (the sensible
world itself) had outside its own range a single highest and
all-sufficient basis, viz.--as it were--an independent, original,
and creative reason. I mean a reason by reference to which we
direct all our reason's empirical use, in its greatest expansion,
as if the objects themselves had arisen from that archetype of all
reason. (23)
In the background is Kant's recognition that, absent God, the
coherence of reality is at least in part is brought into question. That
is, if one acted as if the universe came from nowhere, went to nowhere,
and without a sufficient ground for its coherence, one would at the very
least have a diminished warrant for proceeding as if there will be a
rich coherence of the diversity of possible empirical findings, beyond
the minimal coherence necessary for the constitution of phenomenal
reality. This regulative assumption of coherence Kant takes as necessary
in order properly to direct the acquisition of empirical knowledge.
For the greatest systematic and purposive unity, which your reason
required you to lay at the basis of all natural investigation as a
regulative principle, was precisely what entitled you to lay at the
basis the idea of a supreme intelligence as a schema of the
regulative principle. (24)
From such considerations, Kant grounds the regulative use of the
idea of--but not the actual existence of--his deistic God, (25) which is
regarded as if He could be considered the Creator. The character of the
practice of empirical knowledge legitimates the idea of God.
Not as a claim about theoretical knowledge, but because of the
moral faith he is required to embrace, Kant affirms the existence of a
more theistic God as a postulate of pure practical reason so as to
maintain the coherence of the moral life. In developing his account of
what one can know is required for the integrity of morality, Kant does
not speak merely of an as-if God as he does in the appendix to the
transcendental dialectic of the First Critique, but instead affirms
God's existence as a necessary postulate for the practice of
morality, all without claiming God's actual existence. God's
existence is affirmed for the purposes of morality, but not as an object
of knowledge or theoretical Wissen. God exists as a matter integral to
the rational faith required for a moral life. Kant recognizes that the
morality he wishes to reconstruct, albeit recast in its foundations,
understood as a fact of reason, will be undercut without a point of
ultimate rational coherence. The Western Christian morality Kant
inherited had been grounded in knowledge of God, Who in His rationality
and justice coordinates desert with worthiness, happiness with the
worthiness to be happy, so that through His enforcement of morality God
guarantees that the claims of rational morality will always trump those
of prudential morality. Somewhat like Anscombe not quite 200 years
later, Kant appreciates that without a God Who reliably assures
appropriate rewards and punishments, the very notion of morality is
radically transformed. As Anscombe puts the matter with regard to a
morality without a God to enforce it, "It is as if the notion
'criminal' were to remain when criminal law and criminal
courts had been abolished and forgotten." (26)
In developing his account of what one can know through and about
morality, Kant does not hold that one should be moral in order to avoid
divine punishment. Such a view would be incompatible with Kant's
account of morality, for it would ground morality in nonmoral considerations rather than in respect for the moral law. (27) Instead,
Kant's account of what one can know about morality reflects a
recognition that he articulates in the "Canon of Pure Reason"
at the end of Critique of Pure Reason. There would be a deep
irrationality in necessarily and always giving precedence to moral
rationality over prudential rationality, unless one acts in a way that
affirms that there is a God and immortality so that happiness can be
coincident with worthiness to be happy, which coincidence is for Kant
the highest good. Here he argues for the moral necessity of affirming
the existence of God in order to maintain the rational integrity of
always acting morally.
The idea of such an intelligence [God] wherein the morally most
perfect will, combined with the highest bliss, is the cause of all
happiness in the world, insofar as this happiness is exactly
proportionate to one's morality (as the worthiness to be happy), I
call the ideal of the highest good. Hence only in the ideal of the
highest original good can pure reason find the basis of the
practically necessary connection between the two elements ....
Now, we must through reason necessarily conceive ourselves as
belonging to such a world [a moral world], although the senses
exhibit to us nothing but a world of appearances. Hence we shall
have to assume the moral world as being a consequence of our
conduct in the world of sense, and--since the world of sense does
not now offer us such a connection between happiness and
morality--as being for us a future world. Hence God and a future
life are two presuppositions that, according to principles of pure
reason, are inseparable from the obligation imposed on us by that
same reason. (28)
Since, as Kant holds, one cannot avoid thinking of oneself as a
moral agent, one cannot rationally acknowledge morality's absolute
demands on us, absent acting on the assumption of God's existence.
The postulates of pure practical reason regarding God's existence
and immortality are necessary to remove a cardinal tension between the
right and the good, between morality and prudence, at the core of
Kant's deontology.
In the process, Kant has implicitly recast the relationship between
faith and reason. In a foundationally meaningless universe without
knowledge of any necessary connection between worthiness of happiness
and actual happiness, indeed without knowledge of any enduring
significance to one's moral action (for example, a universe in
which in the end all virtuous acts are forgotten), there is a strong
sense in which always acting in accord with moral rationality would be
irrational, especially when the costs to oneself, one's family,
and/or close associates would be very high and the rewards of immoral
action to oneself, one's family, and/or close associates very
considerable. In such circumstances, one would have very good prudential
reasons not to act morally. Absent the postulates of pure practical
reason of God and immortality, one could not unconditionally affirm
always living morally. However, given the postulates of God and
immortality that morality requires Kant to affirm, he can reconstruct
the morality he found prior to his Copernican revolution. Without
claiming theoretical knowledge about God and immortality, as had been
the case in traditionally natural theologies, Kant established a moral
belief that warrants a kind of moral knowledge.
Kant's claims with regard to what one can know, if only
practically, about God are thus rather robust, despite the absence of
any theoretical knowledge of God's existence. This is the case
because Kant appears to hold that the absence of an affirmation of God
and immortality would constitute a modus tolens against morality.
Referring to God at the end of the first Critique, Kant says
Reason finds itself compelled either to assume such a being, along
with life in such a world, which we must regard as a future world;
or to regard the moral laws as idle chimeras, because without this
presupposition the necessary result that reason connects with these
laws would have to vanish. (29)
Shorn of any theoretical knowledge claim regarding God's
existence, God and immortality are known to be pure practical postulates
that obtain so that one may act while holding that a virtuous life does
indeed necessarily produce happiness. (30) In recognition of this
relation of the good to the right, Kant therefore claims that it is
our duty to promote the highest good; and it is not merely our
privilege but a necessity connected with duty as a requisite to
presuppose the possibility of this highest good. This
presupposition is made only under the condition of the existence of
God, and this condition inseparably connects this supposition with
duty. Therefore, it is morally necessary to assume the existence of
God. (31)
Kant's commitment to affirming the existence of God as a
matter of moral belief in order to secure the absolute claims of
morality is severed from any theoretical knowledge claim regarding
God's actual existence.
The idea of God also plays an implicit role in securing the unity
of morality against moral pluralism. Kant pursues this through two
accounts of God's relationship to morality. The first is advanced
in The Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals. Because for Kant God is
one, Kant's reference to God's holy will as the focus of the
kingdom of ends provides a basis for a single, canonical, moral
standpoint. (32) God functions as a unitary perspective within the
kingdom of ends, and in this fashion preserves morality against a
plurality of moral standpoints. The second account is given in the Opus
Postumum, where Kant invokes God as giving the moral law, and therefore
as providing a unitary moral law. (33)
There exists a God, that is, one principle which, as substance, is
morally law-giving. For morally law-giving reason gives expression
through the categorical imperative to duties, which, as being at
the same time substance, are law-giving over nature and
law-abiding. It is not a substance outside myself, whose existence
I postulate as a hypothetical being for the explanation of certain
phenomena in the world; but the concept of duty (of a universal
practical principle) is contained identically in the concept of a
divine being as an ideal of human reason for the sake of the
latter's law-giving [breaks off]. (34)
In both cases, appeals to God implicitly serve to secure the
canonical character of the moral content and the unity of morality that
Kant takes for granted. In all of this, it is Kant's moral faith
that lies at the basis of moral knowledge.
