Selinger, Evan, ed.: Postphenomenology: A Critical Companion to Ihde.
Hanson, F. Allan
SELINGER, Evan, ed. Postphenomenology: A Critical Companion to
Ihde. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2006. xi + 308 pp.
Cloth, $86.50--This volume is a critical review of how Don Ihde has
contributed to and stimulated phenomenology, postphenomenology and the
philosophy of technoscience over the last four decades. Evan Selinger
brought forth this admirable tribute to his mentor by assembling
original essays from nineteen of Ihde's former students, colleagues
and professional peers. All leading scholars in the field, their
contributions make for required reading, not only for Ihde aficionados
but for anyone interested in the history, sociology, or philosophy of
technoscience.
Ihde dwells in the borderland between philosophy and other
disciplines in that his phenomenological approach directly pertains to
actual experience in many of its forms. Some of the essays are devoted
to insights from or pertinent to Ihde that advance understanding of
concrete things and events. Trevor Pinch writes a history of the
electronic synthesizer and discusses the tension between its having a
voice of its own and its capacity to emulate other instruments, while
Judy Locbhead explores the impact of various forms of visual notation on
the experience of hearing and understanding music. Robert P. Crease
addresses the nature of experimentation in scientific laboratories.
Peter Galison turns a Heideggerian perspective on the Columbia disaster
and other problems in the space program to examine the issue of
breakdown in complex technological systems, and Donna Haraway considers
the numerous implications of the expanded technology-human-animal
interface that is brought about by attaching cameras to turtles, whales
and penguins.
Haraway's paper also embodies a theme that crops up repeatedly
in the volume, as well as in Ihde's work, which is to shift
attention from individual things or activities to the relationships that
emerge from their combinations. This theme takes several forms, one of
which is the relation between science and technology. Selinger recounts
in the Introduction (p. 6) how, in a seminar in Colombia in 1982, Ihde
was denounced for affirming a distinction between science and technology
that masks how the interworkings of the two are often used both
ideologically and materially to undermine indigenous cultures. The
experience had complex ramifications, one being to fix in Ihde the
necessary and historically ubiquitous interconnections of science and
technology, to be studied by the philosophy of
"technoscience." This issue is taken up in essays by Paul B.
Thompson, Robert C. Scharff, and Hans Lenk.
Another aspect of the emphasis on relationships is that between
people and things. Rather than thinking of a person using a tool or
instrument, the human-tool combination is better considered as a single
agency: an actant or a cyborg. Carl Mitcham points out the link between
Ihde's phenomenology and the pragmatism of Dewey, who also held
that things commonly considered to be outside the body--tools, friends,
institutions--are better understood as belonging to it. Donn Welton
examines the difference between mechanical extensions of the body and
machines embedded in the body. A fascinating elaboration on the
human-instrument nexus is found in Finn Olesen's account of the
impact of the stethoscope on the practice of medicine and the
conceptualization of disease. Andrew Feenberg insists that the
body's linkage with things affects not only what that extended
agency does, but also its passive role of how it is treated. Albert
Borgmann elaborates Ihde's distinction between technologies that
directly extend our senses (such as a telescope or microscope) and those
hermeneutic extensions that require interpretation of texts (for
example, read-outs from the Hubble telescope).
Selinger's essay is one of several noting that Ihde has not
pursued the ethical implications of his work as far as might be desired.
This may be partly because, as Richard A. Cohen points out, Ihde has
avoided the dystopian judgments about technology of thinkers like
Heidegger and Ellul. In his concluding essay Ihde discusses several
facets of this issue, among them (perhaps as another upshot of the
criticism he received in Colombia) the "paradox of prognosis,"
which concerns how technologies generate unintended consequences and
have different impacts in different cultural settings. The volume's
most focused effort to extend the ethical dimension is Peter-Paul
Verbeek's contribution, "The Morality of Things." He
surmises that ethics may be on the verge of a Copernican revolution that
will include things among moral agents. Things are invariably involved
in human decisions and actions, he holds, and they should therefore be
implicated in the morality of those decisions and actions. The
difficulty, of course, is dealing with the complaint that things do not
act intentionally and do not receive rewards or punishments. (It was not
always such. Ihde's concluding essay refers to the medieval
practices of punishing the animal as well as the human participants in
bestiality and flogging bells that were used to call people to
insurrection.) Certainly it is high time to extend moral responsibility
to include animals and things. But instead of investigating them in
isolation it would be better to hew to the emphasis Ihde and others
place on relationship, and to concentrate on the moral status of
extended agencies composed of various combinations of human and nonhuman
elements.--F. Allan Hanson, University of Kansas.