Rawls, John. Lectures on the History of Political Philosophy.
Simpson, Peter
RAWLS, John. Lectures on the History of Political Philosophy.
Edited by Samuel Freeman. Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press of Harvard
University Press, 2007. xix + 476 pp. Cloth, $35.00--The title of this
book is misleading: the lectures are not on the history of political
philosophy (nothing is said, for instance, about the ancients or
medievals). Nor are they on the history of moderu political philosophy
(although modern authors are the only ones discussed). The lectures are
much narrower. The course for which they were given was called Modern
Political Philosophy, which would be an accurate enough title if the
themes of Rawls' own Theory of Justice and Political Liberalism can
count as the substance of such a course. What the lectures are about is
the origins of Theory of Justice and Political Liberalism, as Rawls
admits in several programmatic remarks (so it would have been nice if
the editor had made the title do the same). Their express object is the
thought of Hobbes, Locke, Hume, Rousseau, Mill, Marx, Sidgwick, and
Butler, but they do not give a general or overall account. If readers
want that, says Rawls, they should look elsewhere. What he gives here is
only how these authors "treat certain topics discussed in my own
writings on political philosophy" (p. xvii).
It is, of course, not new that Rawls is working out of the Social
Contract tradition which had its modern beginning in Hobbes. But that
Hobbes' view of the selfishness of the natural man is an
anticipation of Theory of Justice's primary goods or Political
Liberalism's overlapping consensus, or that Locke's rejection
of Filmer and Sidgwick's rational method of ethics are an
anticipation of Theory of Justice's reflective equilibrium, or that
Hume's judicious spectator is an anticipation of Theory of
Justice's veil of ignorance, or that Rousseau's general will
and Mill's principle of liberty are an anticipation of Political
Liberalism's public reason, or that Mill's higher pleasures
are an anticipation of Theory of Justice's priority of the right to
the good, or that Marx's public economic planning is an
anticipation of Theory of Justice's difference principle, or that
Butler's conscience is an anticipation of Theory of Justice's
sense of justice and its pyschological satisfaction--all this came as a
welcome surprise to me. It not only made Rawls' thinking and
reasoning more transparent but also displayed how exceedingly fine and
subtle a reader of others he could be.
I was not surprised, although I was disappointed, that in these
lectures, as indeed throughout his work, Rawls has no serious discussion
of, nor makes a serious attempt to grapple with, the great thinkers of
the ancient and medieval worlds. The Hobbesian problematic, which is
absolutely definitive for all modern political thinking, including that
of Rawls (for although those who came after Hobbes often rejected his
answers, they seldom rejected his way of posing the problem), was, if
not decisively refuted, then decisively put into question by
Plato's Republic (to say nothing of Augustine's City of God).
Should not Rawls have somewhere raised the question of whether doing
political philosophy according to this Hobbesian problematic was the
right way to proceed? True, he does in these lectures raise criticisms
against the authors he discusses, but the purpose, he says, is to
examine the respects in which "we, from our point of view and
concerned with our own questions or problems, do not find their answers
or solutions altogether acceptable" (p.104). A not unworthy aim,
but a limited one--so limited, in fact, that one may wonder if Rawls has
not thereby abandoned political philosophy for political apologetics.
The charge, indeed, that Rawls did thus abandon philosophy has often
been leveled against him since he openly professed his aim to be
'political and not metaphysical'.
Actually I wonder whether he even got as far as being political.
For while he here justifies the study of political philosophy because it
is part of the "general background culture of a democratic
society" and because certain "classic texts" are part of
"public lore and a fund of society's basic political
ideas" (p.3), and while he refers in this context to the
Declaration of Independence and the Gettysburg Address, he never
discusses, indeed he barely mentions, that text which really forms the
"background culture", the "public lore", and the
"basic ideas", whether political or otherwise, of our society.
I mean, of course, the Bible, which is at least the subtext of both the
Declaration and the Address and is the express text of a host of major
political documents from the Founding Fathers on. No one who, like
Rawls, professes to be concerned with the "background culture"
or with "our questions and problems" can afford to ignore the
Bible. That Rawls does so throughout his writings is a puzzling
omission--an omission that these lectures do nothing to rectify.--Peter
Simpson, City University of New York.