Faith that is trustworthy is for Kant moral faith. As Kant puts the
matter in Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone,
We have good reason to say ... that "the kingdom of God is come
unto us" once the principle of the gradual transition of
ecclesiastical faith to the universal religion of reason, and so to
a (divine) ethical state on earth, has become general and has also
gained somewhere a public foothold, even though the actual
establishment of this state is still infinitely removed from us."
(35)
By embracing God and immortality in the service of morality, Kant
reduces the significance of religion, doctrinal belief, to that of a
moral faith. In the process, Kant has substantially recast the
relationship of belief and knowledge, where theoretical knowledge has
been set within the bounds of possible experience, and practical
knowledge has provided the substance of moral belief. The latter invokes
God in ways that reach beyond what the regulative use of the idea of God
permits.
There are thus good grounds, given these two quite different
appeals to God and the justifications that sustain them, for holding
that for Kant, God is not one but two. What we can say about God is set
within two quite different practices that invoke God without claiming
theoretical knowledge of God, with the result that Kant has two notions
of God,
grounded in two different cardinal practices, both without
metaphysical substance. Hear, oh Kantians, your God is not one. Like
Hegel and Habermas after him, Kant sought to have a God who was no
longer recognized as transcendently existent or known theoretically but
who nevertheless could do duty for philosophy, in this case as an idea
and as a practical postulate.
In summary, Kant recasts the meaning of Glauben and Wissen, belief
and knowledge, by placing them within the immanence of the practice of
empirical knowledge and the practice of moral action. In each case, God
is rendered immanent to a practice but is nonetheless thought of as
transcendent. Unlike Hegel, who wishes to dismiss the noumenal and the
transcendent, Kant draws on a notion of God as transcendent. In the case
of empirical knowledge, one is warranted in making only a very limited
appeal to a starkly deistic God in order to guide the practice of
coherent empirical investigation. The other practice, morality, allows
an appeal to a sparsely theistic God with those properties needed to
maintain the coherence of the moral life and its rationality in terms of
a final coordination of happiness with worthiness of happiness. However
sparse these deities, Kant thinks of them precisely as transcendent, as
beyond the bounds of possible experience.
III
After 1795 and his very Kantian das Leben Jesu, Hegel critically
distances himself from Kant on many points and moves to develop his own
account of the relationship of faith and knowledge. A crucial point of
difference over against Kant lies in Hegel's relocation of the
transcendent or noumenal within the ambit of categorial thought,
Hegel's speculative reason. The point, as Hegel puts it in 1802, is
that "being and thought are one" (36) so that the possible
transcendent space to which Kant gestured in referring to God and the
thing-in-itself is rendered immanent to thought. For Hegel already in
1802, there is no longer a "beyond," beyond what can be
compassed in categorial thought, beyond what we can know, beyond Wissen.
In his criticism of Kant in "Glauben und Wissen," Hegel
already rejects Kant's position concerning the transcendent or
noumenal (37) because Hegel is prepared to render religious reality,
especially God, into a mode in which being is for thought and therefore
for knowledge. Hegel's foundational critique is directed against
Kant's view that construes the thing-in-itself and God as still
possible existents to be thought as being beyond knowledge. In
Hegel's account, both God and the thing-in-itself are immanentized
and brought within the sphere of knowledge. Because for Hegel there is
no further perspective, no noumenal or transcendent vantage point, as in
Kant, to which one can appeal, even if only in thought and moral belief,
beyond the realm of spatiotemporal sensible finite discursive
experience, so as to relativize philosophy, the rational perspective of
philosophy becomes the absolute perspective, the perspective of Absolute
Spirit. Philosophy as thought thinking about itself thinking about being
becomes the final rational standpoint from which all rational questions
about thought and being can be asked and answered. Philosophy is
rendered absolute, in that it is the standpoint that judges all other
standpoints. The absolute perspective has been claimed by philosophy,
and in the process religion has been fully immanentized. It is this
philosophical Wissen that for Hegel locates and recasts all belief about
God.
In "Glauben und Wissen" Hegel takes his first major step
in articulating this view, while also delivering broadsides against
Kant, Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi (1743-1819), and Johann Gottlieb Fichte (1762-1814). In so doing, Hegel advances what will be a typically
Hegelian claim, namely, that the history of thought leads up to
Hegel's viewpoint, in particular, to his recognition of the
coincidence of thought and being. As Hegel puts it,
Civilization has raised this latest era so far above the ancient
antithesis of Reason and faith, of philosophy and positive religion
that this opposition of faith and knowledge has acquired quite a
different sense and has now been transferred into the field of
philosophy itself. (38)
The force of this contention is that neither God nor religion lies
beyond the ambit of philosophical thought. It is for this reason that
Hegel in "Glauben und Wissen" critically remarks that
"Kant tried to put new life into the positive form of religion with
a meaning derived from his philosophy, but his attempt was received
poorly." (39) In this regard, Hegel speaks of "the corpse of
reason and faith," (40) not because he holds that reason and faith
have themselves passed away, but because his view is that faith and
reason have died to their old meanings and have been resurrected within
Hegel's account of philosophy.
The relation of faith and knowledge has been recast by
philosophical knowledge, which now locates and transforms faith in God.
Specifically, God is now located, in the sense of appropriately and
finally appreciated, within philosophy as Absolute Spirit, a moment of
Geist, a moment of culture philosophically conscious of itself. As a
consequence, God as a transcendent noumenal entity is for Hegel dead. In
claiming that the vanguard of the religion of his time had come to be
marked by "the feeling that 'God Himself is dead,'"
(41) Hegel is recognizing how in some of the religious, primarily
Protestant, reflections of the time there is already a loss of an
acknowledgement of God's transcendent reality. (42) This
transformation was both a consequence of, and a step beyond, the
reflections of Immanuel Kant, who helped effect the Third Protestant
Reformation (that is, after that of the Reformers of the 16th century
and after that of the Pietists following the Thirty Years' War),
which reduced much of mainline central-European Protestantism to its
moral, social, and cultural significance, and effected its conformity
with the requirements of modernity. (43) To this Reformation, which is
closely related to the emergence of a post-Christian and
post-traditional Europe, Hegel crucially contributed.
The most consistent reading of Hegel's claims in "Glauben
und Wissen" in light of the Logic and the Encyclopaedia is that God
as a transcendent or noumenal being does not exist, or at least does not
exist transcendentally or noumenally. After noting the feeling that God
is dead, Hegel resurrects God as a cardinal philosophical category in
the image and likeness of his philosophy's requirements. The result
is that, as Habermas appreciates, "With Hegel, delimiting reason is
replaced by a reason which embraces. Hegel makes death by crucifixion as
suffered by the Son of God the center of a way of thinking that seeks to
incorporate the positive form of Christianity." (44) For Hegel,
Christianity as a corpus of transcendent understandings is recast in
immanent terms under the sovereignty of philosophical knowledge. The
traditional transcendent God of Western European thought, who had been
made an object of philosophical reflection since at least the beginning
of the second millennium, and who was then Finally recast into
Kant's as-if or practically postulated God, so as to become a
noumenal possibility to be thought and for the practice of morality
affirmed but not averred as actually existing, has for Hegel been fully
severed from transcendence (thus dying). Hegel's position is in
part captured by Habermas's remark concerning "the methodical
atheism of Hegelian philosophy and of all philosophical appropriation of
essentially religious contents." (45)
In his thoroughgoing recasting of Glauben and Wissen, belief and
knowledge, Hegel's mature project aims to set aside the precritical metaphysical notion of God as a transcendent but still philosophically
knowable, infinite, personal being. God is dead for Hegel in the sense
that for Hegel the transcendental God has been laid to rest within the
ambit of an immanent account of being and thought. Nevertheless, Hegel
is no laicist. He does not presume that the public forum should be
rendered thoroughly secular. Religion as the absolute presented in
mental pictures, in Vorstellungen, remains as "the mode, the type
of consciousness, in which the truth is present for all men, or for all
levels of education; but scientific cognition [that is to say,
philosophy] is a particular type of the consciousness of truth."
