Moser, Paul K.: The Elusive God: Reorienting Religious Epistemology.
Copan, Paul
MOSER, Paul K. The Elusive God: Reorienting Religious Epistemology.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008. xii + 292. Cloth,
$90.00--In this remarkable, noteworthy volume, Loyola University's
philosophy chair, Paul Moser, has made a comprehensive case for a
"Copernican revolution" in religions epistemology. He presents
a necessary corrective to a history of philosophical and theological
armchair argumentation and speculation, detached from human volition.
Moser carefully follows the Jewish-Christian scriptures'
epistemological approach, including a rejection of fideism, which itself
repudiates all evidential considerations. He writes: "The heart of
the book's account is that we should expect evidence of divine
reality to be purposefully available to humans, that is, available in a
manner, and only in a manner, suitable to divine purposes in
serf-revelation" (p. x).
God, Moser contends, may purposefully hide himself (perhaps because
of prideful human demands insisting on displays of divine pyrotechnics).
Frequently, the evidence for God considered by philosophers is
personally detached, ignoring whether our human wills are properly
oriented to receive God's self-revelation on God's terms--not
our own. This means willing conformity to God's ends for us:
entering into a loving, filial relationship with God (who is not merely
content with our having justified true belief that he exists) and
undergoing God's life giving transformation from selfishness to
selfless love. A truly authoritative, wholly good, worship-worthy God
would desire personal, engaged relationship, not the mere accumulation
of theological facts. Indeed, one may have ample propositional evidence
for God's existence yet hate God all the more.
This book contains a lengthy introduction, five chapters, and an
appendix ("Skepticism Undone," which undermines the major
argument--the circularity objection--supporting skepticism). In chapter
1, "Doubting Skeptics," Moser repudiates "spectator
evidence" (as opposed to "authoritative evidence"),
challenging the reader to be willing to be known by God--a factor almost
wholly ignored when evidence for God is presented. Attempts to dislodge
evidence of a loving God indicate cognitive bias against God's
reality, not genuine truth-seeking (p. 75).
Chapter 2, "Knowing as Attunement," appropriates the
metaphor of a radio dial: humans must be properly attuned to God's
purposefully available evidence. Here Moser even gives his own argument
for God's existence in which an individual's willing,
unselfish reception of the divine transformative gift evidences a
worship-worthy God (p. 135). A biblical epistemological stance calls for
wholehearted seeking--not merely passive, casual observation. In setting
the "dials" our way, we will create barriers to truly knowing
God as he desires to be known.
Chapter 3, "Dying to Know," speaks of the value of
personal knowledge (something reminiscent of Michael Polanyi) as
veridical evidence for God, the second-best kind of such evidence being
firsthand acquaintance with persons transformed by God's Spirit.
Moser here contrasts the wisdoms of Athens (tied to propositionalism,
intellectualist enlightenment, postmortem soul-disembodiment as ideal)
and Jerusalem (involving personal knowledge, forgiveness/reconciliation
with God, eventual bodily resurrection).
Chapter 4, "Philosophy Revamped," calls for reorienting
philosophy around what is ultimate namely, the commands to love God and
others. This means that rather than being an ivory-tower, abstract,
relationally-irrelevant, and often idolatrous discipline, philosophy
should be kerygmatic--namely, concerned about the interests of
God's redemptive purposes and up-building of the transformed
community of God's people. Philosophy (the love of wisdom) should
pay more attention to Jesus, the wisdom of God.
Chapter 5, "Aftermath," speaks of the importance of
evidence (contra Plantinga's Reformed epistemology)--but without
coercion. In light of inevitable death and the hopelessness of
materialism, we must recognize our need for outside help; the gift of
fellowship with God, our greatest good, involves willingly entrusting
ourselves to him rather than living lives morally independent of him.
Some natural theologians will dispute the spectator-evidence versus
divinely-authoritative-purposeful-evidence demarcation: (a) significant
"spectator evidence" for God's existence, though
secondary and not ultimately authoritative, is abundant in Scripture
(for example, many miracles fitting into the "divine
pyrotechnics" category); (b) such evidence can be, and has been,
used by God in combination with--and here Moser's emphasis is
critical--a willing, seeking heart open to relationship with God.
Moser's observation, however, that natural theologians "often
leave their inquirers without an authoritative volitional
challenge" (p. 161) is spot-on.
Truly, Moser has done philosophy--and natural theology in
particular--an immense service by pointing us in a new, exciting
direction. Indeed, his book is a must-read for every philosopher and
theologian!--Paul Copan, Palm Beach Atlantic University.