(46) Religion, the realm of faith, is rendered conceptually accessible
within the critical reflections of philosophy. In Hegel's
Encyclopaedia, religion as the penultimate category is aufgehoben, that
is, speculatively relocated and more fully appreciated as a moment of
philosophy's reflections: the position of Absolute Spirit. As Hegel
puts it at the conclusion of his Encyclopaedia, "God is God only so
far as he knows himself: his self-knowledge is, further, a
self-consciousness in man and man's knowledge of God, which
proceeds to man's self-knowledge in God." (47) The death and
resurrection of God for Hegel thus involves the transcendence by
philosophy of God's transcendent or noumenal character and the
appropriation of the standpoint of God by the standpoint of
philosophical reflection. Philosophy's self-knowledge is divine
consciousness.
It is not just that Hegel, to use Charles Taylor's phrase,
produces a "'de-theologized' Christianity." (48)
More significantly, the very notion of God, even as God still existed
for Kant, is radically transformed, deflated, and placed within the
demands of Hegel's categorial philosophy. One in this way can
understand the force of Hegel's project to "re-establish for
philosophy.., the absolute Passion, the speculative Good Friday in place
of the historic Good Friday. Good Friday must be speculatively
reestablished in the whole truth and harshness of its
God-forsakenness." (49) This "God-forsakenness" is the
absence of God not only as transcendently existing, but even as
Kant's as-if God or his God of the postulates of pure practical
reason. For Hegel, God has been rendered integral to cultural
understandings whose objects are fully immanent. God is relocated within
Geist, within culture as philosophically serf-aware, so that set within
Geist so appreciated, the content of religion becomes integral to
Absolute Spirit, the final, reflective standpoint. Hegel emphasizes this
transformation in the last paragraph of The Phenomenology when he
characterizes his systematic, philosophical science, his absolute
knowledge, as the Golgotha (that is, the Schadelstatte, or Place of the
Skull) of Absolute Spirit. God as traditionally understood and
apprehended in faith dies to be resurrected as Hegel's
categorically domesticated God, Who is compassed by philosophical
knowledge.
Because of these positions taken by Hegel, Frederick Beiser's
attempt slightly to tame Hegel's remark regarding the death of God
is inadequate. By making reference to "Johann Rist's hymn
'O grosse Not! Gott selbst ist tod. Am Kreuz ist er gestorben'
(Oh, great need! God himself is dead. He has died on the cross),"
(50) Beiser seeks to discount the radical character of Hegel's
theological position, although Beiser surely recognizes the early
Hegel's criticisms of Christianity. Beiser wants to impute to
Hegel's mature position an attempt philosophically to come to terms
with Christianity by drawing on and recasting insights from Luther. (51)
Beiser is correct. However, Hegel thoroughly recasts faith in terms of
the demands of Hegel's account of philosophical knowledge. Hegel
sees his position as the philosophical higher truth of Protestantism. As
Walter Kaufmann and Horst Althaus show, (52) there are good grounds for
concluding that Hegel remained far from a traditional believer and had
self-consciously given a foundationally new meaning to Rist's
reference to the death of God. Kaufmann, for example, quotes Heinrich
Heine's (1797-1856) account of an evening with Hegel. The
interchange offers a portrait of Hegel as posttraditional in his
Christian commitments. (53)
I, a young man of twenty-two who had just eaten well and had good
coffee, enthused about the stars and called them the abode of the
blessed. But the master grumbled to himself: "The stars, hum!
Hum! The stars are only a gleaming leprosy in the sky! For God's
sake, I shouted, then there is no happy locality up there to reward
virtue after death? But he, staring at me with his pale eyes, said
cuttingly: "So you want to get a tip for having nursed your sick
mother and for not having poisoned your dear brother?"--Saying
that, he looked around anxiously, but he immediately seemed
reassured when he saw that it was only Heinrich Beer, who had
approached to invite him to play whist....
I was young and proud, and it pleased my vanity when I learned
from Hegel that it was not the dear God who lived in heaven that
was God, as my grandmother supposed, but I myself here on earth.
(54)
Heinrich Heine's report accords with Hegel's having
rejected even Kant's account of moral belief.
Hegel did not consider himself to be under an obligation to provoke
others with a candid disclosure of the posttraditional significance of
his religious commitments. One might think of the character of his
ambiguous response to his wife's question regarding his views about
an afterlife: "when she asked him what he thought of [personal
immortality], he simply without speaking pointed to the Bible, which she
of course interpreted in her own way." (55) Moreover, Hegel likely
saw himself as truly religious, as giving an honest voice to the higher
truth of what he considered Christianity, especially Protestant
Christianity, to be. In this context, his continued use of thickly
theological language or his presentation of himself as a Lutheran is not
at all disingenuous. All of this was in the service of his project of
disclosing and capturing philosophically a foundational shift in
central-European mainline Protestant theological understandings that
involved a reconciliation of Greek and Christian insights, a
reconciliation of faith and philosophical knowledge, of Glauben und
Wissen.
Just as Thomas Aquinas had participated in the radical recasting of
the Christianity of the first millennium by drawing Aristotelian thought
into the vanguard philosophy of the early second millennium in the West,
so too Hegel participated in transforming much of German Protestantism
in the beginning of the 19th century. (56) Hegel effected a substantive
recasting of belief and knowledge. The point is that, while Kant seeks
to moralize religion but nevertheless retain the idea of God so as to
secure the priority of morality over prudence, Hegel seeks to retain
religion as an element of Geist, broadly understood, so that religion
can be regarded as integral to culture become philosophically aware, so
as to recruit, place, and maintain the force of religious images within
the ambit of philosophy, which becomes the custodian of the civil
religion. The domain of faith becomes philosophically understood within
the final perspective of reflective knowledge: Absolute Spirit. Unlike
Kant, Hegel endeavors to engage God for moral and/or cultural purposes,
while discounting God's transcendent existence. Going beyond Kant,
the role of God for Hegel is further diminished in no longer being
regulatively necessary for epistemology or crucially necessary for the
coherence of morality. Nevertheless, religious images still remain
salient.
Through his reflections on the relationship between belief and
philosophical knowledge, between Glauben and Wissen, Habermas further
deflates the place of God. For Habermas, God does not function as a
regulative idea or postulate of pure practice reason as with Kant.
Unlike with Hegel, religion is not an essential (albeit pictorial)
element of a self-reflective culture's apprehension of truth.
Habermas instead wants to translate the claims of religion within the
constraints of secular morality, while nevertheless drawing on
theological ideas, that he holds can remain as a cultural resource to
guide moral reflection. For Habermas, God can still do service for
morality, while no longer even being regulatively necessary, practically
existent, or a presentation in pictorial thought of the truth of
philosophy. Habermas wants religion to enrich philosophy cognitively
(57) by providing moral intuitions, all without dogmatism (58) and
without commitments to any theological claims as having truth-value and
without the rich Hegelian appropriation of religious images. The
question is whether such a quasi-theological proposal after Kant and
Hegel is plausible. The answer to this question has implications for all
endeavors to engage the idea of God shorn of metaphysical roots,
including that of Habermas.
IV
In the October that followed the September 11, 2001 attacks on New
York and Washington, D.C., 199 years after Hegel's publication,
Habermas gave a lecture with the title "Glauben und Wissen."
(59) I proceed with the assumption that he did so both in order to
articulate his view of the proper place of appeals to God and religion,
as well as to connect and critically contrast his arguments with those
of Hegel's "Glauben und Wissen." Hegel's text had
previously been a focus of Habermas's reflections. (60) Like Hegel,
Habermas requires the cultural reduction of religion, although Habermas
goes beyond Hegel in holding that God and religious considerations must
be placed within a conceptual space defined by a secular culture.
Belief, Glauben, can supply guiding images to Wissen, philosophical
knowledge. However, philosophical knowledge must always transform faith
through a secular translation of faith that locates faith within secular
constraints. For Hegel, in contrast to Habermas, culture remains
necessarily structured by religious idiom and images, however much
transformed. Habermas's project of translating religious within,
and reinterpreting it in terms of, a framing, nontheistic moral vision,
does have roots in Hegel's account of God, articulated after the
French Revolution and Napoleon's secularization of Europe. (61) In
the case of Habermas, the moderate secularism of the early 19th century
has been followed by the laicism of the later 19th century. Habermas,
unlike Hegel, finds himself in a Europe marked by a normatively secular,
post-Christian public sphere that now dominates globally. Christianity
was for Hegel still a robust and essential Kulturgut to be drawn upon
for powerful images. Such is no longer the case for Habermas.
Habermas makes reference in the opening paragraphs of his lecture
to "the tension between secular society and religion" (62) and
to how this tension "exploded" in the events of September 11,
2001. Habermas regards the destruction of the Manhattan twin towers as
the result of a religious fundamentalism, which Habermas takes to be an
exclusive feature of modern Western culture and a specific reaction
against modernity. (63) Habermas rejects Hegel's attempt to
understand modernity's standpoint from the perspective of a
sovereign categorial rationality, which seeks to absorb religious idiom
and placed it fully within the ambit of philosophy: Absolute Spirit.
Instead, and towards the goal of avoiding a clash of civilizations,
Habermas wishes to recognize as well as to constrain God and religion
within the requirements of secular thought. Yet, religion does not
possess the penultimate categorial status it had for Hegel. In an
interchange with Joseph Cardinal Ratzinger, later to become Pope
Benedict XVI, Habermas gives at best a backhanded approval of religion
in asserting that "religious convictions have an epistemological
status that is not purely and simply irrational," (64) while
nevertheless appealing to religion to provide moral insight, direction,
and motivation. (65) Habermas wants to domesticate religion within the
constraints of secular thought, while nevertheless appropriating
resources from religion unavailable to philosophy, as he understands
philosophy, so as to secure conclusions Habermas hopes his bioethics can
support. In particular, he wishes to avoid an affirmation of human
genetic engineering. In the process, he develops further the project of
a postmetaphysical construal of God launched by Kant and Hegel, but
which now finds itself in a much more robustly secular context. Also,
because Habermas's Diskursethik does not seek to provide an
absolute philosophical perspective that can embrace and absorb religion,
religion remains a force outside of philosophy such that secular thought
must recognize and address it.
All of this leads to a challenge for Habermas. Against the
background of his attempt to steer a course between what he terms pure
transcendentalism and pure historicism, Habermas acknowledges that the
resources available at the core of his Diskursethik are not sufficient
to erect the prohibition he wants to establish against the genetic
engineering of humans. One might recall Habermas's account of his
Diskursethik, which through an appeal to an ideal speech situation seeks
to reflect the character of communication (that one aims at being
understood). Habermas wants to nest moral arguments in a practice of
rational discourse that
conceptually forces participants to suppose that a rationally
motivated agreement could in principle be achieved, whereby the
phrase "in principle" expresses the idealizing proviso: if only the
argumentation could be conducted openly enough and continued
long enough. (66)
Habermas holds that the failure to embrace this Diskursethik leads
to the performative contradiction of not truly trying to communicate.
The early Habermas, as well as the later Habermas, who adopted a more
empirical and fallibilist position, presumes that this practice will in
principle support the affirmation of the set of social-democratic
concerns, which Habermas endorses. However, by invoking God in his
"Glauben und Wissen" lecture, Habermas implicitly concedes
that, if one approaches the issue of the propriety of genetically
engineering human nature--while acting as if the universe came from
nowhere, went to nowhere, and for no ultimate purpose--there will be
insufficient basis for a rationally grounded sound argument to prohibit
humans from remaking human biological nature and directing human
evolution.
The difficulty is that within the horizon of the finite and the
immanent it is impossible by sound rational argument to establish a
single, canonical normative direction for evolution. If reality is
approached as if it were without ultimate purpose, there would be no
specific, normative directions for evolution. Granted general moral
constraints such as the acquisition of the consent of those who
participate, (67) prudent care not to cause more harm than benefit, and
even conceding Habermas's various justice-directed concerns, there
will not be, as Habermas realizes, a sufficient basis to secure
conclusive secular moral arguments to prohibit one in principle from
pursuing a wide diverse range of genetic engineering projects. (68)
There will remain plausible alternative ways to augment the capacities
of human biological nature, none of which will have a conclusive claim
on our allegiance. For example, one might plausibly revise human
biological nature by providing humans with the capacity not just to
perceive ultraviolet light, to live for hundreds of years, and so on,
but to live in the water with gills. Over the very long run, different
human futures are likely achievable through various projects for human
genetic engineering, and his Diskursethik cannot provide a categorial
prohibition.
Nevertheless, in order to make it plausible that one should
prohibit the engineering of human biological nature, Habermas makes
reference to what he terms "those moral feelings which only
religious language has as yet been able to give a sufficiently
differentiated expression." (69) In developing his position,
Habermas states:
God may "determine" man in the sense of enabling and, at the same
time, obliging him to be free. Now, one need not believe in
theological premises in order to understand what follows from this,
namely, that an entirely different kind of dependence, perceived as
a causal one, becomes involved if the difference assumed as
inherent in the concept of creation were to disappear, and the
place of God be taken by a peer. (70)
Habermas engages the image of God's relationship to humans so
as to advance the claim that, if humans were genetically to design their
human nature, the moral status of humans will be placed at jeopardy
because humans as creatures would be transformed into their own
creators. As Habermas puts it, "God remains a 'God of free
men' only as long as we do not level out the absolute difference
that exists between the creator and the creature." (71) Habermas
invokes God so as to affirm the gulf between Creator and creature in
order to indicate what he considers to be a threatening and harmful
change posed by the possibility of human genetic engineering, which
change offers the possibility of rendering humans into the creators of
their own human biological nature. In his argument there is no gesture
to any sense of the transcendent, or even to the as-if transcendence of
Kant's God. (72) The God that Habermas invokes is fully immanent.
Nor is there Hegel's appreciation of the necessity of religious
images. The invocation of this theological image, and the warranting of
the "moral feelings" it is to support, which is held not even
to be anchored in a practical postulate of God's existence, is not
justified as the conclusion of a sound rational argument, or supported
by religious images centrally placed (aufgehoben) within philosophy. All
of this Habermas acknowledges.
Habermas's recent invocation of God for bioethical purposes
comes after his decade-long increased engagement in concerns bearing on
religion. Initially, these reflections were set against the background
of his methodological atheism, which was designed to avoid "the
Scylla of a leveling, transcendence-less empiricism and the Charybdis of
a high-flying idealism that glorifies transcendence." (73) It is in
this manner, for example, that Habermas provided a response to Max
Horkheimer's (1895-1973) claim, that "To seek to salvage an
unconditional meaning without God is a futile undertaking." (74)
Habermas's counter-claim is that "postmetaphysical thought
differs from religion in that it recovers the meaning of the
unconditional without recourse to God or an Absolute." (75) The
plausibility for Habermas of now invoking God is a function of his
later, amplified, but quite domesticated view of the proper role of
religion in the public square. In his "Glauben und Wissen"
lecture, Habermas is willing to admit religious viewpoints into the
public square, and to allow adherents of religion to advance their
reasons for and against particular policies, as long as the religious
reasons for endorsing particular policies are "not just [reasons]
for the members of [only] one religious community." (76)
Theological grounds appreciated by just one religion are to be excluded.
In addition, and more significantly, in his "Glauben und
Wissen," Habermas allows religion to serve as an important source
of moral direction, but only as long as, as he states in this 2001
lecture, there has been an appropriate "nondestructive
secularization" or "translation" of religious claims into
secular discourse. Within these constraints, so Habermas contends, one
should not "sever secular society from important [religious]
resources of meaning." (77) Faith is to play a role for philosophy.
In his "Glauben und Wissen," Habermas, like Kant and
Hegel, attempts not just to constrain religion within the bounds of
philosophical rationality, but at the same time to draw on its
resources. With similarities to Kant and Hegel, Habermas wants to have
it both ways. On the one hand, Habermas wishes to translate into his
terms the claims of religion so that they can fit within the ambit of
general secular philosophical reflection. He wishes religion to be
constrained within the demands of his secularity and set within a public
discourse become more secular than Kant's and Hegel's. On the
other hand, he wishes nevertheless to invoke the idea of God for moral
cultural purposes, in this case in order to make plausible a moral
barrier against human genetic engineering. Habermas does not wish to
acknowledge religion as having a transcendent grounding, although
Habermas like Kant and Hegel still wishes to have theological concepts
retain sufficient power to do moral and/or cultural service, in this
instance by guiding secular moral reflection (albeit without an adequate
account of why theological concepts should or can still have such moral
or cultural force). Habermas hopes to tame religion but not to render it
too impotent.
These later views of Habermas are closer to Hegel in regarding
religion as a cultural resource, as a source of moral motivation (78)
and, more importantly, as a source of moral insights, than they are to
Kant, who still explicitly treats God as a philosophically crucial idea
Whose existence is a necessary postulate for the moral life. (79)
However, unlike Hegel, who regards religion as an essential,
prephilosophical presentation of the truth that becomes the content of
philosophy, albeit recast as a moment of philosophical reflection,
Habermas is more guarded, indeed much more secular. Still, like Hegel,
Habermas approaches religion as a Kulturgut, a cultural treasure that he
wishes to use. Habermas wants to be sure that this cultural treasure
taken from the past does not challenge the project of modernity (one of
the reasons for Habermas to recast religion by translating it into a
postmetaphysical framework through a "nondestructive
secularization"). (80) However, Habermas also wishes to engage the
resources of religion to stem what he takes to be a particular threat
from modernity: the genetic remaking of human biological nature.
Habermas's attenuated God does not appear up to the task he
has in mind. His God lacks both conceptual necessity and plausible
causal force. Unlike Kant, who regards the idea of God as crucial to
both his theoretical and moral projects, Habermas does not venture to
acknowledge such a centrality for the concept of God. It is not clear
why a notion of God set within the constraints of secular culture should
carry the weight that Habermas expects. His theological invocation is
not a reflection of his procedural or discursive norms. Instead,
Habermas's engagement of God is advanced as a cultural force to be
drawn on so as to protect mutual recognition and reciprocity. The
difficulty is that a God devoid of transcendent significance, or at
least a role necessary for the coherence of unavoidable human practices
(for example, as with Kant), cannot provide the bioethical guidance
Habermas seeks. After Kant's reduction of God to an idea as well as
a postulate of pure practical reason, and after Hegel's reduction
of God to an element of culture that only philosophy can bring to its
full truth and consciousness, Habermas reduces God to a heuristic image.
There is an insufficient account given as to why this invocation of God
should in fact be morally heuristic, much less compelling.
There is little hope that Habermas's strategy will succeed in
constraining the use of human genetic engineering. Habermas's
attempt at cultural intervention so as to recast the moral expectations
of the contemporary lifeworld by an invocation of a theological image,
all towards the goal of supporting a moral position disallowing human
genetic engineering, is unpromising. Among many things, genetic
technologies are dispersed in cultures little influenced by the
theological images still preserved in Western Christianity.
Habermas's engagement of God towards the goal of amplifying the
moral imagination so as to appreciate a difference between the Creator
and the created, which if transgressed would putatively set at jeopardy
the freedom and equality of humans, requires a very specific set of
cultural commitments. Such commitments are not present in many local
cultures or in the dominant secular global culture that is emerging. As
Fukuyama notes, there are significant areas of the world where the
Kulturgut upon which Habermas hopes to draw is not salient or is in
great measure absent. (81)
Habermas hungers after a moral resource, the roots of which he
wishes to extirpate. Habermas is at home with the cardinal cultural
consequences of the death of God, which Hegel appreciates as marking a
central characteristic of post-Enlightenment culture. There has been a
foundational severance from transcendence, the full implications of
which were not yet salient during Hegel's lifetime. Habermas does
recognize that, absent an appreciation of a point of ultimate
orientation, which he and the contemporary secular culture wish to
eschew, there can be no necessary or definitive guidance among many of
the choices that humans confront through human genetic engineering as
they stand before a possible posthuman future. Humans are by default
left as the measure of all things, including how to design their genetic
future, and in the face of de facto moral pluralism they do not possess
one standard of measurement. Habermas's response is to draw on
theologically-rooted, moral insights from those dimensions of a culture
that have not yet been fully secularized, while yet insisting that these
dimensions be located fully within the constraints of secularity.
Habermas acknowledges "the fact that religious communities continue
to exist in a context of ongoing secularization," (82) yet he
requires inter alia that religions "agree to the premises of a
constitutional state grounded in a profane morality." (83)
The question is then how far religion can accommodate to profane
morality without losing the heuristic force that Habermas wants to
engage, as when he appeals to the vigor of "common sense" when
seeking a force to set over against reductive scientific claims
regarding the significance of morality. (84) Can a secularized
theological perspective have the strength that Habermas holds a
commonsense view to possess? It is unlikely that the flowers of
theological insight can long survive after being cut off from their
transcendent roots. Habermas already recognizes the problem when he asks
whether one can keep "one's distance from religion without
closing one's mind to the perspective it offers." (85) Can one
in such circumstances find in religion anything other than contingent,
regionally located, heuristic insights, lacking general normative force?
In the dialectic of faith and knowledge, faith has been extensively
deflated by knowledge. Habermas's proposal in his "Glauben und
Wissen" is not convincing.
V
Habermas's account of a nonexistent God Whose significance has
been set fully within the constraints of a secularized culture raises
wider questions about the recasting of the idea of God from Kant through
Hegel to Habermas. As Habermas acknowledges, Hegel marks a watershed in
the history of the relationship of faith and knowledge, or at least in
one lineage of reflections in the contemporary history of
philosophy's regard of God. (86) Yet, in order to understand the
full significance of Habermas's "Glauben und Wissen," as
well as the contemporary implications of Hegel's essay, it may be
necessary to place Western European reflections concerning God, the
Western dialectic of Glauben und Wissen, in a more critical light. There
are grounds for holding that the synthesis of faith and reason born of
the High Middle Ages, what Habermas characterizes as "the
Hellenization of Christianity" and the "symbiosis of religion
and metaphysics," (87) may well have led down a blind alley, as the
attempts by Kant, Hegel, and Habermas to come to terms with God suggest.
These are not new concerns. Questions have long been raised about the
tie between the emergence of religious disbelief on the one hand, and
Western philosophical reflections on the nature of God and theology on
the other. (88) Attempts to provide an adequate account of this
intellectual history and of the philosophical attempt to deflate the
claims of a radically transcendent God face the larger challenge of
adequately assessing a major shift in Western intellectual history of
which Kant, Hegel, and Habermas are the heirs, a shift that began almost
a millennium ago, through which the transcendent God was interpreted as
open to assessment in terms of the demands of philosophy.
How theology acquired philosophy as a handmaid and then how the
handmaid ceased to be a servant and became the master of theology, and,
then, proceeded to domesticate theology and even God, is part of a long
and complex history that engendered a multifaceted recasting of the
meaning of faith and knowledge, theology and philosophy. (89) It is
worth noting that David Bradshaw in his study of a dimension of this
history has shown how differently God was appreciated in the
circum-Mediterranean Christian culture before the decisive turn through
which Western Christianity, especially in the High Middle Ages, placed
God and religion within the compass and authority of philosophical
reason. As Bradshaw indicates, the West's view of God developed as
a departure from a Christianity that had "no concept of God [that
is, the Christianity of the first millennium] view[ed] God not as an
essence to be grasped intellectually, but as a personal reality known
through His acts, and above all by oneself sharing in those acts."
(90) Kant, Hegel, and Habermas may in the end have shown, as Bradshaw
puts it, that "the God who has been the subject of so much strife
and contention throughout western history was In]ever anything more than
an idol."'
Rice University
Correspondence to: H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr., Department of
Philosophy, MS-14, Rice University, P.O. Box 1892, Houston, TX 77251.
(1) In this article, the terms faith and belief are used
interchangeably, and in each case it identifies faith or belief in the
existence of God.
(2) Jurgen Habermas. "Glauben und Wissen," Frankfurter
allgemeine Zeitung 239 (October 15, 2001): 9.
(3) G. W. F. Hegel, "Glauben und Wissen oder
Reflexionsphilosophie der Subjektivitat in der Vollstandigkeit ihrer
Former als Kantische, Jacobische und Fichtesche Philosophie,"
Kritisches Journal der Philosophie 2, no. 1 (Tubingen: Cotta, 1802).
(4) The Hegel-Jahrbuch in 2003 devoted considerable space to
"Glauben und Wissen," although few of the articles bear
directly upon this essay's focus. An interesting exception is
Gabriel Amengual, "Nihilismus und Gottesbegriff," in
Hegel-Jahrbuch (Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 2003), 38-44. Since
Hegel's announcement of the death of God and the account of
God's death in Friedrich Nietzsche's (1844-1900) Gay Science
(1882), there has developed a recent, complex, and heterogeneous
literature on the subject. For a small sample, see Thomas Altizer,
Living the Death of God: A Theological Memoir (Albany: State University
of New York Press, 2006); Thomas Altizer and William Hamilton, Radical
Theology and the Death of God (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1966); John
Caputo and Gianni Vattimo, After the Death of God (New York: Columbia
University Press, 2007); Daniel J. Peterson, "Speaking of God after
the Death of God," Dialog: A Journal of Theology 44, no. 3 (2005):
207-26; John A. T. Robinson, Honest to God (Philadelphia: SCM Press,
1963).
(5) Jurgen Habermas and Joseph Ratzinger, The Dialectics of
Secularization (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2006), 41.
(6) To disclose a relevant subtext for the author's viewpoints
regarding theological epistemology, see chapter 4 of H. Tristram
Engelhardt, Jr., The Foundations of Christian Bioethics (Salem, MA:
M&M Scrivener, 2000).
(7) Ironically, the characterization of philosophy as the handmaid
of theology (ancilla dominae) was introduced by Peter Damian (1007-1072)
and Gerard of Czanad (d. 1046) in order to limit, not expand, the
authority of philosophy over theology. See, for example, Frederick
Copleston, A History of Philosophy (Garden City, NY: Image, 1962),
volume 2, section 1, 167. The image of philosophy as the handmaid of
theology has antique roots in Christian reflections. It reaches back at
least to book 1, chapter 5, of Clement of Alexandria's (A.D.c.
150-215) Stromata. Clement has quite a different understanding of
philosophy, one he takes and recasts from Philo Judaeus (20 B.C.-A.D.
50), who in On Seeking Instruction regards philosophy as a handmaiden of
theology, but in the sense of the love of the wisdom of God.
(8) For an account of the relationship in Hegel between the
categories of religion and philosophy, see Reinhold Aschenberg's
cogent demonstration that Hegel categorially connects his philosophy of
absolute spirit to that of subjective spirit, finite human subjectivity.
"On the Theoretical Form of Hegel's Aesthetic," in Hegel
Reconsidered, ed. H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr. and Terry Pinkard
(Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1994), 79-101, 82-7, 95-9. The three categories of
absolute spirit--namely, art, religion, and philosophy--are treated as
the different forms of bringing the materially same content to
consciousness; see Vorlesungen uber die Aesthetik in G. W. F. Hegel,
Werke in zwanzig Banden (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1969), vol. 13,
139; and again as different shapes, Gestalten, of knowing the materially
same content in Hegel, Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences in
Outline (1830 ed.), 556, 565, 572. This content is the absolute,
"the divine, the deepest interests of man, the most comprehensive
truths of the spirit." Aesthetik I, 21. The absolute is first
apprehended as art, as knowledge of the absolute in the form of sensible
intuition. Then it is apprehended as religion, as knowledge in the form
of representation and belief. After that it is apprehended as
philosophy, as the same knowledge in the form of categorial thought.
Hegel, thereby, categorially connects his notion of absolute spirit to
the notion of subjective spirit in two respects: first, because
consciousness and knowing, Wissen, are the fundamental themes of the
theory of phenomenological consciousness, or "phenomenology,"
of subjective spirit, and second, because intuition, representation, and
thought are the three types of intentionality in Hegel's treatment
of the psychology of subjective spirit. In all of this, Hegel's
absolute spirit is not a metaphysical absolute, but a conscious content
fully accessible in principle to human subjectivity.
(9) James Kreines, "Between the Bounds of Experience and
Divine Intuition: Kant's Epistemic Limits and Hegel's
Ambitions," Inquiry 50 (2007), 306.
(10) Klaus Hartmann, "Hegel: A Non-Metaphysical View," in
Hegel, ed. Alasdair MacIntyre (Garden City, NY: Anchor Books, 1972),
101-24. A presentation of Klaus Hartmann's account of Hegel's
project is given in Klaus Hartmann, Hegels Logik, ed. Olaf Muller
(Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1999); Klaus Hartmann, Studies in
Foundational Philosophy (Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1988); Klaus Hartmann,
Politische Philosophie (Munich: Alber, 1981); Klaus Hartmann, ed. Die
ontologische Option. (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1976); Klaus Hartmann,
Die Marxsche Theorie. (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1970); Klaus Hartmann,
"On Taking the Transcendental Turn," Review of Metaphysics 20,
no. 2 (1966): 223-49. An overview of some developments from
Hartmann's account of Hegel is presented in H. Tristram Engelhardt,
Jr. and Terry Pinkard, eds., Hegel Reconsidered (Dordrecht: Kluwer,
1994).
(11) Kreines, "Between the Bounds of Experience and Divine
Intuition," 307. Emphasis is in the original quotation unless
otherwise noted.
(12) Thomas J. Bole, III, "Contradiction in Hegel's
Science of Logic." Review of Metaphysics 40, no. 3 (1987): 515-34;
Terry Pinkard, "What is the non-Metaphysical Reading of Hegel? A
Reply to F. Beiser," Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great Britain 34, (1996): 13-20.
(13) Even Stace's once very popular commentary on Hegel speaks
in metaphysical tones of the "world process" being consummated
in philosophy. W. T. Stace, The Philosophy of Hegel (Mineola, NY: Dover,
1955), 518.
(14) A more detailed presentation of my view of Hegel's
project is available in H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr., Mind-Body: A
Categorial Relation (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973), chapter 4,
"A Transcendental Ontological Account."
(15) H. T. Engelhardt, Jr., "The Dialectic as a
Meta-Ontological Method," in Hegel-Jahrbuch, 1975 (Koln:
Pahl-Rugenstein Verlag, 1976), 424-9.
(16) Klaus Hartmann, "Hegel: A Non-Metaphysical View," in
Hegel, ed. Alasdair MacIntyre (New York: Doubleday, 1972), 117.
"[R]eason is only satisfied ... to make ontology possible."
Klaus Hartmann, Studies in Foundational Philosophy (Amsterdam: Rodopi,
1988), 280.
(17) G. W. F. Hegel, Hegel's Philosophy of Mind, trans.
William Wallace (Clarendon Press, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1971), 574.
(18) Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, 16, Bx.
(19) Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, 752, A828/B856.
(20) One might think of the text produced by Baumgarten (1714-1762)
and used by Kant when teaching: Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten,
Metaphysik (Norderstedt, Germany: Books on Demand, 2004 [1739]).
(21) Michel Vovelle, The Revolution against the Church (Columbus:
Ohio State University Press, 1991), 119-21.
(22) Manfred Kuehn, Kant: A Biography (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2001), 391-2.
(23) Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Werner S.
Pluhar (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1996), 640-1, A672-3/B700-1.
(24) Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, 659, A699/B727.
(25) Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, A675/B703.
(26) G. E. M. Anscombe, "Modern Moral Philosophy,"
Philosophy 33, no. 1, (January 1958): 6.
(27) Kant, Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, AK IV,
(Berlin: Koniglich Preussische Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1903-1911),
433. All future references containing AK followed by a Roman Numeral indicate the volume and the page in Kants gesammelte Schriften (Berlin:
Koniglich Preussische Akademie der Wissenschaffen, 1903-1911).
(28) Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, 740, A810-11/B838-9.
(29) Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, 740, A811/B839.
(30) Kant, Critique of Practical Reason, AK V, 114.
(31) Kant, Critique of Practical Reason, 126, AK V, 122.
(32) Kant, The Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, AK IV,
414.
(33) Of course, God (but not for Kant) could give different laws to
different persons or groups of persons, as with the 613 laws given to
Jews and the seven laws given to the sons of Noah. Nevertheless, the
unity of each set of laws is grounded in God.
(34) Immanuel Kant, Opus Postumum, ed. Eckart Forster, trans.
Eckart Forster and Michael Rosen (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1993), 204, AK XXII, 122-3.
(35) Immanuel Kant, Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone (New
York: Harper Torchbooks, 1960), 113, AK VI 114.
(36) G. W. F. Hegel, Jenaer kritische Schriften, in Gesammelte
Werke, volume 4. (Hamburg: Meiner, 1968), 413. Hegel's
"Glauben und Wissen" originally appeared in Kritisches Journal
der Philosophie, volume 2, number 1 (Tubingen: Cotta, 1802). The version
referred to in this paper is the 1977 English translation: G. W. F.
Hegel, Faith & Knowledge, trans. Walter Cerf and H. S. Harris
(Albany: State University of New York Press, 1977), 109.
(37) Hegel, Jenaer kritische Schriften, 325.
(38) Hegel, Faith & Knowledge, 55; Hegel, Jenaer kritische
Schriften, 315.
(39) Hegel, Jenaer kritische Schriften, 315.
(40) Ibid.
(41) Hegel, Faith & Knowledge, 190; Hegel, Jenaer kritische
Schriften, 414.
(42) Reflections on Hegel's views regarding God have generated
considerable literature. For a small sample of the conflicting views,
see Klaus Brinkmann, "Pantheisme, panlogisme et protestantisme dans
la philosophie de Hegel," in Les Philosophes et la question de
Dieu, ed. Luc Langlois (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 2006),
223-38; William Desmond, "Hegel's God, Transcendence, and the
Counterfeit Double: A Figure of Dialectical Equivocity?" Owl of
Minerva 36, no. 2 (2005): 91-110; William Desmond, Hegel's God. A
Counterfeit Double? (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2003); William Franke,
"The Deaths of God in Hegel and Nietzsche and the Crisis of Values
in Secular Modernity and Post-secular Postmodernity," Religion and
the Arts 11, no. 2 (2007): 214-41; Peter C. Hodgson, "Hegel's
God: Counterfeit or Real?" Owl of Minerva 36, no. 2 (2005): 153-63;
Stephen Houlgate, "Hegel, Desmond, and the Problem of God's
Transcendence," Owl of Minerva 36, no. 2 (2005): 131-52; Quentin
Lauer, Hegel's Concept of God (Albany: State University of New York
Press, 1982); Craig M. Nichols, "The Eschatological Theogony of the
God Who May Be: Exploring the Concept of Divine Presence in Kearney,
Hegel, and Heidegger," Metaphilosophy 36, no. 5 (2005): 750-61;
Alan M. Olson, Hegel and the Spirit (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992).
(43) The nineteenth-century transformation of much of main-line
German Protestantism in the wake of Kant and the events of the French
Revolution was itself revolutionary. Many such as Kant sought to achieve
a "purified religion" with only a rational substance. In some
quarters, the changes were so substantial that some liberal Jews could
even contemplate entering congregationally in union with liberal
Protestants. See Jonathan M. Hess, Germans, Jews and the Claims of
Modernity (New Haven, CN: Yale University Press, 2002), 176-82. There
was also the subsequent impact on the mainline Christianity of central
Europe from the influence of Hegel and those who followed him. One might
consider Eduard von Hartmann's remark: "Liberal Protestantism
has necessarily become an irreligious phenomenon of history, because
Protestantism has taken the interest of modern culture to be the
criterion," in: Eduard von Hartmann, Die Selbstzersetzung des
Christenthums (Berlin: Duncker's, 1874), 87. There were surely
those who reacted in opposition, such as Soren Kierkegaard (1813-1855).
(44) Jurgen Habermas, Religion and Rationality, ed. Eduardo
Mendieta (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2002), 112.
(45) Habermas, Religion and Rationality, 68.
(46) Hegel, "Preface to the Second Edition [1827]," in
The Encyclopaedia Logic, trans. T.F. Geraets, W.A. Suchting, and H.S.
Harris (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1991), 11.
(47) Hegel, Philosophy of Mind, 298, [section] 564.
(48) "Thus while Hegel is not in the main line of descent of
liberal Protestantism, he is the point of origin of another important
movement towards a de-mythologized, one might say,
'de-theologized' Christianity. Contemporary theologies of
'the death of God' are his spiritual grandchildren. The
filiation is either direct, as with Paul Tillich who very much
influenced the theologians of this school, or through the young Hegelian
Ludwig Feuerbach." Charles Taylor, Hegel (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1975), 495.
(49) Hegel, Faith & Knowledge, 191.
(50) Frederick Beiser, Hegel (New York: Routledge, 2005), 138.
(51) It must be acknowledged that others have imputed to Hegel a
more theistic account of God than this paper holds to be justified.
Consider, for example, the portrayal of Hegel's position by Quentin
Lauer and the consanguinity it shows with Scholastic philosophical
understandings of the proper relation between philosophy and theology:
"The philosophy of which Hegel speaks has turned out to be
startlingly--for some, perhaps, frighteningly--theological, and yet, for
all that it is not less but all the more philosophical. If it is
possible to identify God with infinite "Reason," absolute
'Spirit,' then it must be said that God, in what he is and
what he does, is supremely rational, that he is infinite
'rationality.' To know God, then, is man's rational goal,
and to be thoroughly rational is to know God. But this can make sense
only if human reason is somehow "divine," continuous with
'infinite' Reason, since "reason" is one, not
many." Quentin Lauer, Hegel's Concept of God (Albany: State
University of New York Press, 1982), 323-4.
(52) Walter Kaufmann, Hegel: A Reinterpretation (Garden City, NY:
Anchor Books, 1966); Horst Althaus, Hegel: An Intellectual Biography
(Cambridge: Polity Press, 2000), 254.
(53) A slightly different translation of this passage can be found
in Heinrich Heine, Heinrich Heine's Memoirs From His Works, Letters
and Conversations, ed. Gustav Karpeles and trans. Gilbert Cannan (London: Heinemann, 1910), 114
(54) Kaufmann, Hegel: A Reinterpretation, 367.
(55) Terry Pinkard, Hegel: A Biography (New York: Cambridge
University Press, 2000), 577.
(56) Emil Fackenheim summarizes the influence of Hegel in very
positive terms: "We may rely on Karl Barth's apt formulation
that Hegel seeks to do for the modern Protestant world what St. Thomas
Aquinas has done for the Catholic Middle Ages." The Religious
Dimension in Hegel's Thought (Bloomington: Indiana University
Press, 1967), 10. Both figures participated in a radical recasting of
Christian discourse and commitments.
(57) Habermas and Ratzinger, The Dialectics of Secularization, 38.
(58) Ibid, 43.
(59) References to the English translation of Jurgen
Habermas's "Glauben und Wissen," which lecture originally
appeared in the Frankfurter allgemeine Zeitung 239 (October 15, 2001):
9, are to "Faith and Knowledge" in Habermas, The Future of
Human Nature (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2003), 101-15.
(60) Habermas, for example, has explored Hegel with an accent on
Hegel's "Glauben und Wissen" in Jurgen Habermas,
"Hegel's Concept of Modernity," The Philosophical
Discourse of Modernity, trans. Frederick Lawrence (Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press, 1987), 23-44.
(61) The year in which Hegel's "Glauben und Wissen"
was published, 1802, proved to be a significantly tumultuous year for
central Europe. After Napoleon had conquered lands west of the Rhine, he
entered into agreements that led to properties being taken from the
Roman Catholic Church, destroying a wide-ranging fabric of charitable
and educational foundations. These events, known as the Secularization,
followed the extraordinary assembly of the Reichsdeputation (August 24,
1802), which enacted the Reichsdeputationshauptschluss and in 1803
produced the dissolution of the remaining Roman Catholic episcopal
principalities. Many of the social functions of the Roman church were
transferred to secular authorities.
(62) Jurgen Habermas, The Future of Human Nature, 101.
(63) Habermas gives the following account of fundamentalists.
"We call 'fundamentalist' those religious movements
which, given the cognitive limits of modern life, nevertheless persist
in practicing or promoting a return to the exclusivity of premodern religious attitudes. Fundamentalism lacks the epistemic innocence of
those long-ago realms in which the world religions first flourished and
which could somehow still be experienced as limitless. Only contemporary
China can provide some small taste of this consciousness of imperial
boundlessness, which once grounded the limited 'universalism'
of the world religions. But modern conditions are compatible only with a
strict, Kantian form of universalism." Habermas, Religion and
Rationality, 151.
(64) Habermas and Ratzinger, The Dialectics of Secularization, 51.
(65) Ibid, 29.
(66) Jurgen Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action, Volume 1,
Reason and the Rationalization of Society, trans. Thomas McCarthy
(Boston: Beacon Press, 1984), 42. This work originally appeared in the
German as Jurgen Habermas, Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns, volume
I, Handlungsrationalitat und gesellschaftliche Rationalisierung
(Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp, 1981).
(67) Children can never consent in advance to being born, much less
request or refuse to be enhanced at conception, although in his
Rechtslehre, AK VI 281, Kant invokes the nonconsent of children to their
existence in order to ground parental duties to their children.
(68) For some reflections on the moral limits to genetic
engineering, see Engelhardt, The Foundations of Bioethics, 2nd ed. (New
York: Oxford University Press, 1996), 207, 416-8, and The Foundations of
Christian Bioethics, 272-3.
(69) Habermas, The Future of Human Nature, 114.
(70) Ibid, 115.
(71) Ibid, 114.
(72) It is worth noting that Habermas denies a need to refer to God
as a transcendent point of reference. Habermas and Ratzinger, The
Dialectics of Secularization, 37.
(73) Habermas, Religion and Rationality, 91.
(74) Jurgen Habermas, "Zu Max Horkheimers Satz: Einen
unbedingten Sinn zu retten ohne Gott ist eitel," in Texte und
Kontexte. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt/Main, 110-26. It appears in English
translation in Habermas, Religion and Rationality.
(75) Habermas, Religion and Rationality, 108.
(76) Habermas, The Future of Human Nature, 108.
(77) Ibid, 109.
(78) Habermas and Ratzinger, The Dialectics of Secularization, 29.
(79) Ibid, 43, 51.
(80) Habermas, The Future of Human Nature, 114.
(81) Francis Fukuyama notes the regional character of
religiously-based hesitations regarding the use of human genetic
engineering. In particular, he observes that there are "... a
number of countries in Asia, which for historical and cultural reasons
have not been nearly as concerned with the ethical dimension of
biotechnology. Much of Asia, for example, lacks religion per se as it is
understood in the West--that is, as a system of revealed belief that
originates from a transcendental deity." Francis Fukuyama, Our
Posthuman Future (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2002), 192. Many
cultures are not framed by Christianity; they do not sustain it as a
secularized Kulturgut.
(82) Habermas, The Future of Human Nature, 104.
(83) Habermas, The Future of Human Nature, 104.
(84) Habermas, The Future of Human Nature, 105-8.
(85) Habermas, The Future of Human Nature, 113.
(86) Habermas and Ratzinger, The Dialectics of Secularization, 39;
41.
(87) Habermas, The Future of Human Nature, 111.
(88) See, for example, Michael Buckley, At the Origins of Modern
Atheism (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1987).
(89) H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr., "Critical Reflections on
Theology's Handmaid: Why the Role of Philosophy in Orthodox
Christianity is so Different," Philosophy & Theology 18, no. 1
(2007): 53-75.
(90) David Bradshaw, Aristotle East and West: Metaphysics and the
Division of Christendom (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2004),
275.
(91) Bradshaw, Aristotle East and West, 277. An ancestral version
of this (my own) paper was presented as a philosophy colloquium at the
University of Minnesota, Minneapolis, April 4, 2008. The author is in
particular grateful to Thomas J. Bole, III, for remarks and
recommendations concerning this essay.